Skip to main content

Full text of "Moralia, in fifteen volumes, with an English translation by Frank Cole Babbitt"

See other formats


PLUTARCH 


MORALIA 
VOLUME ΧΙ PART | 


Translated by 
HAROLD CHERNISS 


IEEE Eeeeeeeeelr 





PLUTARCH (Plutarchus), ca. ap 45—120, 
was born at Chaeronea in Boeotia in cen- 
tral Greece, studied philosophy at Athens, 
and, after coming to Rome as a teacher in 
philosophy, was given consular rank by the 
emperor Trajan and a procuratorship in 
Greece by Hadrian. He was married and 
the father of one daughter and four sons. 
He appears as a man of kindly character 
and independent thought, studious and 
learned. 


Plutarch wrote on many subjects. Most 
popular have always been the 46 Parallel 
Lives, biographies planned to be ethical ex- 
amples in pairs (in each pair, one Greek 
figure and one similar Roman), though the 
last four lives are single. All are invaluable 
sources of our knowledge of the lives and 
characters of Greek and Roman statesmen, 
soldiers and orators. Plutarch’s many other 
varied extant works, about 60 in number, 
are known as Moralia or Moral Essays. They 
are of high literary value, besides being of 
great use to people interested in philoso- 


phy, ethics and religion. 


The Loeb Classical Library edition of the 
Moralia is in sixteen volumes, volume XIII 
having two parts. Volume XVI is a compre- 
hensive Index. 








rid 





J 


! 


\ 
Ἂν 
' τὴν " 
eke | 


i hae 
Ca ers) 


a 





| ras ΕΝ ΜΝ 


han 


ἼΝ τ ὡ: 
ne τ τς Ὁ 
neti me 





“WORAI th 
oe χη sf 


᾿ς ' VE ἵν 
Ὄ 


“τ οὐ 
on ae Ar oh 4 τ 
ora n 4 








THE LOEB CLASSICAL LIBRARY 


FOUNDED BY JAMES LOEB 1911 


EDITED BY 


JEFFREY HENDERSON 


PLUTARCH 
MORALIA 


XIII 


LCL 427 


righ asad aaNet’ ya Ὁ 


ae | τὰ gates , 
“woen παν ΔῊ ran 


HOAATUIT 


| AIGAROM 
1+} τ ἣν 
J 
{ 
ese eG? | 
| ~- 





PLUTARCH 


MORALIA 


VOLUME XIII 
PART I 


WITH AN ENGLISH TRANSLATION BY 
HAROLD CHERNISS 


HARVARD UNIVERSITY PRESS 
CAMBRIDGE, MASSACHUSETTS 
LONDON, ENGLAND 





Copyright © 1976 by the President and Fellows 
of Harvard College 
All rights reserved 
First published 1976 


LOEB CLASSICAL LIBRARY® is a registered trademark 
of the President and Fellows of Harvard College 


ISBN 978-0-674-99470-6 


Printed on acid-free paper and bound by 
Edwards Brothers, Ann Arbor, Michigan 





CONTENTS 


PREFACE vii 
TRADITIONAL ORDER OF THE MORALIA Xxill 
PLATONIC QUESTIONS 1 


ON THE GENERATION OF THE SOUL 
IN THE TIMAEUS 131 


EPITOME OF “ON THE GENERATION OF THE 
SOUL IN THE TIMAEUS 347 


δ τλθλισαὶ wy ; 
a uf due: i orf 


mi) 
vo 


4 {? ΤῸ ea 


“Aa nOM aut 40 


* 


Lien 


\ 


a 


- 


| 


ἢ ἐς ἫΝ 


+0 ΚΟΥ ΚΑΛΗ͂Σ 5 cee eee 


hs 


Ὦ 


ΤΗΣ 


Bemba y wbsfres rari 
A rive abs he ith a, Ana vg, Mie oF 


Ὁ 


thy 


“equamit aa 
oats 90470 ὃ, 


ῃ 
ἴω my 
᾿ hae 
: ὩΣ 
ἘΣ. Ἢ 
ἱ = we 
τς ἡ, 4 
rah 
1a 
A 
“9 
ἄς 
Sue 
“a 
τ 
ν᾿ 






PREFACE 


Tue following are the manuscripts used for the edi- 
tion of the six essays in this volume and the sigla 
that refer to them : 


A =Parisinus Graecus 1671 (Bibliotheque Nationale, 
Paris)—a.p. 1296. 

B =Parisinus Graecus 1675 (Bibliotheque Nationale, 
Paris)—15th century. 

E =Parisinus Graecus 1672 (Bibliotheque Nationale, 
Paris)—written shortly after a.p. 1302. 

}’ =Parisinus Graecus 1957 (Bibliotheque Nationale, 
Paris)—written at the end of the 11th century. 

J =Ambrosianus 881 - C 195 inf. (Biblioteca Am- 
brosiana, Milan)—13th century. 

X =Marcianus Graecus 250 (Biblioteca Nazionale di 
S. Marco, Venice)—the first part (containing the 
De Stoccorum Repugnantis) written in the 11th 
century, the second part (containing the Pla- 
tonicae Quaestiones) written in the 14th century. 

d=Laurentianus 56, 2 (Biblioteca Laurenziana, 
Florence)—15th century. 

e=Laurentianus 70, 5 (Biblioteca Laurenziana, 
Florence)—14th century. 

f = Laurent. Ashburnham. 1441 (not 1444 as in Hubert- 
Drexler, Moralia vi/1, pp. xv1 and xx) (Biblioteca 
Laurenziana, Florence)—16th century. 

vii 


PREFACE 


g =Vaticanus Palatinus 170 (Bibliotheca Apostolica 
Vaticana, Rome)—15th century. 

m =Parisinus Graecus 1042 (Bibliotheque Nationale, 
Paris)—16th century. 

n = Vaticanus Graecus 1676 (Bibliotheca Apostolica 
Vaticana, Rome)—1l4th century (cf. Codices 
Vatican Graect : Codices 1485-1683 rec. C. Gian- 
nelli [1950], pp. 441-443). 

r=Leiden B.P.G. 59 (Bibliotheek der Rijksuniver- 
siteit, Leiden)—16th century (see p. 150, n. ὁ 
in the Introduction to the De An. Proc. in Ti- 
maeo). 

t =Urbino-Vaticanus Graecus 100 (Bibliotheca Apo- 
stolica Vaticana, Rome)—a.p. 1402. 

u = Urbino-Vaticanus Graecus 99 (Bibliotheca Apo- 
stolica Vaticana, Rome)—15th century. 

v =Vindobonensis Philos. Graec. 46 (Nationalbiblio- 
thek, Vienna)—15th century. 

2 =Vindobonensis Suppl. Graec. 23 (Nationalbiblio- 
thek, Vienna)—15th century. 

a =Ambrosianus 859 - C 126 inf. (Biblioteca Am- 
brosiana, Milan)—finished in αὐ. 1295 (cf. 
A. Turyn, Dated Greek Manuscripts of the Thir- 
teenth and Fourteenth Centuries in the Libraries of 
Italy {University of Illinois Press, 1972] i, pp. 81- 

87). 

β =Vaticanus Graecus 1013 (Bibliotheca Apostolica 
Vaticana, Rome)—14th century. 

y =Vaticanus Graecus 139 (Bibliotheca Apostolica 
Vaticana, Rome)—written shortly after a.p. 
1296. 

6 =Vaticanus Reginensis (Codices Graeci Reginae 
Suecorum) 80 (Bibliotheca Apostolica Vaticana, 
Rome)-—15th century. 

vill 





PREFACE 


ε =Codex Matritensis Griego 4690 (Biblioteca Nacio- 
nal, Madrid)—14th century. 

Bonon. =Codex Graecus Bononiensis Bibliothecae 
Universitatis 3635 (Biblioteca Universitaria, 
Bologna)-—14th century. 

C.C.C. 99 =Codex Oxoniensis Collegii Corporis 
Christi 99 (Corpus Christi College, Oxford)— 
15th century. | 

Escor. 72 =Codex Griego 2-I-12 de El Escorial (Real 
Biblioteca de FE] Escorial)—15th and 16th cen- 
turies (ff. 75'-87", which contain the De An. Proc. 
in Timaeo, were written in the 16th century). 

Escor. T-11-5 =Codex Griego T.11.5 de El Escorial 
(Real Biblioteca de ΕἸ Escorial)—16th century. 

Laurent. C. S. 180 =Laurentianus, Conventi Sop- 
pressi 180 (Biblioteca Laurenziana, Florence)— 
15th century. 

Tolet. 51, 5=Toletanus 51, 5 (Libreria del Cabildo 
Toledano, Toledo)—15th century. 

Voss. 16 =Codex Graecus Vossianus Misc. 16 (1) = 
Vossianus P 223 (Bibliotheek der Rijksuni- 
versiteit, Leiden)—15th century. 


In such matters as accent, breathing, crasis, elision 
and spelling I have followed without regard to the 
manuscripts the usage explained in the Introduction 
to the De Facte (L.C.L. Moraha xii, pp. 27-28). 

The readings of the Aldine edition I have taken 
from a copy that is now in the library of The Institute 
for Advanced Study (Princeton, New Jersey) and 
that has on the title-page the inscription in ink, 
—: Donati Jannoctii :—Ex Bibliotheca Jo. Huralti 
Borstallerii : Jannoctii dono ; and from the margins 
of this copy I have cited the corrections or con- 
jectures which in a note at the end of the volume 


1X 


PREFACE 


(pp. 1010 f.) * written in the same ink as the inscrip- 
tion on the title-page are ascribed to Leonicus and 
Donatus Polus. 

For the editions and other works to which there is 
frequent reference in the apparatus criticus and notes 
the following abbreviations or short titles are 
used : 


Amyot =Les cuvres morales et philosophiques de 
Plutarque, translatées de Gree en Frangois par 
Messire Jacques Amyot,.. . corrigées et aug- 
mentées en ceste presente édition en plusieurs 
passages suivant son exemplaire, Paris, Claude 
Morel, 1618. 

Andresen, Logos und Nomos =Car] Andresen, Logos 
und Nomos: Die Polemik des Kelsos wider das 
Christentum, Berlin, 1935. 

Armstrong, Later Greek . . . Philosophy =The Cam- 
bridge History of Later Greek and Early Medieval 
Philosophy, edited by A. H. Armstrong, Cam- 
bridge, 1967. 

Babut, Plutarque de la Vertu Ethique =Plutarque de la 
Vertu Ethique : Introduction, texte, traduction et 
commentaire par Daniel Babut, Paris, 1969 (Biblio- 
théque de la Faculté des Lettres de Lyon XV). 

4 It is the same note as that quoted by R. Aulotte (A myot 
et Plutarque [Genéve, 1965], p. 180) from the end (p. 877) 
of the Basiliensis in the Bibliotheque Nationale (J. 693), the 
title-page of which, he says, bears the inscription Donato 
Giannotti. 

ὃ This definitive edition has been compared with the first 
edition, Les wuvres morales et meslées de Plutarque .. ., 
Paris, Michel de Vascosin, 1572, and with Q/uvres Morales 
et Mélées de Plutarque traduites du Grec par Jacques Amyot 
avec des Notes et Observations de MM. Brotier et Vaul- 
villiers, Paris, Cussac, 1784-1787 =Tomes XIII-XXII of 
(Huvres de Plutarque ..., 25 vols., 1783-1805. 


x 





PREFACE 


Babut, Plutarque et le Stotcusme =Daniel Babut, Plu- 
tarque et le Stoicisme, Paris, 1969 (Publications 
de l'Université de Lyon). 

Basiliensis = Plutarcht Chaerone: Morala Opuscula . . ., 
Basiliae ex Officina I’robeniana per H. Frobenium 
et N. Episcopium, 1542. 

Benseler, De Hiatu=G. E. Benseler, De Hiatu in 
Scriptoribus Graecis, Pars I: De Hiatu in Oratort- 
bus Attécts et Historicts Graecis Libri Duo, Friber- 
gae, 1841. 

Bernardakis = Plutarchi Chaeronensis Moralia recogno- 
vit Gregorius N. Bernardakis, Lipsiae, 1888- 
1896 (Bibliotheca Teubneriana). 

Bidez-Cumont, Les Mages Hellénisés =Joseph Bidez 
et Franz Cumont, Les Mages Hellénisés, 2 vol- 
umes, Paris, 1938. 

Bolkestein, Adversaria =Hendrik Bolkestein, Adver- 
saria Critica et Exegetica ad Plutarcht Quaes- 
tionum Convivalium Librum Primum et Secundum, 
Amstelodami, 1946. 

Bonhoffer, Epictet und die Stoa=Adolf Bonhdffer, 
Epictet und die Stoa : Untersuchungen sur stoischen 
Philosophie, Stuttgart, 1890. 

Bonhoffer, Die Etlik . . .=Adolf Bonhdffer, Die 
Ethk des Stoikers Epictet, Stuttgart, 189+. 

Bréhier, Chrysippe =Emile Bréhier, Chrysippe et l’an- 
cien stoicisme, Paris, 1951 (nouvelle édition revue). 

Bréhier, Théorie des Incorporels =Fmile Bréhier, La 
Théorie des Incorporels dans l’ancien Stoicisme, 
Paris, 1928 (deuxiéme édition). This was origin- 
ally published in 1908 as a “ Thése pour le doc- 
torat.”’ It was reprinted in 1962. 

Burkert, Weisheit und Wissenschaft =Walter Burkert, 
Weisheit und Wissenschaft : Studien zu Pythagoras, 

xi 


PREFACE 


Philolaos und Platon, Niirnberg, 1962 (Erlanger 
Beitrige zur Sprach- und Kunstwissenschaft X). 
There is an English edition, “ translated with 
revisions,” Lore and Science in Ancient Pytha- 
goreanism (Harvard University Press, 1972) ; 
but this appeared too late to permit the use of it 
instead of the German original. 

Cherniss, Artstotle’s Criticism of Plato . . .=Harold 
Cherniss, Aristotle's Criticism of Plato and the 
Academy, Vol. I, Baltimore, 1944. 

Cherniss, Crit. Presoc. Phil. =Harold Cherniss, Aris- 
totle’s Criticism of Presocratic Philosophy, Balti- 
more, 1935. 

Cherniss, 7'he Riddle =Harold Cherniss, The Riddle 
of the Early Academy, Berkeley/Los Angeles, 1945. 

Cornford, Plato's Cosmology =Plato’s Cosmology : The 
Timaeus of Plato translated with a running com- 
mentary by Francis Macdonald Cornford, 
London/New York, 1937. 

Diels-Kranz, Frag. Vorsok.6=Die Fragmente der 
V orsokratiker, Griechisch und Deutsch von Her- 
mann Diels, 6. verbesserte Auflage hrsg. von 
Walther Kranz, 3 volumes, Berlin, 1951-1952 
(later “ editions ” are unaltered reprints of this). 

Doring, Megariker=Die Megariker, Kommentierte 

Sammlung der Testimonien . . . vorgelegt von 
Klaus Déring, Amsterdam, 1972 (Studien zur an- 
tiken Philosophie 2). 

Diibner =Plutarchi Chaeronensis Seripta Moralia. 
Graece et Latine ed. Fr. Diibner, Paris, 1841. 

Dyroff, Die Ethik der alten Stoa = Adolf Dyroff, Die 
Ethik der alten Stoa, Berlin, 1897 (Berliner 
Studien fiir classische Philologie u. Archaeologie, 
N.F. 2ter Band). 


xii 








PREFACE 


Dyroff, Programm Wiirzburg, 1896 =Adolf Dyroff, 
Ueber die Anlage der stoischen Biicherkataloge, Pro- 
gramm des K. Neuen Gymnasiums zu Wiirz- 
burg fiir das Studienjahr 1895/96, Wiirzburg, 
1896. 

Florduy, Sostalphilosophie =Eleuterio Elorduy, Dre 
Soztalphilosophie der Stoa, Grafenhainichen, 1936 
( =Philologus, Supplementband XXVIII, 3). 

Fmperius, Op. Philol.=Adolpht Emperu Opuscula 
Philologica et Historica Amicorum Studio Collecta 
edidit I°. G. Schneidewin, Géttingen, 1847. 

Festa, Stoic: Anticht = I Frammentt degh Stoict Antichi or- 
dinati, tradotti e annotati da Nicola Festa, Vol. 
I e Vol. II, Bari, 1932-1935. 

Giesen, De Plutarcht . . . Dtsputationibus =Carolus 
Giesen, De Plutarch contra Stoicos Disputationi- 
bus, Monasterii Guestfalorum, 1889 (Diss. 
Miinster). 

Goldschmidt, Le systéme stoicien = Victor Goldschmidt, 
Le systéme stoicien et l'tdée de temps, Paris, 1953 
(Seconde édition revue et augmentée, Paris, 
1969). 

Gould, The Philosophy of Chrysippus =Josiah B. 
Gould, The Philosophy of Chrysitppus, Leiden, 
1970 (Philosophia Antiqua XVII). 

Grilli, Zl problema della vita contemplativa = Alberto 
Grilli, Jl problema della vita contemplativa nel 
mondo Greco-Romano, Milan/Rome, 1953 (Uni- 
versita di Milano, Facolta di Lettere e Filosofia, 
Serie prima: Filologia e Letterature Classiche). 

Grumach, Physis und Agathon=Ernst Grumach, 
Physis und Agathon in der alten Stoa, Berlin, 1932 
(Problemata 6). 

H. C. =the present editor. 


xiii 


PREFACE 


Hahn, ‘De Plutarchi Moralium Codicibus ” = 
Victor Hahn, “‘ De Plutarchi Moralium Codici- 
bus Quaestiones Selectae,’’ Académie Polonaise : 
Rozprany Akademu Umiejetnosci, Wydzial Filo- 
logiczny, Serya ii, Tom xxvi (1906), pp. 43- 
128. 

Hartman, De Avondzon des Heidendoms =J. J. Hart- 
man, De Avondzon des Heidendoms : Het Leven 
en Werken van den Wijse van Chaeronea, 2 vol- 
umes, Leiden, 1910. 

Hartman, De Plutarcho =J. J. atta, De Plutarcho 
Scriptore et Philosopho, Lugduni-Batavorum, 
1916. 

Heath, Aristarchus of Samos =Sir Thomas Heath, 
Aristarchus of Samos, The Ancient Copernicus, Ox- 
ford, 1913. 

Heath, History =Sir Thomas Heath, A History of 
Greek Mathematics, 2 volumes, Oxford, 1921. 
Heath, Manual =Sir Thomas L. Heath, A Manual of 

Greek Mathematics, Oxford, 1931. 

Helmer, De An. Proc. =Joseph Helmer, Zu Plutarchs 
‘“ De animae procreatione in Timaeo’”’: Ein. Beitrag 
gum Verstiéndnis des Platon-Deuters Plutarch, 
Wiirzburg, 1937 (Diss. Miinchen). 

Hirzel, Untersuchungen =Rudolf Hirzel, Untersuch- 
ungen zu Cicero's philosophischen Schriften, 3 
volumes, Leipzig, 1877-1883. 

Holtorf, Plutarcht Chaeronensis studia ... =Herbertus 
Holtorf, Plutarchi Chaeronensis studia in Platone 
explicando posita, Stralesundiae, 1913 (Diss. 
Greifswald). 

Hubert-Drexler, Moralia vi/1 =Plutarcht Morala Vol. 
VI Fase. 1 recensuit et emendavit C. Hubertt, 
additamentum ad editionem correctiorem col- 

XiV 





PREFACE 


legit H. Drexler, Lipsiae, 1959 (Bibliotheca 
Teubneriana). 

Hutten =Plutarcht Chaeronensis quae supersunt omna 
. . . opera Joannis Georgi Hutten, Tubingae, 
1791-1804. 

Jagu, Zénon=Amand Jagu, Zénon de Citttum : Son 
Réle dans lVétablissement de la Morale stoicienne, 
Paris, 1946. 3 

Joly, Le theme . .. des genres de vie =Robert Joly, 
Le Théme Philosophique des Genres de Vie dans 
VAntiquité Classique, Bruxelles, 1956 (Académie 
Royale de Belgique, Mémoires de la Classe des 
Lettres, Tome XXIX, fasc. 3). 

Jones, Platonism of Plutarch =Roger Miller Jones, 
The Platontsm of Plutarch, Menasha (Wisconsin), 
1916 (Diss. Chicago). References are to this edi- 
tion, in which the pagination differs somewhat 
from that of the edition of 1915. 

Kaltwasser =Plutarchs moralische Abhandlungen aus 
dem Griechischen iibersetzt von Joh. Fried. Sal. 
Kaltwasser, Frankfurt am Main, 1783-1800 = 
Plutarchs moralisch-philosophische Werke iiber- 
setzt von J. F. 5, Kaltwasser, Vienna/Prague, 
1796 ff. 

Kilb, Ethische Grundbegriffe=Georg Kilb, Ethische 
Grundbegriffe der alten Stoa und thre Ueberiragung 
durch Cicero im dritten Buch de finitbus bonorum et 
malorum, Freiburg im Breisgau, 1939 (Diss. Frei- 
burg i.Br.). 

Kolfhaus, Plutarchti De Comm. Not. =Otto Kolfhaus, 
Plutarchi De Communibus Notitis Librum Genui- 
num esse demonstratur, Marpurgi Cattorum, 1907 
(Diss. Marburg). | 

Kramer, Arete=Hans Joachim Krimer, Arete bei 

XV 


PREFACE 


Platon und Aristoteles : Zum Wesen und sur Ge- 
schichte der platonischen Ontologie, Heidelberg, 
1959 (Abhandlungen der Heidelberger Aka- 
demie der Wissenschaften, Phil.-Hist. K1., 
1959, 6). 

Kramer, Getstmetaphystk =Hans Joachim Kramer, 
Der Ursprung der Geistmetaphysik : Untersuch- 
ungen zur Geschichte des Platonismus zwischen 
Platon und Plotin, Amsterdam, 196-4. 

Krimer, Platonismus =Hans Joachim Krimer, Plato- 
nsmus und hellenistische Philosophie, Berlin/New 
York, 1971. 

L.C.L. =The Loeb Classical Library. 

Latzarus, Idées Religieuses =Bernard Latzarus, Les 
Idées Religteuses de Plutarque, Paris, 1920. 

Madvig, Adversaria Critica =Jo. Nic. Madvigii Ad- 
versaria Critica ad Scriptores Graecos et Latinos, 3 
volumes, Hauniae, 1871-1884 (Vol. 1 : Ad Scrip- 
tores Graecos). 

Mates, Stoc Logic =Benson Mates, Stoic Logic, Ber- 
keley/Los Angeles, 1953. 

-Maurommates -- Πλουτάρχου περὶ τῆς ἐν Τιμαίῳ ψυχο- 
γονίας, ἐκδόντος καὶ εἰς τὴν ἀρχαίαν συνέχειαν ἀπο- 
καταστήσαντος ᾿Ανδρέου 4. Μαυρομμάτου Kop- 
κυραίου, Athens, 1848. 

Merlan, Platonism to Neoplatonism =Philip Merlan, 
From Platonism to Neoplatonism, second edition, 
revised, The Hague, 1960. The later “ edi- 
tions’ are merely reprints of this; the first 
edition was published in 1953. 

Moutsopoulos, La Musique ... de Platon =Kvanghélos 
Moutsopoulos, La Musique dans I’(kuvre de 
Platon, Paris, 1959. 

B. Miller (1870) =Berthold Miiller, “ Eine Blatter- 


xVl 





PREFACE 


vertauschung bei Plutarch,” Hermes iv (1870), 
pp. 390-403. 

B. Miiller (1871) =Berthold Miller, “ Zu Plutarch 
περὶ ψυχογονίας,᾽᾿ Hermes v (1871), p. 154. 

B. Miller (1873) =Berthold Miiller, Plutarch iiber die 
Seelenschépfung im Timaeus, Gymnasium zu St. 
Elisabet, Bericht tiiber das Schuljahr 1872-1873, 
Breslau, 1873. 

Nogarola =Platonicae Plutarchi Cheronet Quaestiones. 
Ludovicus Nogarola Comes Veronensis vertebat, 
Venetiis apud Vincentium Valgrisium, 1552. 

Pearson, Fragments =A. C. Pearson, The Fragments 
of Zeno and Cleanthes nith Introduction and Ex- 
planatory Notes, London, 1891. 

Pohlenz, Moralia i=Plutarchi Moralia, Vol. I re- 
censuerunt et emendaverunt W. R. Patont et 
I. Wegehauptt. Praefationem scr. M. Pohlenz, 
Lipsiae, 1925 (Bibliotheca ‘Teubneriana). 

Pohlenz, Moralia vi/2 =Plutarchi Moralha, Vol. VI, 
Fase. 2 recensuit et emendavit M. Pohlenz, 
Lipsiae, 1952 (Bibliotheca Teubneriana). 

Pohlenz-Westman, Moralia vi/2 =Plutarcht Moralza, 
Vol. VI, Fasc. 2 recensuit et emendavit M. Poh- 
lenz. Editio altera quam curavit addendisque in- 
struxit R. Westman, Lipsiae, 1959 (Bibliotheca 
Teubneriana). 

Pohlenz, Grundfragen =Max Pohlenz, Grundfragen 
der stoischen Philosophie, Géttingen, 1940 (Ab- 
handlungen der Gesellschaft der Wissenschaften 
zu Géttingen, Phil.-Hist. K]., Dritte Folge Nr. 26). 

Pohlenz, Stoa =Max Pohlenz, Die Stoa : Geschichte 
einer geistigen Bewegung, 2 volumes, Gottingen, 
1948-1949 (ii =2. Band: Erlduterungen, 4. Auf- 
lage, Zitatkorrekturen, bibliographische Nach- 


XVil 


PREFACE 


trige und ein Stellenregister von H.-Th. Jo- 
hann, 1972). | 

Pohlenz, Zenon und Chrysipp =M. Pohlenz, Zenon und 
Chrysipp, Gottingen, 1938 (Nachrichten von der 
Gesellschaft der Wissenschaften zu Géttingen, 
Phil.-Hist. Kl., Fachgruppe I, Neue Folge: 
Band II, Nr. 9) =Max Pohlenz, Klezne Schriften 
i,spp. 1438. 

Problems in Stoicism = Problems in Stovcasm edited by 
A. A. Long, London, 1971. 

R.-E. =Paulys Realencyclopddie der classischen Alter- 
tumsnissenschaft . . ., Stuttgart, 1894-1972. 
Rasmus, Prog. 1872 =Eduardus Rasmus, De Plutarcha 

Libro qui wnscribitur De Communibus Notitizs Com- 
mentatio, Programm des Friedrichs-Gymnasiums 
zu Frankfurt a.O. fiir das Schuljahr 1871-1872, 

Frankfurt a.O., 1872. 

Rasmus, Prog. 1880 =Eduardus Rasmus, Jn Plutarch 
librum que inscribitur De Stoicorum Repugnantis 
Coniecturae, Jahres-Bericht iiber das vereinigte 
alt- und neustadtische Gymnasium zu Branden- 
burg von Ostern 1879 bis Ostern 1880, Branden- 
burg a.d.H., 1880. 

Reiske =Plutarcht Chaeronensis, Quae Supersunt, Om- 
nia, Graece et Latine .. . lo. Iacobus Reiske, 

‘Lipsiae, 1774-1782 (Vols. VI-X [1777-1778] : 
Opera Morala et Philosophica). 

Rieth, Grundbegriffe =Otto Rieth, Grundbegriffe der 
stoischen Ethik : Eine traditionsgeschichthche Un- 
tersuchung, Berlin, 1933 (Problemata 9). 

Robin, Pyrrhon = Léon Robin, Pyrrhon et le Scepticisme 
Grec, Paris, 1944. 

S.V.F. =Stowcorum Veterum Fragmenta collegit loannes 
ab Arnim, 3 volumes, Lipsiae, 1903-1905. 

XVill 








PREFACE 


Sambursky, Physics of the Stoics =S. Sambursky, Phy- 
sics of the Stoics, London, 1959. 

Schafer, Ein friihmittelstoisches System =Maximilian 
Schafer, Hin friihmittelstoisches System der Ethik 
bet Cicero, Munich, 1934. 

Schmekel, Philosophie der mittleren Stoa = A. Schmekel, 
Die Philosophie der mittleren Stoa in ihrem ge- 
schichtlichen Zusammenhange dargestellt, Berlin, 
1892. 

Schroeter, Plutarchs Stellung zur Skepsis =Johannes 
Schroeter, Plutarchs Stellung zur Skepsis, Greifs- 
wald, 1911 (Diss. Kénigsberg). 

Stephanus =Plutarcht Chaeronensis quae extant opera 
cum Latina interpretatione . . . excudebat Henr. 
Stephanus, Geneva, 1572. 

Taylor, Commentary on Plato’s Timaeus =A. E. Tay- 
lor, A Commentary on Plato’s Timaeus, Oxford, 
1928. f 

Thévenaz, L’Ame du Monde=Pierre Thévenaz, 
L’ Ame du Monde, le Devenir et la Matiére chez 
Plutarque avec une traduction du traité “᾿ De la 
Genése de l’ Ame dans le Timée’’ (1176 partie), Paris, 
1938. 

Treu, Lampriascatalog =Max Treu, Der sogenannte 
Lampriascatalog der Plutarchschrifien, Walden- 
burg in Schlesien, 1873. 

Treu, Ueberleferung i, ii, and iii = Max Treu, Zur Ge- 
schichte der Ueberheferung von Plutarchs Moralia i 
(Programm des Stadtischen evangel. Gymna- 
siums zu Waldenburg in Schlesien 1877), ii 
(Programm des Stidtischen Gymnasiums zu 
Ohlau 1881), iii (Programm des K@nigl. Fried- 
richs-Gymnasiums zu Breslau 1884). 

Turnebus, Plutarchi de procreatione = Plutarchi dialogus 

xix 


PREFACE 


de procreatione tn Timaeo Platonis Adriano Tur- 
nebo interprete, Parisiis, 1552. 

Usener, Epicurea = Epicurea edidit Hermannus Use- 
ner, Lipsiae, 1887. 

Valgiglio, De Fato =Ps.-Plutarco De Fato (περὶ εἷ- 
pappevns) : Introduztone testo commento traduztone 
di Ernesto Valgiglio, Rome, 1964. 

van Straaten, Panétsus =Modestus van Straaten, 
Panétius : sa vie, ses écrits et sa doctrine avec une 
édition des fragments, Amsterdam, 1946. The 
third part of this book, the text of the fragments 
(pp. 325-393), is replaced by Panetu Rhodu Frag- 
menta collegit tertioque edidit Modestus van 
Straaten O.E.S.A., editio amplificata, Leiden, 
1962 (Philosophia Antiqua V). 

Verbeke, Kleanthes =G. Verbeke, Kleanthes van Assos, 
Brussel, 1949 (Verhandelingen van de K. Vlaamse 
Academie voor Wetenschappen, Letteren en 
Schone Kunsten van Belgié, Ki. der Letteren, 
XI [1949], No. 9). 

Volkmann, Philosophie des Plutarch =Richard Volk- 
mann, Leben, Schriften und Philosophie des Plu- 
tarch von Chaeronea, Zweiter Teil: Philosophie 
des Plutarch von Chaeronea, Berlin, 1869. 

Wegehaupt, Plutarchstudien =Hans Wegehaupt, Plu- 
tarchstudten in ttalienischen Bibliotheken, Hihere 
Staatsschule in Cuxhaven, Wissenschaftliche 
Beilage zum Bericht iiber das Schuljahr 1905/ 
1906, Cuxhaven, 1906. 

Wegehaupt, “ Corpus Planudeum’’ =Hans Wege- 
haupt, ‘ Die Entstehung des Corpus Planudeum 
von Plutarchs Moralia,” Sttzungsberichte der K. 
Preussischen Akademie der Wissenschaften, 1909, 
2. Halbband, pp. 1030-1046. 

XX 











PREFACE 


Weische, Cicero und die Neue Akademie = Alfons 
Weische, Cicero und die Neue Akademie : Unter- 
suchungen zur Entstehung und Geschichte des an- 
ttken Skeptizismus, Miinster Westf., 1961 (Orbis 
Antiquus 18). 

Weissenberger, Die Sprache Plutarchs i and ii =B. 
Weissenberger, Die Sprache Plutarchs von Chae- 
ronea und die pseudoplutarchtschen Schriften I. Teil 
(Programm des K. hum. Gymnasiums Straubing 
fiir das Schuljahr 1894/1895), II. Teil (Programm 
des K. hum. Gymnasiums Straubing fir das 
Schuljahr 1895/96), Straubing, 1895 and 1896. 

Westman, Plutarch gegen Kolotes =Rolf Westman, 
Plutarch gegen Kolotes : Seine Schrift “ Adversus 
Colotem ”’ als philosophiegeschichtliche Quelle, Hel- 
singfors, 1955 (Acta Philosophica Fennica, Fasc. 
vii, 1955). 

Witt, Albinus =R. E. Witt, Albinus and the History of 
Middle Platonism, Cambridge, 1937 (Transactions 
of the Cambridge Philological Society, Vol. vii). 

Wyttenbach =Plutarcht Chaeronensis Morala, id est 
Opera, exceptis Vitis, Reliqua . . . Daniel Wytten- 
bach, Oxonii, 1795-1830 (Wyttenbach, Animad- 
versiones =Vols. vi and vii; Index Graecitatis = 
Vol. viii). 

Xylander =Plutarcht Chaeronensis omnium, quae ex- 
stant, operum Tomus Secundus continens Moralia 
Gulielmo Xylandro interprete, Francofurti, 1599. 
At the end of this volume, separately paged, 
there are Xylander’s annotations followed by 
those of Stephanus and then variant readings 
ascribed to Turnebus, Vulcobius, Bongarsius, 
and Petavius as well as those of the Aldine and 
the Basiliensis. | 

xxi 


PREFACE 


Zeller, Phil. Griech. =Eduard Zeller, Die Philosophie 


Xxii 


der Griechen in threr geschichthchen Entnicklung, 3 
parts in 6 volumes, Leipzig, 1920-1923 (last re- 
vised editions): I/1 and 2, 6. Auflage hrsg. von 
Wilhelm Nestle ; II/1, 5. Auflage mit einem An- 
hang von Ernst Hoffmann ; II/2, 3. Auflage (4. 
Auflage =Obraldruck) ; III/1, 4. Auflage hrsg. 
von Eduard Wellmann ; III/2, 4. Auflage. 





THE TRADITIONAL ORDER or tue Booxs of 
the Moralia as they appear since the edition of 
Stephanus (1572), and their division into volumes 
in this edition. 


he 


LL. 


It]. 


De liberis educandis (Περὶ παίδων ἀγωγῆς) 

Quomodo adolescens poetas audire debeat 
(Πῶς δεῖ τὸν νέον ποιημάτων ἀκούειν) 

De recta ratione audiendi (Περὲ τοῦ ἀκούειν) 

Quomodo adulator ab amico internoscatur 
(Πῶς av τις διακρίνεις τὸν κόλακα τοῦ φίλου). 

Quomodo quis suos in virtute sentiat profectus 
(Πῶς dv τις αἴσθοιτο ἑαυτοῦ προκόπτοντος ἐπ᾽ 
ἀρετῇ) 

De capienda ex inimicis utilitate (Πῶς ἄν τις 
ὑπ᾽ ἐχθρῶν ὠφελοῖτο) 

De amicorum multitudine (Περὶ πολυφιλία) 

De fortuna (Περὶ τύχης) 

De virtute et vitio (Περὲ ἀρετῆς καὶ ἐ καλοί] 

Consolatio ad Apollonium (Παραμυθητικὸς δρῦς 
᾿Απολλώνιον). 

De tuenda sanitate praecepta (γγιεινὰ πάρ. 
αγγέλματα) . 

Coniugalia praecepta (Γαμικὰ πόρῳ ἐλματα). 

Septem sapientium convivium (Τῶν ἑπτὰ σοφῶν 
συμπόσιον) . 

De superstitione ΓΕ οὶ δεισιδαιμονίας) . 

Regum et imperatorum apophthegmata (° Amo- 
φθέγματα βασιλέων καὶ oTparny γῶν) 

NG ni Laconica (’ Αποφθέγματα Aa- 
KWVLKG) . 

Instituta Laconica (Ta qodausran ὑπαὶ ΨΩ, ίων 
ἐπιτηδεύματα). 


PAGE 
1A 


17 
378 


488 


T5a 
86B 
93a 
9%c 
1008 
10lr 


122B 
1384 


1468 
164£ 


172a 
208a 


236Fr 
XXlli 


THE TRADITIONAL ORDER 


Lacaenarum aRAE eae (Λακαινῶν. ἀπο- 


φθέγματα) 
Mulierum virtutes (To υναικῶν » ἀρεταί) 


ΙΝ, Quaestiones Romanae (Aira ‘Pwyaixa). 


vi, 


Vit. 


XXIV 


Quaestiones Graecae (Αἴτια ‘EAnuixa) . 

Parallela Graeca et Romana (Συναγωγὴ στο- 
ριῶν παραλλήλων “᾿ὔλληνικῶν καὶ ἹΡωμαϊκῶν).. 

De shee Romanorum (Περὶ τῆς Ῥωμαίων 


νὰν ἐκ τις magni ‘fortuna aut virtute, li- 
ae ii (Περὶ τῆς ᾿Αλεξάνδρου τύχης ἢ ἀρετῆς, 
λόγοι B’). 

Bellone an pace ‘clariores fuerint Athenienses 
(Πότερον ᾿Αθηναῖοι κατὰ πόλεμον ἢ y κατὰ σοφίαν 
ἐνδοξότεροι) 


. De Iside et Osiride (Περὶ Ἴσιδος καὶ Ὀσίριδος). 


De E apud Delphos (Περὶ τοῦ EI τοῦ ἐν Δελφοῖς) 

De Pythiae oraculis (Περὶ τοῦ μὴ χρᾶν ἔμμετρα 
νῦν τὴν Πυθίαν) 

De defectu oraculorum (Περὶ κῶν ἐκλελόίμότῶν 
χρηστηρίων) 

An virtus doceri possit (Ee διδακτὸν ἡ ἀῤῥγῃν. 

De virtute morali (Περὶ τῆς ἠθικῆς cnr} 

De cohibenda ira (Περὶ ἀοργησίας) 

De tranquillitate animi (Περὶ εὐθυμίας)". 

De fraterno amore (Περὶ φιλαδελφίας) 

De amore prolis (Περὶ τῆς εἰς τὰ ἔκγονα φιλο 
oropyias) 

An vitiositas ad infelicitatem sufficiat (Εἰ 
αὐτάρκης ἡ κακία πρὸς κακοδαιμονίαν). ἢ 

Animine an corporis affectiones sint peiores 
(Πότερον τὰ τῆς ψυχῆς 7 τὰ τοῦ Partie bee 
χείρονα). ς 

De garrulitate (Περὶ ἀδολεσχίας) 

De curiositate (Περὶ πολυπραγμοσύνης). 

De cupiditate divitiarum (Περὶ φιλοπλουτίας). 

De vitioso pudore (Περὶ δυσωπίας) ; 

De invidia et odio (Περὶ φθόνου καὶ jilatios) 

De se ipsum citra invidiam laudando Sein τοῦ 
ἑαντὸν ἐπαινεῖν epic ing : 

De sera numinis vindicta (Περὶ τῶν ὑπὸ τοῦ 
θείου βραδέως τιμωρουμένων) 


PAGE 


240c 
249r 
2638p 
2010 


305A 
3168 


326pD 


345c 
3551. 
3840 


9940 


4095 
439 4 
4400 
459: 
4645 
478A 


493A 
498 
5008 
5028 
515s 
523c 
528c 
5368 
5394 


5484 





VI. 


ΙΧ. 


THE TRADITIONAL ORDER 


De fato (Περὶ εἱμαρμένης) . 

De genio Socratis(Ilepi τοῦ pw eet: US δαιμονίου) 

De exilio (Περὶ φυγῆς). 

Consolatio ad uxorem (Παραμυθητικὸς πρὸ τὴν 
γυναῖκα). 

Quaestionum convivalium libri vi ἔδυ πεν. 
κῶν προβλημάτων βιβλία s’) ; 

I, 612c; II, 6298; III, 6445; IV, 659E : V, 
672} ; VI, 6864 

Quaestionum convivalium libri iii (Συμποσια- 
κῶν προβλημάτων βιβλία γ᾽) ᾿ 

VII, 697c ; ait’ 716pD; Tx, 736¢ 

Amatorius Γ Epurixés) 


. Amatoriae narrationes (’ Eparixal Senyfoets) 


Maxime cum principibus philosopho esse dis- 
serendum (Περὶ τοῦ ὅτι μάλιστα τοῖς ΠΡ 
δεῖ τὸν φιλόσοφον διαλέγεσθαι) 

Ad principem ineruditum (Πρὸς ἡγεμόνα ἀπαί- 
δευτον) . 

An seni respublica gerenda sit (Ri apeoBurépw 
πολιτευτέον) 

Praecepta gerendae reipublicae (Tloeruxe. 
παραγγέλματα 

De unius in republica dominatione, populari 
statu, et paucorum imperio (Περὲ μοναρχίας 
καὶ δημοκρατίας καὶ ὀλιγαρχίας 

De vitando aere alieno (Περὶ τοῦ μὴ Sit» Sadel- 
ζεσθαι). 

oo ho τὸν oratorum (Tlépt γῶν. ϑέκα inré- 
ρων 

Comparationis Aristophanis et Menandri com- 
mage (Συγκρίσεως ἜΝ καὶ Μεν- 


υ ἐπιτομή) 
XI. De ng: ae malignitate (Πφὶ τῆς Ἡροδότου 


κακοηθείας) 


*De placitis philosophorum, libri v ( Περὶ τῶν 


ἀρεσκόντων τοῖς φιλοσόφοις, βιβλία €’) . 
Quaestiones naturales (Αἰτίαι φυσικαί) 


XII. De facie quae in orbe lunae apparet (Περὶ τοῦ 


ἐμφαινομένου προσώπου τῷ κύκλῳ τῆς σελή- 


νης) 


PAGE 
5688 


575A 
J99A 


6084 
612c 


697c 
1488 
T71E 
1104. 
7796 
783A 
7984 


826A 
597} 
8328 


8534 
854E 
8140 
9116 


9204 


* This work, by Aétius, not Plutarch, is omitted in the current edition. 


XXV 


XITI, 


XIII, 


XIV. 


THE TRADITIONAL ORDER 


De primo frigido (Περὶ τοῦ πρώτως ψυχροῦ) 

Aquane an ignis sit utilior (Περὶ τοῦ πότερον 
ὕδωρ ἢ πῦρ χρησιμώτερον). 

Terrestriane an aquatilia animalia sint callidi- 
ora (Πότερα τῶν ζῴων ἐς δα τὰ χερσαῖα 
ἢ τὰ ἔνυδρα) 

Bruta animalia ratione uti, sive Gryllus (Tlept 
τοῦ τὰ ἄλογα λόγῳ χρῆσθαι) 

De esu carnium orationes ii (Περὶ εἰσ κότος 
λόγοι β΄) 

Part I. Platonicae quaestiones Cane ae bn- 
τήματα). 

De animae procreatione i in Timaeo (Teg τῆς ἐν 
Τιμαίῳ ψυχογονίας) 

Compendium libri de animae procreatione in 
Timaeo (Emrou7) τοῦ περὶ τῆς ἐν τῷ Τιμαίῳ 
ψυχογονίας) 

Part II. De Stoicorum repugnantiis (Περὶ 
Στωικῶν ἐναντιωμάτων) 

Compendium argumenti Stoicos absur diora 
poetis dicere. (Σύνοψις τοῦ ὅτι παραδοξότερα οἱ 
Στωικοὶ τῶν ποιητῶν λέγουσι) 

De communibus notitiis adversus Stoicos (Ilepi 
TOV κοινῶν ἐννοιῶν πρὸς τοὺς Σ;τωικούς) 

Non posse suaviter vivi secundum Epicurum 
(Ὅτι οὐδὲ ζῆν ἔστιν ἡδέως κατ᾽ *"Emixoupov) 
Adversus Colotem (Πρὸς Κωλώτην ὑπὲρ τῶν 

ἄλλων φιλοσόφων) 

An recte dictum sit latenter esse vivendum (Ei 
καλῶς εἴρηται τὸ λάθε βιώσας) 


᾿.}}6 musica (Περὶ μουσικῆς). 


XV. 
XVI. 


XxXvVi 


Fragments 
General Index 


PAGE 
945E 


955D 


9594 
985D 
9934 
ἘΜ 
10124 


1030bD 
10334 


0576 
10588 
1086c 
1107p 


1128a 
1131a 





PLATONIC QUESTIONS 
(PLATONICAE QUAESTIONES) 


INTRODUCTION 


Or Plutarch’s works which, to judge by the titles 
listed in the Catalogue of Lamprias, were devoted 
particularly to the interpretation of Plato 5 only two 
are extant, the Περὶ τῆς ἐν Τιμαίῳ ψυχογονίας (65) 
and the ΠΠ᾿λατωνικὰ ζητήματα (136). 

The term ζητήματα had come to be used in a quasi- 
technical sense for problems or questions raised con- 
cerning the meaning first of expressions or verses in 
the text of Homer and then of specific passages in 
other texts or of particular statements or opinions 
or incidents, problems which with the solutions sug- 
gested might be made available to interested readers 
in the form that today would be called “ collected 
notes ’’ but sometimes in that of a “symposium,” ? 


* Nos. 65-68, 70, 136, and 221; cf. also on Academic 
doctrine Nos. 64, 71 (=131 ὃ), 134, and especially No. 63. 

® For the history of the term and genre, ζήτημα, cf. 
A. Gudeman, &.-H#. xiii/2 (1927), cols. 2511, 46-2529, 34 
(cols, 2525, 18-2527, 18 on Plutarch); H. Dorrie, Por- 
phyrios’ “ Symmikta Zetemata ’’ (Miinchen, 1959), pp. 1-6 ; 
K.-H. Tomberg, Die Kaine Historia des Ptolemaios Chennos 
(Diss. Bonn, 1967), pp. 54-62; R. Pfeiffer, History of 
Classical Scholarship (Oxford, 1968), pp. 69-71 and p. 263. 
Dorrie (op. cit., p. 2) says that in the technical vocabulary 
of philosophers the word was almost entirely avoided. 
Nevertheless, Plutarch cites works by Chrysippus entitled 
ἠθικὰ ζητήματα and φυσικὰ ζητήματα (De Stoic. Repug. 1046 
ἢ and F and 1053 r-rF, De Comm. Not. 1078 © and 1084 pb); 


2 





PLATONIC QUESTIONS 


a literary frame not inappropriate, since in intel- 
lectual circles questions like these were proposed for 
discussion by the company after dinner.* Plutarch 
himself in his Symposzacs ὃ uses the term ζητήματα of 
the questions or problems there propounded and 
discussed,° of which several without their literary 
embellishment could appropriately have been in- 
cluded in the Platonic Questions,¢ just as all the latter 
could have been used as material for the Symposzacs. 

The Platonic Questions, as we have them, are ten 
separate ζητήματα, each concerned with the mean- 
ing of a passage or apparently related passages in 
the text of Plato but unconnected with one another 





---- 


a work entitled σύμμικτα ζητήματα is ascribed to Aristotle 
(V. Rose, Aristotelis Fragmenta [1886], p. 17, # 168; cf. 
P. Moraux, Les Listes Anciennes des Ouvrages d’ Aristote 
[Louvain, 1951], p. 117, n. 17 [on pp. 118-119] and pp. 280- 
281); and Porphyry (Vita Plotini, chap. 15, 18-21) says 
that Eubulus wrote and sent from Athens συγγράμματα ὑπέρ 
τινων Πλατωνικῶν ζητημάτων. 

¢ Cf. Plutarch, Quaest. Conviv. 614 Α-Ἑ and 686 υ-Ὁ: 
Aulus Gellius, vit, xiii, 1-12 and xvi, ii, 1-16 (especially 
6-14). 

δ For the literary form and “ historicity ᾿" of Plutarch’s 
Symposiacs ef. J. Martin, Symposion (Paderborn, 1931), pp. 
167-184; H. Bolkestein, Adversaria, pp. 1-46; K. Ziegler, 
R.-F. xxi, 1 (1951), cols. 886, 40-887, 55. 

¢ Cf. Quaest. Conviv. 645 c, 660 pv, 736 c, 737 ν. 

4 Notably Quaest. Conviv. vii, 1 and 2; viii,2; and ix, 5. 

¢ That they are just ten may be only an accident; but 
ten is also the number of questions that Plutarch expressly 
allocated to each book of the Symposiacs (ef. 612 5, 629 Ἐπ, 
660 pn) save one, the ninth, which he begins with a special 
apology for exceeding ‘‘ the customary ten ”’ (736 c). 

7 Question VIII (1006 s—1007 £), for example, begins 
with Timaeus 42 pv 4-5, considers the possible relation to 
this of 40 8 8- 2, and then returns to interpret 38 c 5-6 in 


3 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


by any transition and without any general introduc- 
tion or conclusion to give the collection unity or to 
suggest a reason for the sequence in which the ques- 
tions are arranged. Had the sequence been deter- 
mined by the subject-matter, II and IV would not 
have been separated from each other by III and VI 
would not have been placed between V and VII; 
and, if by the source of the passages treated, III 
and IX, which deal with the Republic, would have 
come together, as would II, IV, V, VH, and VIII, 
all five of which deal with the Timaeus. The ten 
ζητήματα may not all have been written at one time 
and for a single work. It is at least as likely that at 
some time Plutarch put together ten separate notes 
on Platonic passages that he had written at different 
times and had found no suitable occasion to incor- 
porate into his other compositions.” If this is so, 
any indication of the relative chronology of one of 





relation to expressions in Republic 506 E—509 vb and 
Timaeus 37 n—39 5, By the remark at the end of VIII, 3 
and the beginning of VIII, 4 Plutarch practically admits 
that VIII is in fact two ζητήματα rather than one. 

« Cf. what is said by Elias (dn Aristotelis Categorias, 
p. 114, 13-14) of the σύμμικτα ζητήματα ascribed to Aristotle 
and by Athenaeus (v, 186 e= Usener, Epicurea, p. 115, 9-11) 
of the Symposium of Epicurus. 

» Cf. what he says of his De Tranquillitate Animi at the 
beginning of that essay (464 F): . . . ἀνελεξάμην περὶ 
εὐθυμίας ἐκ τῶν ὑπομνημάτων ὧν ἐμαυτῷ πεποιημένος ἐτύγχανον. 
Paccius had asked him also for something on the passages 
of the Timaeus that require exegesis (464 ©), and Plutarch 
probably had in those “‘ note-books ”’ of which he speaks 
such things as our ζητήματα or the material for them. One 
can well imagine that De Defectu Orae. 421 e—431 a (chaps. 
22-37) is the elaboration of such a ζήτημα concerning Timaeus 
55 c T—p 6 (cf. Κι. Ziegler, R.-E xxi/1 [1951], col. 834, 47-53). 


4 





PLATONIC QUESTIONS 


the ten would not necessarily be pertinent to that 
of the others. 

That Plutarch had not himself been the first to 
pose questions about these particular Platonic 
passages is clear from the fact that he commonly dis- 
cusses or refers to answers other than those he 
finally gives as his own. That he had himself dis- 
cussed at least one of them earlier is made certain by 
the remark that his answer is τὸ πολλάκις ὑφ᾽ ἡμῶν 
λεγόμενον (1003 a). This is the answer to IV, which 
is a complement of that of IT ® and together with it 
gives in brief the interpretation that Plutarch was 
later to set out in detail in the De Animae Procreatione 
in Timaeo but himself says here had frequently been 
stated earlier than IV.¢ There is no other indication 
even of the relative chronology of any of these 
ζητήματα unless the mistake in V, “ each of which 
consists of thirty of the primary scalene triangles ”’ 
(1003 p) be thought to prove V earlier than De 
Defectu Orac., where in 428 a this is corrected ; but 
that would be a precarious inference, for the mistake 
in 1003 ἢ is part of the interpretation of others to 
which Plutarch then gives his own as an alternative. 

The text of this work, No. 136 in the Catalogue of 


¢ In IV he gives only his own answer. The authors of the 
answers that he rejects are not identified more clearly than 
by some such expression as δόξει δ᾽ αὐτόθεν (1001 D), ὡς 
ὑπονοοῦσιν ἔνιοι (1003 c), Or οὗ . . . ἀποδιδόντες ἀγνοοῦσιν om... 
(1008 5-ο). 

> See also the end of VIII (1007 c-p); ef. Quaest. Conviv. 
718 « and 719 a with H. Dorrie, Philomathes ...in Memory 
of Philip Merlan (The Hague, 1971), pp. 40-42. 

¢ So he begins De An. Proc. in Timaeo itself by saying 
that it is to bring together in a single work τὰ πολλάκις εἰρημένα 
Kal γεγραμμένα σποράδην ἐν ἑτέροις ἕτερα. .. . ᾿ 


5 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


Lamprias and No. 38 in the Planudean order, is here 
printed on the basis of X J ga AB y E Ben Voss. 16 
Bonon. C 3635 and Eseorial T-11-5, all of which I have 
collated from photostats. Of these only XJ gE Be 
and n contain the whole of the work ; and in E itself, 
although the whole is written by a single hand, folio 
606" has above the first column, which begins with 
the words τοῦ νοητοῦ μόνον ἐστὶν ὁ νοῦς (1002 5), 
the superscription 4 0 πλατωνικὰ ζητήματα ὧν οὐχ 
εὑρέθη ἡ ἀρχή, through which in the same ink a line 
has been drawn.? This same superscription occurs in 
a A B Bonon. C 3635 Voss. 16 and Escorial T-11-5, in 
all of which τοῦ νοητοῦ x.7.X. (1002 D) are the first 
words of the work preserved,® and also in y, where 
the first words, however, are τί δήποτε τὴν ψυχὴν 
(1002 £), the beginning of Question IV.¢ 


* This was accurately described by Treu ( UVeberlieferung 
i, p. 1x). Cf. Pohlenz, Jforaliad, p. x, n. 3 (p. x1); Wege- 
haupt, Philologus, \xiv (1905), p. 396; Sandbach, Class. 
Quart., xxxv (1941), p. 110; Manton, Class. Quart., xliii 
(1949), p. 98. 

» This is true also of §6=Vat.Reg.80 (cf. H. Stevenson, 
Bibliothecae Apostolicae Vuticanae ... Codices Reginae 
Suecorum et Pui PP. 11 Graeci [Romae, 1888], p. 63 and 
Hahn, “ De Plutarchi Moralinm Codicibus,” p. 57) and of 
Marcianus 259, in which latter, however, the text ends with 
ἀλλὰ ἕτερον in 1008 a, where the first hand of n leaves off 
(cf. Treu, Lampriascatalog, p. 23 and Hubert-Drexler, 
Moralia vi/1, p. xtv). In Voss. 16 by an error in binding 
the text of the work has been divided ; it appears on folios 
Qt-10V and 26-28%. 

¢ This is also the case with Laur. 80, 5 and Laur. 80, 22 
(cf. Wegehaupt, Plutarchstudien, pp. 27-28 and ‘‘ Corpus 
Planudeum,”’ p. 1034, n. 1), with Marcianus 248 (cf. Treu, 
Lampriascatalog, p. 23 [where what is said of the beginning 
in Parisinus 1671 =A, however, is a mistake]), with Tolet. 
51, 5 (cf. Fletcher, Class. Quart., xxi [1927], pp. 166-167 


6 





PLATONIC QUESTIONS 


If y was copied from A, as has been supposed,? the 
scribe of y must purposely have omitted the end of 
Question III (1002 p-£) which a and A preserve, to 
begin with Question IV {τί δήποτε) and must also 
have disregarded either purposely or inadvertently 
the lacuna indicated in a and A between σωμάτων 
and ὁ σίδηρος in 1005 c. Otherwise y differs from a 
and A (uncorrected and corrected) in only six places, 
none of which is decisive.’ Only once does y agree 
with a against A (1005 ὁ [μέν τι : μέντοι -A, Esc.}). 
Four times it agrees with A against a (1003 a [7: 
ἡ -a.|, 1005 a [οὐρανὸν : ? -αἱ ; ἦκον -α, π ; εἶκον -A, 
y and all other ss.], 1007 a [ἔκγονος : ἔγγονος -Α, 
γ]» 1011 a [τὸν : τοῦ -a]) and twice with A? against 
A! and a (1003 Ε [πασῶν : παθῶν -a, ΑἸ], 1005 c 
[τρίψει : τῇ τρίψει -A?, y]). It appears, then, that 
the scribe of y copied this work from A after A had 
been corrected. 

Since f contains the end of Question III (1002 p-r), 
which is not in y, the source of 8 for this work cannot 
have been y. Nor can it have been X, J, g, B, ε, n, or 
E.¢ All these contain the beginning of the work, 
and p. 170, n. 6), and with Parisinus 2076 (ff. 132¥-145Y), 
which last was generously verified for me by M. Joseph 
Paramelle of the “Centre National de la Recherche 
Scientifique.” 

* Cf. B. Einarson and P. De Lacy, Class. Phil., xlvi(1951), 
p- 103, col. 1 and V algiglio, De Fato, p. xu. 

> 1003 B (σπέρματος : σώματος -y), 1006 D (λαμβάνοντας: 
᾿ λαμβάνοντος “Yr, Ksc.? ; “λαμβάνοντα τὰ ΓᾺΡ Bie ἮΝ ἘΠ ἢ), 
1008 c (περὶ ὦτα: eon τὰ ὦτα -y)s 1008 ν (λογιστικὸν : 
λογικὸν -a, A, B, E, B, «), 1010 c (ἅλας : ἄλλας -y, J). In 
the sixth (1006 A) γ has the negative ov which is erased in a 
and cancelled in A; but this cancellation, a dot under the 
ov, might easily have been overlooked. 

¢ B and g are presumably younger than f anyway, being 


7 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


which £ does not have and says has not been found ; 
but besides that in one passage or another after the 
point at which the text in 8 begins all of them lack 
words that were present in 8 even before correction,” 
as doa, A, and y also.® In more than a dozen places 
where f originally agreed with a, A, E it has been 
changed so that it agrees instead with the reading 
of Bonon., which is frequently shared with X and n 
and occasionally with J ore. In half a dozen of these 
places words not present in a, A, E, and y have been 
added by f? either in the margin or superscript 
(1005 c-p, 1007 p [bis], 1010 c, 1010 p, and 1011 8). 
In 1010 c B* has added in the margin ten words that 
occur in X, ε, ἢ, Bonon., Voss., and Escor., nine of 
which are omitted by J, g, a, A, y, E, and B. In 
1005 c-p, where J, g, and y have σωμάτων. 6 σίδηρος 
and where a lacuna of varying length between 
σωμάτων and ὁ σίδηρος is indicated by a, A, E, B, 
and £1, the five words ἐλυσπᾶν οὕτως ὑπὸ τοῦ 1]|λά- 
twvos have been added in the margin by B?. These 
five words with the last four deleted are in Bonon. ; 
otherwise they are preserved—but with εἰλυσπᾶν in- 
stead of iAvomwaév—only in X, ε, and n. Moreover, B 


of the 15th century, whereas β is of the 14th; n, which has 

generally been dated to the 15th century, is of the 14th 

according to (Ὁ. Giannelli (Codices Vaticani Graeci [1980], 
pp. 442-443). 

2 This eliminates bine possibility that 8 might have been 
copied from E before the lost beginning had been discovered 
and added to that ms. 

> ¢.g. 1005 a (ἅμα -omitted by n), 1006 a (οὐ -omitted by 
X, ες ἢ [erased in a and cancelled in Α7), 1006 c (ἰλλομένην.... 
ἀνειλουμένην -omitted by J, g), 1009 B (Acyou... vac.... 
kat ~a, A, y, B), 1011 a (’OSuocda... vac.... od -X, a, A, 
y, Εἰ, B, e). 


8 





PLATONIC QUESTIONS 


has uncorrected readings that differ from those of a, 
A, and E and agree with those of Bonon., shared 
sometimes by X, J, n, or € as well (1006 p, 1007 c, 
1009 a, 1009 B, 1010 B, 1010 Ρ, and 1011 a [ῤ16]) ; 
and in the last of these places 8! agrees exactly with 
Bonon. alone (λυγῶντα πρὸς τὴν τῶν προβάτων 
συν... .). It is probable therefore that B was not 
just corrected by reference to Bonon. but was copied 
from the archetype of the latter. 

Bonon. C 3635 not only has the end of QuEsTIoN 
III, which is not in y, and words that are not in fp? 
but also preserves words that are missing from X, 
from J, and from a, A, y, E,e, and n.¢ Though very 
often in agreement with a and A against J and some- 
times against X or both X and J, it agrees at times 
with X or J or both of them against a and A and 
occasionally disagrees with all four—X, J, a and A.® 


3 There are more than 35 places where Bonon. with a, A, 
and X preserves words lacking in J, among which see 1003 B 
(τῶν δὲ κυκλικῶν . . . τῶν εὐθυγράμμων), 1004 a (ὅτι τοίνυν. .. 
τὸ εὐθύγραμμον), 1006 ς (ἰλλομένην . . . ἀνειλουμένην). For 
words in Bonon. lacking in others see 6.5. 1003 8 (ὑπὸ τῆς 
ψυχῆς omitted by X), 1005 κ (τὸ δ᾽ ἤλεκτρον... τὸν σίδηρον 
omitted by ε), 1005 c-p (ἐλυσπᾶν . .. Πλάτωνος omitted by J, g, 
y, a, A, Εἰ, B, β"), 1007 p (μὲν omitted by all except Bonon., 
Voss., Escor., 8? ; and ἐστι omitted by a, A, B', y, E, B, ες n), 
1009 B (μερῶν μηθὲν ἅμα omitted by a, A, y, B), 1010 c 
(κράτιστον ... eivar omitted by J, g, a, A, y, E, B), 1011 a 
(λυγῶντα . . . συν omitted by X, a, A, y, E, B, €), 1011 B 
(νὴ Δία omitted by J, g, a, A, β', y, Εἰ, B 

δ Examples of this last case are 1011 a in the preceding 
note, 1010 B (διάλεκτος : διάλογος -Bonon.), 1010 ἢ (μὴ omitted 
by X, J, a, A); of agreement with X against a and A 
1005 c-p, 1009 Β, 1010 c, and 1011 B in the preceding note 
and 1006 c (τεταμένον) and 1009 a (76); of agreement with 
J against a and A 1002 p (ἄλλα ἄλλοις), 1004 5 (μὲν omitted 
by X, a, A), 1009 Ε (καθ᾽ αὑτὰ) ; of agreement with X and J 


9 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


It must have been copied from a ms. which, though 
mutilated at the beginning of the work in the same 
way as a, had a text in some cases nearer to that of 
X and in a few nearer to that of J than to that of a. 

The text of Voss. 16, though for the most part 
identical with that of Bonon., differs from it in seven- 
teen places.* In six of these differences, moreover, 
Voss. agrees with J} and in three others with n?; 
and this suggests that Voss. was copied not from 
Bonon. itself but possibly from the latter’s archetype 
or a Ms. very much like it. 

The same is true of Escor. T-11-5, which agrees 
with Voss. against Bonon. eight times and with 
Bonon. against Voss. seven times but disagrees with 
both Bonon. and Voss. in 31 cases,¢ in two of which 


against a and A 1006 pb (λαμβάνοντας), 1007 p (ἐστι omitted 
by a, A), 1008 p (λογιστικὸν), 1011 a (τὰς omitted by a, A). 

@ This is assuming that in 1005 c-p (where Hubert’s 
apparatus is doubly in error) the line through οὕτως ὑπὸ 
τοῦ Πλάτωνος was drawn by the first hand of Bonon. Other- 
wise the differences would be eighteen. 

> 1004 a (εὐθύγραμμοι : εὐθύγραμμον -J, g, Voss.); 1004 ἃ 
(συναρμοττομένοις : συναρμοττόμενος -J, g, Voss.4); 1005 a 
(ἀφιεμένῳ : ἐφιεμένῳ - 1, g, Voss., Escor.); 1005 ὁ (τῷ : τὸ τ΄, 
g, Voss.); 1005 Ἐ-Ρ (πληθύοντες : πληθύνοντες -J, 5. Voss., 
Escor.); 1011 B (θεωρικὰ : θεωρητικὰ -J, g, Voss., Escor.) ; 
1010 ς (Evnvos: εὔωνος -n, Voss.) ; 1011 a (παρὰ τοῖς : map’ 
οἷς -n, Voss.) 3; 1011 A (τῶν προβάτων ovv...: συν omitted 
by nand Voss.). The last is one of the two passages adduced 
by Pohlenz and Hubert (Hubert-Drexler, Moralia vi, 1, 
p. xiv); in the other, 1003 a, though Voss. disagrees with 
Bonon. and others (συνυπῆρχον), its reading, συνυπάρχον, is 
not that of J! as it is there said to be. 

¢ Perhaps a dozen of these are errors of the scribe of 
Escor. himself, one of which is interesting as a warning, 
however, for it can be only by a coincidence that in 1004 a 
Escor. omits seven words that are omitted by J and g but 
are preserved by all other mss. 


10 








PLATONIC QUESTIONS 


it agrees with others in the correct reading.* In 
1011 a Escor. like Voss. and ἢ omits the prefix συν 
preserved by Bonon. and β alone but alone has λέ- 
γοντα instead of the λυγῶντα of these four mss., and 
in 1003 a it alone has συνυπάρχουσιν instead of the 
συνυπάρχον of Voss. and the correct συνυπῆρχον of 
Bonon. Moreover, it alone has καὶ ἰλυσπᾶν in 1005 c, 
παραλιπόντα μηθὲν καὶ in 1009 Β where Bonon. and 
Voss. have μερῶν μηθὲν ἅ ἅμα καὶ, and in 1010 » ὁρῶ. 
vac. 80... ἀλλ᾽ ὥσπερ ὁμοῦ instead of their S50 
μέλλων viv ee, τι. 

In that part οὗ E that fills folios 606'-610' (τοῦ 
νοητοῦ μόνον {1002 p]—to the end) and was copied 
before the beginning of the work had been found 
FE, never agrees with a against A. It agrees with 
A, a” and others against αἱ thrice,® with A against a 
eight times,° and with A? against a and A! twice 4; 
but once it agrees with a! and A! against a and A as 
corrected,’ and eight times it disagrees with both 
a and A. One of these differences is a matter of 
word-order and is changed by E? (1003 B), one is 
the omission by E and B of two words that appear in 
all other Mss. (1010 a: καθ᾽ αὑτὸ), and three concern 

4 1004 B (ἐντάσει -E, B, n, Escor.), 1008 κε (ὃν -Escor. 
with all except n, Bonon., Voss). 

> 1002 Ἑ (δεῖ : δὴ -αἷ, €), 1009 D (τὸ πρῶτον omitted by a!), 
1009 F (τὸν λέγοντα : λέγον -a!). 

¢ In five of these cases E and A are wrong, though a is 
right (1006 B [ὁ δὴ -a], 1007 a [ἔκγονος -a], 1007 F [πρότε- 
pov -a], 1008 c [τιμωρίας -a], 1009 Ε [καὶ -a]); in two E and 
A are right and a wrong (1003 a [ἢ -E, A] and 1011 a 
[τὸν -E, ΑἸ): and in one all are wrong (1005 A [ἦκον -a?; 
εἶκον Ἢ, ΑἸ). 

4 1003 ΕἙ (πασῶν -E, A?) and 1005 c (τῇ τρίψει -E, A*). 

“ In 1006 a the οὐ after πρότερον that is absent from X, ε, 
n and is erased in a and cancelled in A is present in E. 


11 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


the form of a single word ¢ ; but in two cases E with 
B has a word that is in no other ms.,° and in 1009 B 
there are in E three words, μερῶν μηθὲν ἅμα, that 
are absent from the lacuna in a, A, y, and B and 
occur only in X, β, e, n, Bonon., and Voss. The 
scribe of E might have found these three words in 
the ms. from which he later copied the beginning 
of the work and might then have entered them here 
in the lacuna that he had left ; but, if so, it is strange 
that the scribe of B, whether he copied the whole 
work from E or from the ms. whence E took the first 
part of it, omitted just these three words and pre- 
served exactly the lacuna of a, A,andy. Itis more 
probable that the scribe of E copied the three words 
in question and all this second part of the work from 
a congener of a, which was also the source of A’s 
corrections. ° 

In the first part of the work (999 c—1002 Ὁ), which 
the scribe of E added later, there are 53 cases in 
which E agrees with X against J ; and in fifteen of 
these E preserves a word or words missing from J 
(cf. 1000 a, c, and E; 1001 c and p; 1002 4), In 
only two cases does E agree with J against X; and 
in another, where it agreed with X, it was changed 
so that E* agrees with J instead.¢ In eight cases 


α 1004 B (ἐντάσει -E, B, ἢ, Escor.; ἐνστάσει -all other 
MSS8.), 1004 c (κυκλοφορητικὴν : κυκλοφορικὴν ~E, B, n), and 
1005 A (συνεπιταχύνων : ἐπιταχύνων -E, B, Escor.). 

4 1007 F (σελήνην : τὴν σελήνην -E, B) and 1009 a (μεσό- 
τητας: ὡς μεσότητας - 

¢ Cf. Valgiglio, De Fato, p. xr and his references to Treu 
and Larsen, p. xxxIx, ἢ. 36. 

4 999 ἢ (πότερον -E, B, J, g;3 πότερα -X, ες n), 1001 5 
(τῇ ὕλῃ -E, B, J, g, ε, ns τῆ ἕλη -X), 1001 ς (γένους -E}, 
ἈΠΕ, Ts See θα J, g, B). 


12 





PLATONIC QUESTIONS 


E with B in agreement has a reading different from 
that of X and J¢; and in still another E, agreeing 
with X and J, was changed by E? to disagree with 
both.? The first part of the work, then, must have 
been copied by E from a ms. the text of which was 
much nearer to that of X than to that of J. 

In the first part of the work (999 c—1002 pb) B 
disagrees with E and all other mss. seven times,° in 
agreement with J disagrees with E and all others 
once, and in agreement with E? disagrees with ΕΝ 
thrice. In the second part of the work B agrees 
once with E? and all other mss. against Εἰ in the order 
of words (1003 a-s), disagrees with E eight times,’ 
and once, though agreeing with E, has a “ correction ” 


4 1000 F (ἢ : καὶ -Εἰ, B; omitted by X, J, g,«,n.). The 
other seven cases are 999 F, 1000 8, 1001 pb (b2s), 1002 a, 
1002 5, 1002 pb. 

b i A (ἐμφαινομένων -B, E*; ἐκφαινομένων -X, J, g, E}, 
ες Nj). 

¢ Twice in the order of words (999 E-F and 1001 8), thrice 
by wrongly omitting a word (1001 Β [ἔοικεν], 1002 a [ἐν after 
ὥσπερ]. and 1002 8 [τῆς after ἔκ te), and twice in the form 
of a word (1000 a [διανομὴ : νομὴ -Β] and 1000 pb [νοητὸν : 
νοητὴν -B}). 

4 1002 B (μικρότητα : μακρότητα -J, B). 

4 1001 c (γένους -E, X, ε, ἢ ; γένος -B, E*, J, g), 1002 a 
(ἐκ δὲ : δὲ with three dots superscript -E ; δὲ omitted by B), 
and 1002 a (ἐμφαινομένων -B, ΕΞ; ἐκφαινομένων -E! and 
all other mss.). 

f 1004 B (καμπυλωτέρας : καμπυλοτέρας -B, €), 1007 κε (dp- 
μονίᾳ : ἁρμονίαν -B), 1007 F (τὸν ἐν μὲν τοῖς : τὸν μὲν τοῖς - Ὁ : 
τὸν μὲν ev τοῖς -J, g), 1008 c (ὀρέξει : ἕξει -Β), 1008 c (τῷ 
λογισμῷ καὶ σύμμαχον : καὶ σύμμαχον τῷ λογισμῷ -Β ; καὶ 
λογισμῷ σύμμαχον “n), 1008 D (ὑπάτη : ὑπάτην -B), 1008 F (ὁτὲ 
μέν τε μετὰ: ὁτὲ μὲν μετὰ -B; ὁτὲ... vac. 5... μετὰ -J ; 
ὁτὲ μετὰ -5), 1009 B (λόγου 7A μηθὲν dua...vac. 13... 
καὶ -Ε ; λόγου... vac. 34... -B). 

op 
13 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


that points to a variant resembling the readings 
of J and σα This last and the lacuna in 1009 B are 
the strongest indications that the second part of the 
work in B was copied neither from E nor from the 
source of E for this part; and, although no single 
passage decisively proves that B did not copy the 
whole work from E after E had been corrected,?® it 
is at least equally possible that B copied it from the 
MS. whence E had taken the first part of it. 

Of the extant Mss. containing the whole work the 
oldest is J (13th century),° for the part of X that 
contains it was written in the 14th century. It has 
been asserted that J is nearer than X to the Planu- 
dean text,? but the very opposite is true. In that 
part of the work which is preserved in a and A 
(1002 p ff.) J and X agree against a A FE seven times 
and three more against α ὁ; but, where J and X 
disagree, while J agrees with a A FE against X 
twenty times, with a! A! E against X α A? once, 
and with a! against X a? A E oncef X agrees with 
a A E against J 167 times and with a against J four 

op 

* 1003 B (διάφωνον -B; διαφέρειν -J 3; διαφέρον -Β : διάφω- 
νον - Εἰ and all other mss.). 

» Yor the controversy concerning the relation of B to E 
see Plutarch, Moralia (L.C.L.), xii (1957), pp. 26-27 and 31- 
32 (with B. Einarson, Class. PAil., liii [1958], p. 265, n. 3), 
ix (1961), p. 305, and xi (1965), p. 6; Pohlenz-Westman, 
Moralia vi/2 (1959), pp. 228-229. 

¢ J4=the corrections made by Demetrius Ducas in pre- 
paring J as “copy for the printer of the Aldine edition ”’ 
(ef. Treu, Ueberlieferung iii, pp. 22-26). 

¢ Hubert-Drexler, Moralia vi/1, p. x1. 

¢ In all eases I disregard differences of accent and breath- 
ing alone. 

7 Of these 22 cases two are omissions of words in X and 
two are omissions of words in J. 


14 





PLATONIC QUESTIONS 


times more. Since not only X but all other ss. 
preserve words that J omits, J cannot be the source 
of any other ms. for this work, not even of g. 

The agreement of g with J is striking even in the 
omission of words that are present in all other mss.? 
and in the preservation of words that are missing 
from X°; but g agrees with X and others against 
J at least 38 times, in two cases preserving words 
that are omitted by J alone.¢ The close agreement 
of g with J suggests, therefore, that both were copied 
from the same ms. and that this ms. itself exhibited 
most of the errors and omissions common to J and 
g. It may have been a copy or a twin of the arche- 
type of X and may have contained some of the 
variants that X appears to have preserved from that 


2 Of these differences between X and J 35 are omissions 
of a word or words in J and three are omissions of a word or 
words in X. If these omissions were the fault of the scribes 
of J and X themselves, their originals may have shown less 
of a difference in relation to a A E, as is indicated by 1006 c, 
where X agrees with a A E in preserving sixteen words 
omitted by J and yet in these sixteen words differs from α A 
E three times. 

’ J and g agree against all other mss. more than 150 
times, in 45 of which they omit words that all others have, 
e.g. 1000 Ε (καὶ δεόμενον and καὶ βεβαιοῦντος), 1003 B (τῶν 
δὲ κυκλικῶν ... τὰς τῶν εὐθυγράμμων), and 1006 ς (ἐλλομένην 

. ἀνειλουμένην). 

ὁ. 1008 B (ὑπὸ τῆς ψυχῆς) and 1011 A (λυγῶν πρὸς τὴν τῶν 
προβάτων -omitted by X. F, B, and ε as well as by a, A, y). 

4 There are also about 25 unique readings in g, some ten 
of which are omissions of a single word, probably the fault 
of the scribe of g himself. 

¢ 1000 ς (οὐ προσδέξεται. . . τὸ πλῆθος) and 1004 ν» 
(πλειόνων). ‘The statement in Hubert-Drexler, Jforalia vi/1, 
p. x1u, line 1 concerning voovpev(ov), “ exhib. g,” is er- 
roneous. 


15 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


archetype, e.g. 1005 F (kevoupevas -X1; κινουμένας -J ; 


TE 
κενουμένας -g and all other mss.), 1006 B (yap -X!; 
τερον 
τε -J, g3 γὰρ -all other ss.), 1008 E (ἀνωτάτω -X! ; 
ἀνώτερον -J, £5 ἀνωτάτω -all other mss.). 

Both ε and the part of n written by the first 
hand @ agree with X in preserving the many words 
omitted by J and g and almost never agree with J 
or g or J g alone against X,° and in the part of the 
work that is missing from the mutilated mss. (2.e. 
before τοῦ νοητοῦ in 1002 p) they agree in several 
significant readings with X, J, and g against EK and 
B.c Thereafter, although they occasionally agree 
with a, A, E, and B against X, J, and g,? they pre- 
serve with X words that are missing from these 
Mss.* and never agree with Bonon., Voss., or Escor. 
against all others ; but both of them also preserve 
words omitted by X,f and each of the two has words 

¢ That is from the beginning of the work through ἀλλὰ 
ἕτερον at the end of 1008 a=folios 1'-6% (see p. 6, n. b 
supra). 

» The exceptions are 1001 (μαθηματικόν : μαθητικόν -J, e), 
1001 pv (δὲ τοῖς : δὲ τῆς -J, g, n), 1005 D (τις -omitted by 
J, g, €), 1005 F (ὑπείκοντος : ὑπήκοντος -J, €, n), and 
1006 B (τὸν : τὸ -J, g, ε). 

¢ 1000 B (φιλοσοφίᾳ -X, J, g, εν 1; σοφίᾳ -E, B), 1000 F 
(7 τῇ : καὶ τῇ -Li, Β: 3 TH -X, Ὁ, 8. ες Π), 1001 » rs τμήματα 
... ἔτεμε -K, Bs ἄνισα τὰ τμήματα. .. ἔτεμνε -X, J, g, en), 
1002 B (Gdn: θεοῖς -X, J, 2, €, ἢ : νοητοῖς -E, B). 

4 1006 vb (λαμβάνοντας : λαμβάνοντα ε, ἢ. a, A, EF, B), 
1007 pb (ἐστι -omitted by ε, n, a, A, nee 16 EK, B), 1007 πὶ (οὐ 
φαύλων : οὐδὲ φαύλων -e, Nn, a, A, β'. γ, Εὶ 2); 

ε 1005 c-D (σωμάτων εἰλυσπᾶν οὕτως ὑπὸ τοῦ OAC ὁ -Ν, 
én; owudrwy...vac....6-a, A, K, B; σωμάτων, o -J, 


8. γ). 
f 1003 B (ὑπὸ τῆς ψυχῆς), 1007 F (καὶ -omitted by X alone). 
16 





PLATONIC QUESTIONS 


that the other omits.¢ Neither ε nor this part of n, 
then, could have been derived from any of the extant 
mss.; and both are probably independent copies of 
the archetype of X. 

This i is not the case, however, with folios 7:-θν of n 
(of yap ὡς κυρίαν [1008 a sub finem] to the end of the 
work). The text of these folios, written in a hand 
different from that of folios 17-6’, while agreeing 
with e and X in preserving words omitted by J and 
g, by E and B, and by a, A, and y,? also preserves 
words omitted by e and X ¢; and in all these passages 
n is in agreement with one or more of the group con- 
sisting of Bonon., Voss., and Escor., as it also is in 
23 of the 24 cases in which—besides five readings 
unique to it—it disagrees with ε. In eleven of these 
23 cases, moreover, n is in agreement only with one 
or more of this group (81 or f? included in some 
cases). It was certainly from a ms. related to this 
group, therefore, and possibly from the archetype 
of Bonon. that this last part of the work in n was 
taken. 


* e.g. 1001 a sub finem (τοῦ τεκνώσαντος -omitted by n 
alone), 1005 a (ἅμα -omitted by n alone), 1005 B (τὸ δ᾽ η- 
λεκτρον ... συνεφέλκεται τὸν σίδηρον -omitted by ε alone), 
1007 Ε (καὶ πρώτῳ -omitted by ε alone). 

> 1009 B (λόγου psa: μηθὲν ἅμα καὶ -e, n, Χ, β, Bonon. “ 
Voss.; λόγου ...vac....Kxai-a, A, y, B), 1010 a (καθ᾽ αὑτὸ 
aye by E , B), 1010 ὁ earaaran » + « μέρος εἶναι -omitted 

ΟΥ͂ aes A: γι K, B, 81), 1011 B (νὴ Δία -omitted by J, g, 
Ay the Ys τὸ, Dy 

5 1010 bv (ἐκπώμασι μὴ -n, Bonon., Voss., Escor., f?; 
μὴ omitted by all other mss.), 1011 a (Ὀδυσσέα λυγῶντα πρὸς 
τὴν τῶν προβάτων. .. vac. ...ov-n, Voss.; Ὀδυσσέα ... 
vac....ov-X, a, A, y, ἔν B, e). 


17 


(999 C) ΠΛΑΤΩΝΙΚΑ ZHTHMATA? 


ZHTHMA A’ 


1. Tt δήποτε τὸν Σωκράτην ὁ θεὸς μαιοῦσθαιἶ 
μὲν ἐκέλευσεν ἑτέρους, αὐτὸν δὲ γεννᾶν ἀπεκώ- 
λυσεν, ὡς ἐν Θεαιτήτῳ λέγεται; Οὐ γὰρ ᾿εἰρω- 
νευόμενός γε" καὶ παίζων TPOGEXPHGAT. av τῷ 
D τοῦ᾽ θεοῦ ὀνόματι. καὶ ἄλλως ἐν τῷ Θεαιτήτῳ 
πολλὰ μεγάλαυχα καὶ σοβαρὰ Σωκράτει περι- 
τέθεικεν, ὧν καὶ ταῦτ᾽ ἐστί: “ πολλοὶ γὰρ δή," 
ὦ θαυμάσιε, πρός με οὕτω" διετέθησαν, ὥστ᾽ 
ἀτεχνῶς δάκνειν' ἐπειδάν τινα λῆρον αὐτῶν ἀφ- 
αἱιρῶμαι: καὶ οὐκ οἴονταί με εὐνοίᾳ τοῦτο ποιεῖν, 
πόρρω ὄντες τοῦ εἰδέναι ὅτι οὐδεὶς θεὸς δύσνους 
ἀνθρώποις οὐδ᾽ ἐγὼ δυσνοίᾳ τοιοῦτον οὐδὲν δρῶ, 
ἀλλά μοι ψεῦδός τε συγχωρῆσαι καὶ ἀληθὲς ἀ- 
᾿φανίσαι οὐδαμῶς θέμις." 
Πότερον οὖν τὴν ἑαυτοῦ φύσιν ὡς κριτικω- β 


1X, J, g, E, Β, ε, ἢ ; πλατωνικὰ ζητήματα ὧν οὐχ εὑρέθη 
ἡ ἀρχή -α, A, β, Bonon. C 3635, Voss. 16, Escorial T-11-5 (all 
beginning with τοῦ νοητοῦ μόνον [1002 5} and γ (beginning 
with τί δήποτε τὴν ψυχὴν [1002 Ε]). 

5 μαιεύεσθαι -Plato (Theaetetus 150 c 7). 3 γὲ -J, g. 

4 τῷ -omitted by J and added superscript by J*; τοῦ 

“omitted by X, g, E, B, e, n. 
ἤδη ~Nogarola from Theaetetus 151 ὁ 5. 

5 πρός με οὕτω -Ν, Εἰ, B, ε. n, Plato; οὕτω πρός με -J, δ΄. 

7 «ἕτοιμοι εἶναι» -added by Stephanus from Theaetelus 
151 c 7. 


18 





PLATONIC QUESTIONS 


QUESTION I 


1. WuyveEveR did god, as is stated in the Theaetetus,¢ 
bid Socrates act as midwife to others but prevent 
him from himself begetting ? Certainly he would 
not have used the name of god in irony or jest ὃ ; 
and besides in the Theaetetus Socrates has been 
made to say many arrogant and haughty things, 
among them this °: “ For a great many men, my 
excellent friend, have got into such a state of mind 
towards me as practically to bite when I remove 
some silliness of theirs; and they do not believe 
that I am doing this out of benevolence, for they 
are a long way from knowing that no god is male- 
volent towards men and that neither do I do any 
such deed out of malevolence but that it is quite 
illicit for me to admit falsehood and suppress truth.”’ 

Is it then his own nature, as being more dis- 

α Plato, Theaetetus 150 c 7-8. } 

’ Cf. Plato, Symposium 216 Ἑ 4-5 (εἰρωνευόμενος δὲ καὶ 
παίζων πάντα τὸν βίον πρὸς τοὺς ἀνθρώπους διατελεῖ). The ten- 
dency to dismiss as “‘irony”’ statements of Socrates that 
connected with god his behaviour in carrying on his elen- 
chus is mentioned not only in Anon. in Platonis Theae- 
tetum (Pap. Berl. 9782), col. 58, 39-49 (p. 39 [Diels-Schubart]) 
but also in the Platonic Apology 37 © 5—38 a 1. 

© Theaetetus 151 c ὅ- 3. 

8. πότερα -Χ, e, N. 


19 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


? Ni , > θ ‘ A θ 
(999) τέραν 7° γονιμωτέραν οὖσαν θεὸν προσεῖπε, καθ- 
ἅπερ Μένανδρος “6 νοῦς γὰρ ἡμῶν ὁ Geos” 
1 ¢ , 1“ 3 , ὁ , ” ‘ 
καὶ ᾿ Πράκλειτος “᾿ ἦθος ἀνθρώπου" δαίμων ᾿"" ἢ 
E θεῖόν τι καὶ δαιμόνιον ὡς ἀληθῶς αἴτιον ὑφηγή- 
σατο Σωκράτει τοῦτο τῆς φιλοσοφίας τὸ γένος, 
@ N ” > , > \ , \ / 3 
ᾧ τοὺς ἄλλους ἐξετάζων ἀεὶ τύφου Kat πλάνου 
καὶ ἀλαζονείας καὶ τοῦ βαρεῖς εἶναι πρῶτον μὲν 
αὑτοῖς εἶτα καὶ τοῖς συνοῦσιν ἀπήλλαττε; καὶ 
γὰρ ὥσπερ ἐκ τύχης τότε φορὰν συνέβη γενέσθαι" 

A > ~ ς / \ f ε , 
σοφιστῶν ev τῇ “Ἑλλάδι: καὶ τούτοις ot νέοι 
πολὺ τελοῦντες" ἀργύριον οἰήματος ἐπληροῦντο καὶ 
δοξοσοφίας, καὶ λόγων ἐζήλουν" σχολὴν καὶ διατρι- 


1 ἢ -Turnebus, Nogarola : καὶ -all mss. 

2 ἀνθρώπῳ -Bernardakis (cf. Stobaeus, Anth. iv, 40, 28 -Ξ 
v, Ὁ. 925, 12 [Hense]); but cf. ἀνθρώπων in Alexander, De 
Fato, p. 170, 18-19 and De An. Inbri Mantissa, p. 185, 23 
(Bruns). 

3 πλάνης -J, ἘΠ 

* γενέσθαι συνέβη -J, g. 

δ πολυτελοῦντες -X}, J}, ε. 

8. ἐζήλουν -X, EF, e, n, Βόοττ, (ἐζήτουν -B! with A superscript 
over τὴ ; ζήλου -J, g. 


“ Being predominantly, therefore, cognition (cf. τῷ κριτικῷ 
in De An. Proc. in Timaeo 1024 B infra), the part or faculty 
which exists without difference in the soul of gods also (cf. 
Albinus, Epitome xxv, 7 [Louis] =p. 178, 32-33 [Hermann]). 
For τὸ γόνιμον as part of the irrational soul ¢f. Philo Jud., 
De Agricultura 30-31 (ii, p. 101, 5-7 [Wendland}) and Quis 
Rerum Div. Heres 232 (iii, p. 52, 13-15 [Wendland)]) ; 
Plutarch probably identified it with that fifth part which he 
calls now θρεπτικόν and again φυτικόν (De EH 390 τ and 
De Defectu Orac. 429 ©; cf. Aristotle, De Anima 415 a 
23-26 and Eth. Nic. 1102 a 32~b 2). 

” Cf. ὅτι εἰκάζει ἑαυτὸν θεῷ (Anon. in Platonis Theaete- 
tum [Pap. Berl. 9782], col. 58, 42-43) and τῷ θεῷ συνέταξεν 
éavtov (Olympiodorus, ln Platonis Alcibiadem Priorem, 
p. 53, 14-15 and pp. 173, 21-174, 9 [Creuzer]). 


20 





PLATONIC QUESTIONS I, 999 


cerning than fertile,* that he called god,? as Men- 
ander said “for our intelligence is god’’* and 
Heraclitus ‘‘ the character of a man is his guardian 
spirit’’?; or did some truly divine and spiritual 
cause ὁ guide Socrates to this kind of philosophy 
with which by continually subjecting others to ex- 
amination he made them free of humbug and error 
and pretentiousness and of being burdensome first 
to themselves and then to their companions also ἢ f 
For at that time as if by chance there happened also 
to have sprung up in Greece a crop of sophists ; and 
the young men, paying these persons a large amount 
of money, were getting themselves filled full of self- 
conceit and sham-wisdom and were zealous for dis- 


¢ Menander, frag. 749 (Koerte-Thierfelder) =frag. 762 
(Kock) ; of. frag. 64 (Koerte-Thierfelder) =frag. 70 (Kock). 

4 Heraclitus, frag. B 119 (D.-K. and Walzer) =frag. 121 
(Bywater). For the implied polemic against the conven- 
tional notion of the δαίμων as the “ destiny ᾿᾿ assigned to a 
man cf. G. Misch, 4 History of Autobiography in Antiquity 
(London, 1950), pp. 94-95 ; and see Plato, Republic 617 £ 1 
and 620 p 8, where the soul of each selects its own δαίμων, 
and Apuleius, De Deo Socratis xv, 150(‘‘... animus humanus 
etiam nunc in corpore situs daemon nuncupatur . . . daemon 
bonus id est animus virtute perfectus est ’?) = Xenocrates, frag, 
81 (Heinze). 

e This is surely a reference to the “divine sign,” τὸ 
δαιμόνιον (cf. 1000 Ὁ infra), which in Plato’s Apology 31 c 8— 
Ὁ 1 Socrates calls θεῖόν τι καὶ δαιμόνιον (cf. Proclus, In 
Platonis Alcibiadem Priorem, p. 79, 1-14 [Creuzer] =p. 35 
{ Westerink]) and the nature of which is discussed by Plu- 
tarch in De Genio Socratis 580 c—582 c and 588 c—589 F. 
ὑφηγήσατο could not properly be used of the sign which 
according to Plato ἀεὶ ἀποτρέπει . . . προτρέπει δὲ οὔποτε 
(Apology 31 Ὁ 3-4, cf. Phaedrus 242 c 1), but Plutarch seems 
to have neglected this limitation (cf. De Genio Socratis 581 B: 
δαιμόνιον εἶναι τὸ κωλῦον ἢ κελεῦον ἔλεγε). 


7 Cf. Plato, Theaetetus 210 c 2-4 and Sophist 230 5 4-Ὁ 8. 
21 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(999) ) Bas ἀπράκτους ἐν ἔρισι καὶ φιλοτιμίαις καλὸν δὲ 
καὶ χρήσιμον οὐδ᾽ ὁτιοῦν. τὸν οὖν ἐλεγκτικὸν 
λόγον ὥσπερ καθαρτικὸν ἔ ἔχων φάρμακον ὁ Σω- 

F κράτης ἀξιόπιστος ἢ ἦν ἑτέρους ἐλέγχων τῷ μηδὲν 
ἀποφαίνεσθαι, καὶ μᾶλλον ἥπτετο δοκῶν ζητεῖν 
κοινῇ τὴν ἀλήθειαν οὐκ αὐτὸς ἰδίᾳ δόξῃ; βοηθεῖν. 

1000 2. "Ἔπειτα τοῦ κρίνειν ὄντος ὠφελίμου, τὸ γεν- 
vay" ἐμπόδιόν ἐστι. τυφλοῦται γὰρ τὸ φιλοῦν 
περὶ τὸ φιλούμενον" φιλεῖται δὲ τῶν ἰδίων οὐδὲν 
οὕτως ὡς δόξα καὶ λόγος ὑπὸ τοῦ τεκόντος. ἡ 
γὰρ λεγομένη τέκνων δικαιοτάτη διανομὴ" πρὸς 

ὄγους ἐστὶν ἀδικωτάτη" δεῖ γὰρ ἐκεῖ μὲν λα- 
βεῖν᾽ τὸ ἴδιον ἐνταῦθα δέ, κἂν ἀλλότριον ἢ, τὸ 
’ e € ~ ΜΝ U , 
βέλτιστον. ὅθεν ὁ γεννῶν ἴδια γίγνεται φαυλό- 
τερος ἑτέρων κριτής. καὶ καθάπερ ᾿Ηλείους τῶν 
~ 6 yu f “A 4 ~ 3 / 
σοφῶν" tis ἔφη βελτίους av εἶναι τῶν ᾿Ολυμπίων 
3 ’ > A t 3 ’ = 3 ; 
ἀγωνοθέτας, εἰ μηδὲ εἷς ᾿Ηλείων ἦν ἀγωνιστής, 
οὕτως ὁ μέλλων ἐν λόγοις ὀρθῶς ἐπιστατήσειν 
1 φάρμακον € ἔχων -Β. 3 δόξης -X, J} (ὃ -ἢ over erasure), 
εἼ ἐνναῖον -J, g. νομὴ -Β. 


& X, E, B e,N; ἐκεῖ λαβεῖν μὲν -J, g. 
6 σοφιστῶν -J, g. 


* See 1000 c-p infra (οὐ yap σώματος ἡ Σωκράτους i ἰατρεία 
ψυχῆς δ᾽ ἦν... καθαρμός). The source is Plato’s Sophist 280 c 
3-r 3 and 231 s 3-8. Cf. Philo of Larissa in Stobaeus, Eel. 
ii, 7, 2 (p. 40, 11-20 [Wachsmuth]); Albinus, Prologue vi 
(p. 150, 15-35 [Hermann]) ; Cebetis Tabula xix; ; Philo 
Jud., De Decalogo 10-13 (iv, pp. 270, 23-271, 13 {Cohn}). 

> Theactetus 150 c 5-6; ; ef. Anon. in Platonis Theaetetum 
(Pap. Berl. 9782), col. 54, 17-26. 

¢ Cf. Plutarch, Quomodo Adulator ab Amico Internoscatur 
72a and Adv. Colotem 1117 Ὁ (cf. Pohlenz-Westman, Moralia 
vi/2, p. 237, note to p. 194, 26-28); Plato, Charmides 165 B 
5-8 and Gorgias 506 a 3-5 and Cratylus 384 c 1-3. 

@ So given as from Plato in Quomodo Adulator ab Amico 


22 





PLATONIC QUESTIONS 1, 999-1000 


cussion of arguments and for disputations futile in 
wranglings and ambitious rivalries but not for any- 
thing fair and serviceable at all. So Socrates with 
his refutatory discourse like a purgative medicine 2 
by maintaining nothing ὃ claimed the credence of 
others when he refuted them, and he got the greater 
hold on them because he seemed to be seeking the 
truth along with them, not himself to be defending 
an opinion of his own.°¢ 

2. In the second place, while the exercise of judg- 
ment is beneficial, begetting is an obstacle to it, for 
what loves is blinded about the thing it loves ὁ and 
nothing of one’s own is so beloved as is an opinion 
or an argument by its parent. For the distribution 
of offspring that is proverbially most just ὁ is most 
unjust when applied to arguments, for in the former 
case one must take what is one’s own but in the 
latter what is best even if it be another's.‘ For this 
reason the man who begets his own becomes a poorer 
judge of others; and just as one of the sages said 
that Eleans would be better directors of the Olympic 
games if not a single Elean were entered in the con- 
test, so one who is going to be an upright moderator 


Internoscatur 48 E-F and in De Capienda ex Inimicis Utili- 

tate 90 a and 92 E; Plato in Laws 731 £ has τυφλοῦται yap 
περὶ τὸ φιλούμενον ὁ φιλῶν. 

¢ I have not found the proverb or saying cited elsewhere. 

7 Cf. Plato, Philebus 29 a (.. . δεῖν τἀλλότρια . . . λέγειν 

. ) and Phaedo 85 c 8-9 (.. pew γοῦν βέλτιστον ray ἀνθρω- 
πίνων λόγων λαβόντα .. .). 

σ Cf. Herodotus, ii, 160 and Diodorus Siculus, i, 95, 2. 
The impartiality with which the Eleans administered the 
games was, nevertheless, held to be exemplary (cf. Plutarch, 
TIycurgus xx, 6 [52 c-p]= Reg. et Imp. Apophthegmata 190 
c-p and 215 £-r; Dio Chrysostom, Oratio xiv =xxxi [von 
Arnim], 111; Athenaeus, viii, 350 b-c). 

3 


(1000) 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


καὶ βραβεύσειν' od δίκαιός ἐστιν αὐτὸς φιλοστε- 
φανεῖν οὐδ᾽ ἀνταγωνίζεσθαι τοῖς κρινομένοις. καὶ 
ap οἱ τῶν Ἑλλήνων στρατηγοὶ τὴν περὶ τῶν 
ἀριστείων ψῆφον φέροντες αὑτοὺς ἀρίστους ἔκρι- 
ναν ἅπαντες"" καὶ τῶν φι οσόφων οὐδεὶς ἔστιν, 
ὃς οὐ τοῦτο πέπονθε δίχα τῶν ὥσπερ Σωκράτης 
ὁμολογούντων. μηδὲν ἴδιον λέγειν" οὗτοι δὲ καθα- 
ροὺς μόνοι καὶ ἀδεκάστους τῆς ἀληθείας παρέχου- 
σιν ἑαυτοὺς δικαστάς. ὥσπερ γὰρ ὁ ἐν τοῖς ὠσὶν 
ἀήρ, ἂν μὴ σταθερὸς 7 μηδὲ φωνῆς ἰδίας ἔρημος ἀλλ᾽ 
ἤχου καὶ ῥοίζου μεστός, οὐκ ἀκριβῶς ἀντιλαμβάνε- 
ται τῶν φθεγγομένων, οὕτω TO τοὺς λόγους ἐν φι- 
Aocodia* κρῖνον, ἂν ἔνδοθεν ἀντιπαταγῇ {τιν καὶ 
ἀντηχῇ., δυσξύνετον ἔσται τῶν λεγομένων ἔξωθεν. 
ἡ γὰρ οἰκεία δόξα καὶ σύνοικος οὐ προσδέξεται τὸ 
διαφωνοῦν πρὸς αὑτήν, ὡς μαρτυρεῖ τῶν αἱρέσεων 
τὸ πλῆθος, ὧν, ἂν ἄριστα πράττῃ φιλοσοφία, 
μίαν ἔχει κατορθοῦσαν οἰομένας δὲ τὰς ἄλλας 
ἁπάσας καὶ μαχομένας" πρὸς τὴν ἀλήθειαν. 

8. "Ext τοίνυν, εἰ μὲν οὐδέν ἐστι καταληπτὸν 
ἀνθρώπῳ καὶ γνωστόν, εἰκότως ὁ θεὸς ἀπεκώ- 
καὶ βραβεύσειν -omitted by J, g. 
ἅπαντας τυ. 
τὸ -omitted by g. 
σοφίᾳ -Ἐὶ, B. 
ἀντιπαγῆ -8. 

Hubert; ἔνδοθέν «τῷ ἀντιπαταγῇ -Wyttenbach. 
οὐ προσδέξεται. .«. τὸ πλῆθος -omitted by J. 
φιλοσοφία, μίαν ἔχει -X, Ἐς, B; φιλοσοφίαν ἔχειν -J, δ: 


οσοφία μίαν ἔχειν -¢, ἢ. 
καὶ μαχομένας -omitted by J, g. 


O23 ὦ σι m@ (9 8 μα 


Ξ, 


φι 


4 Cf. De Herodoti Malignitate 871 ν-Ὲ and Themistocles 
xvii, 2; Herodotus, viii, 123. 
ὃ Cf. Theophrastus, De Sensibus 19 (Dox. Graeci, pp. 504, 


24 





PLATONIC QUESTIONS 1, 1000 


and umpire in arguments is bound not to crave the 
palm himself or to vie with the contenders. For 
even the generals of the Greeks when casting their 
ballot for the award of excellence all gave judgment 
for themselves as best 2; and of philosophers there 
is none to whom this has not happened apart from 
those who like Socrates admit that they say nothing 
original, and these alone show themselves to be 
sound and incorruptible judges of the truth. For as 
the air in the ears does not accurately perceive utter- 
ances if it be not still and free from sound of its own 
but full of ringing and buzzing,® so what judges argu- 
ments in philosophy will have poor understanding of 
statements coming from without if they are muffled 
by the clatter and noise {οἵ something) from within.¢ 
For personal opinion to which one is wedded will not 
accept what disagrees with her, as the multitude of 
systems testifies, of which philosophy, if she is faring 
her best, involves a single one being right and all 
the others guessing and being in conflict with the 
truth. 

3. Furthermore, if nothing is apprehensible and 
knowable to man,? it was reasonable for god to have 


29-505, 2) and 41 (Dow. Graeci, p. 511, 6-8) =Diogenes of 
Apollonia, frag. A 19 (ii, p. 55, 26-28 [D.-K.]). 

¢ Cf. the explanation of Socrates’ sensitivity to the 
‘* spiritual voice’ given in De Genio Socratis 588 p-r and 
589 c-p. 

¢ The position of Arcesilaus (for whom see note a on De 
Stoic. Repug. 1036 a infra), ascribed by him to Socrates also 
(cf. Adv. Colotem 1121 r—1122 a; Cicero, Acad. Post. i, 
44-45 and De Oratore iii, 67; Lactantius, Div. Inst. iii, 6, 
7=p. 188, 11-14 [Brandt]; A. Goedeckemeyer, Die Ge- 
schichte des griechischen Skeptizismus [Leipzig, 1905], pp. 
33-34). 


25 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1000) λυσεν αὐτὸν ὑπηνέμια καὶ ψευδῆ καὶ ἀβέβαια 
γεννᾶν ἐλέγχειν" δὲ τοὺς ἄλλους ἠνάγκαζε τοιαῦτα 
δοξάζοντας. οὐ γὰρ μικρὸν ἦν ὄφελος ἀλλὰ μέ- 
γιστον ὁ τοῦ μεγίστου τῶν κακῶν, ἀπάτης καὶ 
κενοφροσύνης, ἀπαλλάττων λόγος 


οὐδ᾽" βακληριήθοια τοῦτό γ᾽ ἔδωκε θεός. 


οὐ γὰρ σώματος ἡ Σωκράτους ἰατρεία ψυχῆς δ᾽ 
D ἦν ὑπούλου καὶ διεφθαρμένης καθαρμός. εἰ δ᾽ 
ἔστιν ἐπιστήμη τοῦ ἀληθοῦς ἕν δὲ τὸ ἀληθές, οὐκ 
ἔλαττον ἔχει τοῦ εὑρόντος ὁ μαθὼν παρὰ τοῦ 
e / 4 4 “- ς εὖ 4 
εὑρόντος" λαμβάνει δὲ μᾶλλον ὁ μὴ πεπεισμένος 
” A v A / > € 7 σ 
ἔχειν, καὶ λαμβάνει τὸ βέλτιστον ἐξ ἁπάντων, ὥσ- 
περ ὁ μὴ τεκὼν παῖδα ποιεῖται" τὸν ἄριστον. β 
4, Ὅρα δὲ μὴ τἄλλα μὲν οὐδεμιᾶς ἦν ἀξια 
σπουδῆς ποιήματα καὶ μαθήματα καὶ λόγοι ῥητό- 
ρων καὶ δόγματα σοφιστῶν, a Σωκράτην' γεννᾶν 
τὸ δαιμόνιον ἀπεκώλυσεν᾽ ἣν δὲ μόνην ἡγεῖτο Σω- 
κράτης σοφίαν, {τὴν " περὶ τὸ θεῖον καὶ νοητὸν" 
1 λέγειν -J, 8. 
εἰ δ᾽ ee (οὐ δ᾽ -Vat. gr. 915), 
8 Wyttenbach ; παιδοποιεῖται -MSS. 
δῦ, £3; Σωκ i7n -Χ, Εἰ, Β, e, ἢ. 
5 «τὴν» -added by Wilamowitz. 


6 νρητὴν -B. 


«α Cf. Plato, Theaetetus 151 © 5-6 and 160 © 6—161 a 4. 

ὃ Theognis, 432; cf. the use of the line (also with initial 
οὐδ᾽) by Dio Chrysostom, Oratio i, 8 (von Arnim). 

¢ Cf. Plato, Sophist 230 c—231 8B and note a on p. 22 
supra; and with ψυχῆς ὑπούλου cf. Gorgias 480 B 1-2 and 
524 £ 5—525 a 2. 

4 Cf. Cicero, Acad. Prior. ii, 115 and 147 and De Oratore ii, 
30 (‘cum plus uno verum esse non possit’’); Seneca, 
Epistle cii, 13; Lucian, Hermotimus 14 (τὸ δέ ye ἀληθὲς... 
ἕν ἦν avray.. ἐν ; and Aristotle, Anal. Prior. 47 a 8-9. 


26 





PLATONIC QUESTIONS 1, 1000 


prevented Socrates from begetting inane and false 
and baseless notions and to compel him to refute 
the others who were forming such opinions.* For 
the discourse that liberates from the greatest of 
evils, deception and vanity, was not a slight but a 
very great help— 

This gift god didn’t grant even Asclepius’ sons. ὃ 


lor the treatment given by Socrates was not of the 
body but was a purgation of the ulcerous and cor- 
rupted soul.¢ If, however, there is knowledge of 
what is true and what is true is single,¢ he who has 
learned it from the discoverer does not possess it less 
than he who discovered it ¢; but the one who ac- 
quires it is rather he who is not sure that he possesses 
it,f and he acquires what is best of all, just as he 
who is not a parent himself adopts the child that is 
best. 

4. Consider too that, while the other things, 
poetry and mathematics and rhetorical speeches 
and sophistic doctrines, which the spiritual power 9 
prevented Socrates from begetting, were worth no 
serious concern, what Socrates held to be alone 
wisdom, <that) which he called passion for the 


¢ See, however, De Recta Ratione Audiendi 48 B-p and 
Plutarch’s advice there ἀσκεῖν ἅμα τῇ μαθήσει τὴν εὕρεσιν. 
The proverbial alternative ἢ εὑρεῖν ἢ παρ᾽ ἄλλου μαθεῖν (cf. 
Plato, Laches 186 c and 186 π΄--Ι87 a; Phaedo 85 c 71-8 
and 99 c 6-9; [Alcibiades i] 106 bp, 109 p-r, and 110 p; 
[ Demodocus] 381 £ 6-8; Aristotle, Topics 178 Ὁ 34-35) was 
itself converted into a proof that μάθησις is ἀνάμνησις (Maxi- 
mus of Tyre, Philos. x, v h -vib=pp. 119, 8-120, 20 [Ho- 
bein}). 

f Contrast the situation of those who . . . πρὶν ἢ λαβεῖν 
ἔχειν ὁμολογοῦντες οὐ λαμβάνουσιν (De Recta Ratione Audiendi 
47 p). 9 See note 6 on p. 21 supra. 


27 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


3 \ δι εὐ > ~ , ’ " 
(1000) ἐρωτικὴν ὑπ᾽ αὐτοῦ προσαγορευομένην, ταύτης οὐ 
1) / 3) Be! θ 7 10 \ vd > 3. “5 / 
γένεσις ἔστιν ἀνθρώποις οὐδὲ εὕρεσις ἀλλ᾽ ἀνάμνη- 
\ QO 7 4 3 3... 
σις. ὅθεν οὐδὲν ἐδίδασκε Σωκράτης, ἀλλ᾽ ἐνδιδοὺς 
A 7 A 3 
ἀρχὰς ἀποριῶν ὥσπερ ὠδίνων τοῖς νέοις ἐπήγειρε 
καὶ ἀνεκίνει καὶ συνεξῆγε τὰς ἐμφύτους νοήσεις" 
καὶ τοῦτο μαιωτικὴν τέχνην ὠνόμαζεν, οὐκ ἐν- 
τιθεῖσαν ἔξωθεν, ὥσπερ ἕτεροι προσεποιοῦντο, νοῦν 
τοῖς ἐντυγχάνουσιν, ἀλλ᾽ ἔχοντας οἰκεῖον ἐν 
ἑαυτοῖς ἀτελῆ δὲ καὶ συγκεχυμένον καὶ δεόμενον' 
τοῦ τρέφοντος καὶ βεβαιοῦντος" ἐπιδεικνύουσαν. 


ZHTHMA Β΄ 


1. Τί δήποτε τὸν ἀνωτάτω θεὸν πατέρα τῶν" 
πάντων καὶ ποιητὴν προσεῖπε," πότερον ὅτι" τῶν 
μὲν θεῶν τῶν γεννητῶν" καὶ τῶν ἀνθρώπων πα- 

1 καὶ δεόμενον -omitted by J, g. 

2 καὶ βεβαιοῦντος -omitted by J, g. 
8 τῶν -omitted by J, g. 
* προσεῖπεν -J, g. 

5 πότερον ὅτι -omitted by J, g. 

wen £3 γενητῶν a EB. 6, Bs 
¢ Cf. Plato, Symposiwm 204 8B 2-5 and 210 r—212 a; 
Republic 490 a 8-8 7 and 501 ἢ 1-2 with 409 a (... ἣν 
μόνην δεῖ... σοφίαν καλεῖσθαι) and Theaetetus 176 c 85-Ὁ 1. 

’ Cf. Plutarch, De Defectu Orac. 422 B-c and the theses 
ascribed to him in Olympiodorus, Jn Platonis Phaedonem, 
pp. 155, 24-157, 12 and 212, 1-26 (Norvin). For parallels 
with this and the remainder of this section in Cicero, Albinus, 
Maximus of Tyre, and the anonymous commentator on 
Plato’s Theaetetus cf. O. Luschnat, Theologia Viatorum, viii 
(1961/62), pp. 167-171; and for the Platonic doctrine of 
reminiscence cf. Meno 85 p—86 B, Phaedo 72 ε---ἴθ πὶ and 
91", and Phaedrus 249 5 5—c 4. 

¢ Cf. Theaetetus 151 a 5-8 1 and 157 c 9—n 2. The ἔμφυτοι 
νοήσεις here are not “inbred” as are the Stoic ἔμφυτοι 
προλήψεις (see note 6 on De Stoic. Repug. 1041 Ἑ infra), 


28 





PLATONIC QUESTIONS 1-11, 1000 


divine and intelligible,* is for human beings a matter 
not of generation or of discovery but of reminiscence.? 
For this reason Socrates was not engaged in teaching 
anything, but by exciting perplexities as if inducing 
the inception of labour-pains in young men he would 
arouse and quicken and help to deliver their innate 
conceptions ©; and his name for this was obstetric 
skill,¢ since it does not, as other men pretended to 
do, implant in those who come upon it intelligence 
from without but shows that they have it native 
within themselves but undeveloped and confused and 
in need of nurture and stabilization. 


QUESTION II 


1. WuyeEver did he call the supreme god father and 
maker of all things ἢ ὁ Was it because he is of gods, 
the gods that are engendered,f and of men father, as 


despite the Stoic terminology : cf. Cicero, Tusc. Disp. i, 57 : 
“,..insitas ... notiones quas ἐννοίας vocant...”’; Anon. in 
Platonis Theaetetum (Pap. Berl. 9782), col. 47, 42-45: . .. 
ἀναπτύσσων αὐτῶν tas φυσικὰς ἐννοίας . . . 3; and especially 
re” Epitome iv, 6 (Louis) =P. 155, 17-29 (Hermann) : 
νόησις . . διττὴ. ΐ ἡ μὲν πρὸ τοῦ ἐν σώματι γενέσθαι τὴν ψυ- 
χὴν. . γενομένης δ᾽ pret ἐν σώματι ἡ τότε λεγομένη νόησις νῦν 
ἐλέχθη φυσικὴ ἔννοια. .. 
¢ Cf. Theaetetus 161 π 4-6, 184 a 8- 2, 210 B 8-9; Olym- 

piodorus, Jn Platonis Phaedonem, p. 159, 1-3 (N orvin) = Plu- 
tarch, AZoralia vii, p. 33, 7-10 (Bernardakis). 

eA paraphrase of Timaeus 28 c 3-4 (τὸν μὲν οὖν ποιητὴν 
καὶ πατέρα τοῦδε τοῦ παντός), the interpretation of which is 
discussed at length by Proclus (In Platonis Timaeum i, pp. 
299, 13-319, 21 [Diehl], especially pp. 299, 21-300, 28; pp. 
303, 24-304, 22; and pp. 311, 25-312, 9) and which is para- 
phrased somewhat differently by Plutarch in Quaest. Conviv. 
718 a (. τὸς α καὶ ποιητὴν τοῦ τε κόσμου καὶ τῶν ἄλλων 
hl hdl Cf. also Timaeus 37 c7 and 41 a 5-7. 

oy. fia a Ὁ 4 (θεῶν ὁρατῶν καὶ γεννητῶν). 


29 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1000) τήρ ἐστιν, ws’ Ὅμηρος ἐπονομάζει, ποιητὴς δὲ 
Ε τῶν ἀλόγων καὶ ἀψύχων; οὐδὲ yap" xopiov® φη- 


1001 


at Χρύσιππος πατέρα καλεῖσθαι τὸν παρασχόντα 
τὸ σπέρμα, καίπερ ἐκ τοῦ σπέρματος γεγονότος. 
7 τῇ μεταφορᾷ “χρώμενος, ὥσπερ εἴωθε, τὸν 
αἴτιον πατέρα τοῦ κόσμου κέκληκεν; ὡς τῶν 
ἐρωτικῶν λόγων πατέρα Φαῖδρον ἐν Συμποσίῳ 
προσεῖπεν, εἰσηγητὴν αὐτῶν" γενόμενον ἐν δὲ 
τῷ “ὁμωνύμῳ διαλόγῳ καλλίπαιδα": πολλοὺς γὰρ 
καὶ καλοὺς λόγους ἐν φιλοσοφίᾳ γενέσθαι, τὴν 
ἀρχὴν ἐκείνου παρασχόντος. 7° διαφέρει πατήρ 


τε ποιητοῦ καὶ γεννήσεως γένεσις 3; ws γὰρ TO 


γεγεννημένον και γέγονεν, * od μὴν ἀνάπαλιν, ov- 


TWS ὁ γεννήσας καὶ πεποίηκεν" ' ἐμψύχου γὰρ γέ- 
νεσις ἡ γέννησίς ἐστι. καὶ ποιητοῦ μέν, οἷος 
οἰκοδόμος 7 ἢ ὑφάντης ἢ λύρας δημιουργὸς 7 ἢ ἀνδρι- 
dvtos, ἀπήλλακται γενόμενον τὸ Epyov"*: ἡ δ᾽ ἀπὸ 


Ξ δ -e3 ὡς -all other MSS. 
AX, FE, B, ns ov yap -J, 23 οὐδὲ -e. 

3 » Te xopeiov -X, FE, B; χωρίου -J, £3 χωρείου -e, 
nN. 

4 ἢ -Stephanus; καὶ -Εἰ (added superscript), B; omitted 
by δ J > 2,6, Nn 

5 αὐτὸν -J, g. 

6 Wyttenbach ; καλλιπίδαν -X, J, σ᾽; καλλιππίδαν -E, B, 
Ey τῇ 

᾿ γὰρ καὶ -Χ, τ ΒΒ, ε. ἢ ; γὰρ ἦν καὶ -J, g. 
7-3, 5: ΤῸΝ Dy Ὡς: tp 

ϑ f, B, ἐπ: γένησις rd ἘΣ ε superscript over 7 -δ ἢ): 
γέννησις -J, £3 ποίησις -Leonicus. 

10 γέγονεν ~MSS. 5 πεποίηται -Donato Polo. 

τ «οὐ μὴν ἀνάπαλιννρ -added by Meziriac; «οὐ μὴν ὁ 
πεποιηκὼς γεγέννηκενΣ -added by Pohlenz after πεποίηκεν. 

a γένεσις “MES. 3 ποίησις -TLeonicus. 

183. ἀνδρίαν τε -J. 14 τὸ γενόμενον ἔργον -J, £. 











en ee 








@ Jliad i, 544 and often elsewhere. 


30 





PLATONIC QUESTIONS τι, 1000-1001 


Homer names him,? but maker of irrational beings 
and of inanimate things?’ For not even of the 
placenta, says Chrysippus,° though it is a product of 
the seed, is he who provided the seed called father. 
Or is it by his customary use of metaphor that he 
has called him who is responsible for the universe 
its father ? Soin the Symposium ἃ he called Phaedrus 
father of the amatory discourses because he was in- 
stigator of them and in the dialogue that bears his 
name ὁ called him blessed with fair children because 
as a result of his initiative philosophy had been filled 
with many fair discourses.’ Or is there a difference 
between father and maker and between birth 9 and 
coming to be? For as what has been born has ipso 
facto come to be but not contrariwise so it is that he 
who has begotten has ipso facto made, for birth is 
the coming to be of an animate thing. Also in the 
case of a maker, such as a builder is or a weaver or 
one who produces a lyre or a statue, his work when 
done is separated from him, whereas the principle 

ὃ This interpretation is mentioned and rejected by Proclus, 
In Platonis Timaeum i, p. 319, 15-21 (Diehl). 

¢ §.V.F. ii, frag. 1158. 

4 Symposium 177 vp 4-5 (cf. 177 a 4). 

¢ Phaedrus 261 a 3-4. 

t Cf. Phaedrus 242 a 8-8 5 and Hermias, In Platonis 
Phaedrum, Ὁ. 223, 18-19 (Couvreur): ... καλοὺς παῖδας 
τίκτοντα τοὺς λόγους. 

σ For this passive meaning οὗ γέννησις cf. e.g. Cornutus, 
Theologia Graeca 30 (p. 58, 14 [Lang]) and Hippolytus, 
Refutatio, vii, 29, 14 (p. 212, 18 [Wendland]). The erroneous 
assumption that the word can have only the active meaning, 
‘* procreation,’ was apparently responsible for the drastic 
emendations of tie passage made in the sixteenth century 
and adopted by later editors. It should be noticed, moreover, 
that Hubert’s report of the readings of X in this passage is 
erroneous. 


31 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


lo , > \ \ , 3 
(1001) τοῦ γεννήσαντος ἀρχὴ καὶ δύναμις ἐγκεκραται 
“a A ἤ 4 , : 
τῷ τεκνωθέντι καὶ συνέχει τὴν φύσιν, ἀπόσπασμα 
καὶ μόριον οὖσαν τοῦ τεκνώσαντος. ἐπεὶ τοίνυν 
7 ς / 0 .κ 
Β οὐ πεπλασμένοις ὁ κόσμος οὐδὲ συνηρμοσμένοις 
ποιήμασιν ἔοικεν, ἀλλ᾽ ἔνεστιν αὐτῷ μοῖρα 
\ , 4 ι , a « ἢ > 
πολλὴ ζῳότητος" Kai θειότητος, ἣν ὁ θεὸς ἐγ- 
/ > 795 ¢ ie A. bie te \ , 
κατέσπειρεν ap” ἑαυτοῦ τῇ ὕλῃ" Kal κατέμιξεν, 
εἰκότως ἅμα πατήρ τε τοῦ κόσμου, ζῴου γεγονό- 
τος, καὶ ποιητὴς ἐπονομάζεται 
2. Τούτων δὲ μάλιστα τῆς [[λάτωνος ἅπτο- ἑ 
, , er, > ee ae ΄, ; 
μένων δόξης, ἐπίστησον εἰ κἀκεῖνος λεχθήσεται. 
πιθανῶς" ὅτι, δυεῖν ὄντων ἐξ ὧν ὁ κόσμος συνέ- 
στῆκε, σώματος καὶ ψυχῆς, τὸ μὲν οὐκ ἐγέννησε 
θεὸς ἀλλά, τῆς ὕλης παρασχομένης, ἐμόρφωσε καὶ 
συνήρμοσε, πέρασιν οἰκείοις καὶ σχήμασι δήσας 
( καὶ ὁρίσας τὸ ἄπειρον' ἡ δὲ ψυχή, νοῦ μετασχοῦσα 
καὶ λογισμοῦ καὶ ἁρμονίας, οὐκ ἔργον ἐστὶ τοῦ 


=< 


1 τοῦ τεκνώσαντος -omitted by n. 
2 ἔρικεν -omitted by B. 
3 ἔστιν -J. 
4 ζωότητος πολλὴ -Β. 
5 ἐφ᾽ -J, τι 
6 τῇ ἕλη -Χ. 
ὀνομάζεται -ε. 
8 κἀκεῖ -J, ρ΄. 


9 ὁ E 3 δυοῖν -J, gz; B, €, ἢ. 


a ........-...-΄ ς΄. --ῦΠ5..-.ρ΄π.....-΄΄...νϑν.΄ῤ.ᾷν0........Ν.1τ.ὕ0...---. 


7 


“ΟἹ De Sera Numinis Vindicta 559 dD (τὸ γεννηθὲν οὐχ 
ὥς τι δημιούργημα πεποιημένον ἀπήλλακται τοῦ γεννήσαντος) 3 
S.V.F. ii, p. 308, 15-18; [Galen], Ad Gaurum x, 4 (p. 47, 
12-15 [Kalbfleisch]) ; and contra Philoponus, De Aeternitate 
Mundi xiii, 9 (pp. 500, 26-501, 12 [Rabe]}). 


32 





PLATONIC QUESTIONS u, 1001 


or force emanating from the parent is blended in the 
progeny * and cohibits its nature, which is a frag- 
ment or part of the procreator.? Since, then, the 
universe is not like products that have been moulded 
or fitted together but has in it a large portion of 
vitality and divinity, which god sowed from himself 
in the matter © and mixed with it, it is reasonable 
that, since the universe has come into being a living 
thing, god be named at the same time father of it 
and maker. 

2. While this most nearly coincides with Plato’s 
opinion, consider whether there will be plausibility 
in the following statement also: There are two con- 
stituent parts of the universe, body and soul.4 The 
former god did not beget ; but, matter having sub- 
mitted itself to him, he formed and fitted it to- 
gether ὁ by binding and bounding the unlimited with 
suitable limits and shapes.f The soul, however, when 
it has partaken of intelligence and reason and con- 

> Cf. S.V.F. i, frag. 128 including Plutarch, De Cohibenda 
Ira 462 τ. 

CCF. Quaest. Conviv. 118 ἃ (. . . ἄλλῃ δὲ δυνάμει τοῦ θεοῦ 

τῇ ὕλῃ γόνιμον ἀρχὴν . .. ἐντεκόντος) and Plato, Timaeus 
41 c 7-p 1, where the figure of “ sowing ᾿ is used but not in 
connexion with the vitalization of the universe, for which c/. 
Timaeus 36 Ὁ 8-£ 5. 

4 Cf. Albinus, Epitome xiii, 1 (p. 73, 4-5 [Louis] =p. 168, 
6-7 [Hermann}) ; Plato, Timaeus 34 a 8—B 4 and 36 Dp 8- 
= 1, 

eT. De An. Proc. in Timaeo 1014 B-c (τὴν δ᾽ οὐσίαν καὶ 
iy . . ἐμπαρασχεῖν. eae ἔταξε καὶ διεκόσμησε καὶ συνήρμοσε 

) and De Iside 372 F (... χώρα καὶ ὕλη . . . παρέχουσα 


ΠΆΡΕ ἐξ ἑαυτῆς ἐκείνῳ. 

7 Cf. Quaest. Conviv. 719 c-r and De An. Proc. in Timaeo 
1048 ὁ. For the figure of the “ bond ” cf. Timaeus 31 ς 1— 
32 c 4 and for the “ binding” of the unlimited by limit 
Philebus 27 p 9. 


33 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1001) θεοῦ μόνον ἀλλὰ καὶ μέρος, οὐδὲ ὑπ᾽ αὐτοῦ ἀλλὰ 
Kat’ ἀπ᾽ αὐτοῦ καὶ ἐξ αὐτοῦ γέγονεν. 


ZHTHMA I” 


3 “» an ~ 
Ev τῇ [Πολιτείᾳ [γοῦν] τοῦ" παντὸς ὥσπερ 
ἡ δὶ γραμμῆς τετμημένης εἰς" ἄνισα τμήματα, 
πάλιν τέμνων ἑκάτερον τμῆμα εἰς δύο ἀνὰ τὸν 
αὐτὸν λόγον, τό τε τοῦ ὁρωμένου γένους" καὶ τὸ 
~ / ~ 
τοῦ νοουμένου, τέσσαρα τὰ πάντα ποιήσας τοῦ 
ron) a > ~ 
μὲν νοητοῦ πρῶτον ἀποφαίνει TO περὶ τὰ πρῶτα 
Uy , A > ~ 
εἴδη, δεύτερον TO μαθηματικόν, τοῦ δ᾽. αἰσθητοῦ 
πρῶτον μὲν τὰ στερέμνια σώματα, δεύτερον δὲ 
,“ 3 
τὰς εἰκόνας καὶ τὰ εἴδωλα τούτων: καὶ κριτήριον" 
D ἑκάστῳ τῶν τεσσάρων ἀποδίδωσιν ἴδιον, νοῦν μὲν 
τῷ πρώτῳ διάνοιαν δὲ τῷ μαθηματικῷ" τοῖς δ᾽ 
’ 6 A ἢ > , δὲ ἊἋ 10 tle? ἫΝ 
αἰσθητοῖς πίστιν, εἰκασίαν δὲ Tots’ περὶ τὰ εἴδωλα 
3 - 
Kal Tas εἰκόνας. τί οὖν διανοηθεὶς Eis’ ἄνισα τμή- 
1 καὶ -omitted by J, g; ἀλλὰ καὶ -all other mss. 
2 New question distinguished by Wyttenbach. 
3 [γοῦν] -deleted by Wyttenbach; γοῦν τοῦ -X, KE, B, «, 
n; γοῦν -J, g. 4 εἰς -omitted by J, g. 
5 γένους -X, E!, ες n, Plato (Republic 509 pv 8); γένος -J, 
g, B, E? (os superscript over ous). 


’ Hubert (τέτταρα [ra] -Wyttenbach) ; ; περὶ τὰ -J ; παρὰ τ 
-all other Mss. ; μέρη δ᾽ (1.6. μέρη τέσσαρα) - -Bernardakis, aes 


basileios (Athena, x [1898], p. 225). » μαθητικόν -J}, ε: 
8 κριτηρίῳ -J, δ. ® μαθητικῷ -J, 8". 
10 δὲ τῆς -J, g, ἢ. 11 εἰς -omitted by J, 5 Β2 


....-...-...-. Ρ΄΄ΠΡὅὄἧΠἷἝἷὙΠἷὔἷΠὅΠ΄“΄“΄Π΄Π ΄΄΄΄΄΄.- .-.....:..΄.--Ὃὦἃὦ΄΄'ὦΚ...-.-..-. .... -. 





α Cf. 1003 a infra and De An. Proc. in Timaeo 1014 Ἐ eee 
1016 B (quoting Timaeus 36 © 6—37 a 1). ἁρμονία, which I 
regularly translate ‘ concord,” means not “᾿ harmony ”’ in 
the modern sense of notes played or sung together as 
‘‘ chords ” but generally a “ fitting together ἢ and in ninsic 
such a fitting together of sequential sounds to produce a tune 
ora“ scale’ (e.g. De An. Proc. in Timaeo 1021 8 infra) ; and 


34 





PLATONIC QUESTIONS 11-10, 1001 


cord,* is not merely a work but also a part of god 
and has come to be not by his agency but both from 
him as source and out of his substance.? 


QUESTION II 


1. In the Republic ¢ he likens the sum of things to a 
single line that has been divided into unequal seg- 
ments, again divides into two in the same ratio each 
of the two segments, that of the visible class and 
that of the conceptual, and, having made four in 
all, declares first of the intelligible segment that of 
the primary ideas, second the mathematical, and 
first of the perceptible segment the solid bodies and 
second the semblances and images of these. Also 
to each of the four he assigns its own peculiar 
criterion: intelligence to the first and thought to 
the mathematical segment and to the perceptibles 
belief and conjecture to matters of images and 
semblances. What, then, did he have in mind when 
he divided the sum of things into unequal? seg- 
of harmony in this sense the theory is ἡ ἁρμονική (e.g. 1001 F 
infra). 

> Cf. De Sera Numinis Vindicta 559 pv (. .. ἐξ αὐτοῦ γάρ, 
οὐχ ὑπ᾽ αὐτοῦ, γέγονεν ὥστ᾽ ἔχει τι Kal φέρεται τῶν ἐκείνου μέρος 
ἐν ἑαυτῷ .. .) and see Jones, Platonism of Plutarch, Ὁ. 10, 
n. 15 and p. 105; Η. Dérrie, Museum Helveticum, xxvi 
(1969), p. 222 and Philomathes : Studies ...in Memory of 
Philip Merlan (The Hague, 1971), pp. 40-41. 

¢ Republic 509 p 6—511 £ 5. 

4 Even in antiquity some, apparently reading ἀν᾽ ἴσα or ica 
in Republic 509 ἢ 6 (cf. dv, ἴσα -cod. ΕἾ, tried to explain why 
Plato had divided the line into equal segments (Iamblichus, 
De Comm. Math. Scientia, p. 36, 15-23 [Pseudo-Archytas, 
frag. 3, Nolle] and p. 38, 15-28 [Festa] ; Scholia in Platonis 
Rem Publicam 509 p [vi, p. 350, 9-16, Hermann]) ; but con- 


trast Proclus, Jn Platonis Rem Publicam i, p. 288, 18-20 and 
26-27 (Kroll). 


35 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1001) para’ τὸ πᾶν ἔτεμε; ὖ καὶ πότερον τῶν τμημά- 
τῶν, τὸ νοητὸν ἢ τὸ αἰσθητόν, μεῖζόν ἐστιν; αὐτὸς 
γὰρ οὐ δεδήλωκε. 

Δόξει δ᾽ αὐτόθεν μὲν εἶναι μεῖζον τὸ αἰσθητόν" 
ἡ γὰρ ἀμέριστος οὐσία καὶ κατὰ ταὐτὸν ὡσαύτως 
ἔχουσα τῶν νοητῶν ἐστιν εἰς βραχὺ συνηγμένη" 
καὶ καθαρόν, ἡ δὲ σκεδαστὴ περὶ τὰ σώματα καὶ 
περιπλανὴς τὸ αἰσθητὸν παρέσχεν. ἔτι τὸ μὲν ἀσώ- 
ματον πέρατος οἰκεῖον, τὸ δὲ σῶμα τῇ μὲν ὕλῃ" 
ἄπειρον καὶ ἀόριστον αἰσθητὸν δὲ γιγνόμενον" ὅταν 

E ὁρισθῇ μετοχῇ τοῦ νοητοῦ. ἔτι, καθάπερ αὐτῶν 
τῶν αἰσθητῶν ἕκαστον εἰκόνας ἔχει πλείους καὶ 
Ἁ Ἁ ᾽} Α i > 3 ag | , 
σκιὰς καὶ εἴδωλα καὶ ὅλως ἀφ᾽ ἑνὸς παραδείγμα- 
τος πάμπολλα μιμήματα γίγνεσθαι καὶ φύσει καὶ 
τέχνῃ υνατόν ἐστιν, οὕτως ἀνάγκη τὰ ἐνταῦθα 
τῶν ἐκεῖ πλήθει διαφέρειν κατὰ τὸν [ἰλάτωνα 
παραδείγματα καὶ ἰδέας τὰ νοητὰ" τῶν αἰσθητῶν 
ὥσπερ εἰκόνων ἢ ἐμφάσεων ὑποτιθέμενον. ἔτιδ 

” ϑῶ A e tp / *\9 3 > / 
τῶν εἰδῶν ἡ νόησις <- νόησιν δ᾽)" ἐξ ἀφαιρέσεως 

ἔτ, Ἔ : τὰ τμήματα -X, J, 2, «, 1 

Ξ τι. Β: ἔτεμνε -X, J, G. €, Nl. 

ὁ συνημμ ἕνη τε. 
4 τῇ ὕλῃ μὲν -Benseler (but ef. Bolkestein, Adversaria, 
pp. 98-99 and Ρ. 105). 

5 γίγνεται μόνον -Bernardakis (but cf. De Exilio 599 B-c 
and Wyttenbach, Animadversiones on 40 p). 

6 Stephanus ; νοήματα -Μ88. 

7 ὑποτιθεμένων J; g. ὃ ἔτι -Leonicus : ἕν -Mss. 

9Ὴ. C.3 ἡ νόησις ἐξ -μ88.; τὴν νόησιν ἐξ -Leonicus ; 
νόησιν ἐξ -Stephanus. 





α Cf. the argument of Pseudo-Brontinus, μεῖζον . .. τὸ 
διανοατὸν τῶ νοατῶ, quoted and commented upon by Iambli- 
chus, De Comm. Math. Scientia, pp. 34, 20-35, 26 (Festa). 
> This terminology comes from Timaeus 35 a 1-6 and 37 a 
5-6. Cf. De An. Proc. in Timaeo 1012 B, 1014 p, and 1022 


36 





PLATONIC QUESTIONS m1, 1001 


ments? And which of the segments is larger, the 
intelligible or the perceptible ? For he has not made 
it clear himself. 

On the face of it the perceptible segment would 
seem to be larger,* for the indivisible and invariably 
identical being of the intelligibles is narrowly and 
purely concentrated but the perceptible segment was 
provided by the dispersed and erratic being of 
bodies. Moreover, incorporeality is proper to 
limit,° whereas body, while in matter it is unlimited 
and indefinite, becomes perceptible whenever it is 
bounded by virtue of participation in the intelligible.4 
Moreover, just as each of the perceptibles them- 
selves has a multiplicity of semblances and shadows 
and images and as generally both in nature and in 
art it is possible for numerous copies to come from a 
single pattern, so the things of this world must sur- 
pass in number the things of that world according to 
Plato’s supposition that the intelligibles are patterns, 
that is ideas, of which the perceptibles are as sem- 
blances or reflections.¢ Moreover, the ideas are the 
objects of intellection 4 {; and intellection) he in- 


E-F ; De Defectu Orac. 428 8 and 430 F; and further with ἡ 
σκεδαστὴ ... καὶ περιπλανής De An. Proc. in Timaeo 1023 c 
and 1024 a, Quaest. Conviv. 718 p and 719 Ε. 

¢ Cf. De Comm. Not. 1080 Ἑ (τὸ δὲ πέρας σῶμα οὐκ ἔστιν). 

4 See 1001 8 supra and note /f there but especially De An. 
Proc. in Timaeo 1013 ὁ (τῆς μὲν ὕλης τὸ μετοχῇ . . . τοῦ 
νοητοῦ μορφωθὲν εὐθὺς ἁπτὸν καὶ ὁρατόν ἐστιν). 

ε Cf. Areius Didymus, Epitomes Frag. Phys. 1 (Dox. 
Graeci, p. 477 a 5-16 and 8 4-12) =Eusebius, Praep. Evang. 
xi, 23, 3-4 and Albinus, Epitome xii, 1 (Louis) =pp. 166, 37- 
167, 5 (Hermann). 

t Republic 511 Ὁ 8 ; cf. Timaeus 52 a 1-4 and 28 a 1-2 with 
Philebus 62 a 2-5, and n.b. Republic 534 a, where νόησις 
refers to the two upper segments of the line together. 


37 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1001) καὶ περικοπῆς" σώματος ἐπάγει, TH τῶν μαθημά- 
tov’ τάξει καταβιβάζων ἀπὸ τῆς ἀριθμητικῆς ἐπὶ 
γεωμετρίαν, εἶτα μετὰ ταύτην ἐπ᾽ ἀστρολογίαν, 
2, 2% 4 A A K , 

Ε ἐπὶ πάσαις δὲ τὴν ἁρμονικὴν τιθείς" γίγνεται γὰρ 
τὰ Lev’ γεωμετρούμενα, τοῦ ποσοῦ μέγεθος προσ- 
λαβόντος". τὰ δὲ στερεά, τοῦ μεγέθους βάθος' 
τὰ δ᾽ ἀστρολογούμενα, τοῦ στερεοῦ κίνησιν: τὰ 
δὲ ἁρμονικά, τῷ κινουμένῳ σώματι φωνῆς προσ- 
γενομένης. ὅθεν ἀφαιροῦντες φωνὴν μὲν τῶν κι- 
νουμένων κίνησιν δὲ τῶν στερεῶν βάθος δὲ τῶν 

1002 ἐπιπέδων, μέγεθος δὲ τῶν ποσῶν, ἐν αὐταῖς γε- 
νησόμεθα ταῖς νοηταῖς ἰδέαις, οὐδεμίαν διαφορὰν 
> ’ 8 4 > Ζ Ἁ αἱ Δ \ 4 6 
ἐχούσαις" πρὸς ἀλλήλας κατὰ TO Ev καὶ μονάδα 
νοουμένζαις).ἷ οὐ γὰρ ποιεῖ μονὰς ἀριθμόν, ἂν 

1 περισκοπῆς -J, g- 2 Leonicus ; μαθητῶν -Mss. 

γίγνεται μὲν γὰρ τὰ Εν τ λυ ταν -J, g. 

προλαβόντος -J*. 5 EK, Β, ε: ἐχούσας -X, J, g, n. 

μονάδα -H. Ὁ. ; μόνον -mss.; [καὶ] μόνον -Bury. 

7 Pohlenz; νοοῦμεν -X, E, B, ε, n; omitted by J, g; 
νοούμενον -Diibner. 


* The course of studies in Republic 525 5 3—531 τ 6 is 
meant. According to Plato (Republic 531 p 7—535 a 2) the 
_ whole of this is a progressive course of training leading up to 
dialectic, the method which alone reveals the ideas; but 
καταβιβάζων here implies that it is instead a graduated descent 
and departure from the ideas, and hence it is inferred that 
graduated abstraction in the reverse order (cf. ὅθεν ἀφαιροῦν- 
res... [1001 F tnfra}) will bring one to the ideas them- 
selves. 
> Because of ra δὲ στερεά infra and Republic 528 a 6-x 2 
it has been thought that stereometry must have been men- 
tioned after γεωμετρίαν, but the latter by itself could have 
been meant to include both plane and solid geometry (cf. 
Non Posse Suaviter Vivi 1093 pv and Moralia vii, p. 113, 
11-14 [Bernardakis] =vii, p. 90, 11-14 [Sandbach]; Proclus, 
In Primum Euclidis El. Lib., p. 39, 8-10 [Friedlein]). 
¢ With this use of μέγεθος for extension in a single plane 


38 


oo » © 





PLATONIC QUESTIONS πὶ, 1001-1002 


troduces as a result of abstraction or lopping away 
of body when in the order of studies he leads down 4 
from arithmetic to geometry and then after this ὃ to 
astronomy and crowns all with the theory of har- 
mony, for the objects of geometry are the result 
when quantity has taken on extension,° the solids 
when extension has taken on depth, the objects of 
astronomy when solid body has taken on motion, 
and the objects of harmonics when sound has been 
added to the body in motion. Hence by abstracting 
sound from the things in motion and motion from the 
solids and depth from the planes and extension from 
the quantities we shall arrive at the intelligible ideas 
themselves,? which do not differ from one another 
at all when conceived in respect of their singularity 
and unity.¢ For unity does not produce number un- 


ef. Sextus, Adv. Math. vii, 73 (=Gorgias, frag. B 3 [D.-K.}), 
where σῶμα, characterized as having three dimensions, is dis- 
tinguished from μέγεθος ; Aristotle, Metaphysics 1053 a 25- 
26, where the particular examples of μέγεθος are only μῆκος 
and πλάτος : and the definition of line as μέγεθος ἐφ᾽ ἕν 
διαστατόν (Proclus, Jn Primum Euclidis El. Lib., Ὁ. 97, 7-8 
[ Friedlein]). 

4 Cf. Albinus (L’pitome x, 5 [Louis] =p. 165, 14-17 [Her- 
mann]) for god like the point conceived κατ᾽ ἀφαίρεσιν (also 
Clement, Stromata v, xi, 71, 2-33; νι, xi, 90, 4). Plato did 
not say or imply that the ideas can be reached by such a pro- 
cedure, though Aristotle contended that those who posited 
the ideas did so by an invalid extension of the kind of abstrac- 
tion legitimately used in mathematics (Physics 193 Ὁ 35— 
194a7; cf. Cherniss, Aristotle's Criticism of Plato ..., pp. 
203-204). 

¢ Cf. [Plutarch], De Placitis 877 8= Dox. Graeci, p. 282, 
17-25 (ὁ yap νοῦς κατὰ μονάδα θεωρεῖται . . . τὰ yap εἴδη ταῦτα 
πάντα καὶ γένη κατὰ μονάδας εἰσί) ; Sextus, Adv. Math. x, 258 
(ἑκάστη ἰδέα κατ᾽ ἰδίαν μὲν λαμβανομένη ἕν εἶναι λέγεται .. .) 5 


and Theon Smyrnaeus, p. 100, 4-8 (Hiller). 
39 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1002) μὴ τῆς ἀπείρου δυάδος ἅψηται" ποιήσασα δὲ 
οὕτως ἀριθμόν, εἰς στιγμὰς εἶτα γραμμὰς ἐκ de? 
τούτων εἰς ἐπιφανείας καὶ βάθη καὶ σώματα 
πρόεισι καὶ σωμάτων ποιότητας ἐν πάθεσι γιγνο- 
μένων. ἔτι τῶν μὲν νοητῶν" ἕν κριτήριον ὁ νοῦς" 
καὶ γὰρ ἡ διάνοια νοῦς ἐστιν ἐν τοῖς μαθηματικοῖς 
ὥσπερ ev* κατόπτροις ἐμφαινομένων" τῶν νοητῶν. 
ἐπὶ δὲ τὴν τῶν σωμάτων γνῶσιν ὑπὸ πλήθους 
πέντε δυνάμεις καὶ διαφορὰς αἰσθητηρίων ἡ φύσις 
ἔδωκεν ἡμῖν" καὶ οὐ πάντα φωρᾶται ταύταις ἀ) 

Β ἐκφεύγει πολλὰ διὰ" μικρότητα τὴν αἴσθησιν. ἔτι, 
ὥσπερ" ἡμῶν ἑκάστου συνεστῶτος ἔκ τε τῆς" ψυ- 
χῆς καὶ τοῦ σώματος μικρόν ἐστι τὸ ἡγεμονικὸν 
καὶ νοερὸν ἐν πολλῷ τῷ τῆς σαρκὸς ὄγκῳ κεκρυμ- 


μι 


δὲ -omitted by B; three points superscript over δὲ -E. 


. σώματος -J. 3 τὸ μὲν νοητὸν -8΄. 

4 éy-omitted by B. 

5. B, E* (ἐμ superscript) ; ἐκφαινομένων -all other mss. 

6 εἰς -J 3 διὰ -all other mss. (g over erasure). 

7 μακρότητα -J, ΒΗ: μικρότητα -all other mss. (μι over 
erasure ~g). 

8. ἔτι, ὥσπερ -Wyttenbach; ἐν ᾧ καίπερ -MSS.3 ἐν @ καὶ 
ὥσπερ -Nogarola. τῆς χάρη δ by B. 


« Cf. De An. Proc. in Timaeo 1012 Ἐ and De Defectu Orar. 
428 r—429 Bp; Aristotle, Metaphysics 1081 a 14-15, 1088 ἢ 
28-35, and 1091 a 4-5. For the further derivation of points, 
lines, ete. which follows cf. Theophrastus, Metaphysics 6 4 
23-8 5; Alexander Polyhistor in Diogenes Laertius, viii, 25 ; 
Sextus, Adv. Math. Xs 276-283 and Pyrrh. Hyp, iii, 153-154. 

ὑ Cf. ποιότητα καὶ χρῶσιν .. . ἐν πεντάδι (Nicomachus in 
lamblichus, Theolog. Arith., Ὁ. 74, 11-12 [De Falco}) and πε- 
ποιωμένῳ δὲ σώματι πεμπτάς (Proclus In Platonis Timaeum 
iii, p. 382, 15 and ii, p. 270, 8 [Dieh]}). 

eS Quaest. Conviv. 718 Ἐ (πᾶσι μὲν οὖν τοῖς καλουμένοις 
μαθήμασιν ὥσπερ . . κατόπτροις ἐμφαίνεται τῆς τῶν νοητῶν 
ἀληθείας ἴχνη καὶ eiBashe) s ; Syrianus, Aetaph., p. 82, 22-25; 


40 





PLATONIC QUESTIONS 111, 1002 


less it comes into contact with the unlimited dyad ; 
and, when it has thus produced number, it passes 
on into points and then lines and from these into 
surfaces and depths and bodies and qualitics ὃ of 
bodies in process of modification. Moreover, of the 
intelligibles there is a single criterion, the intelli- 
gence, for thought too is intelligence concerning the 
intelligibles that are reflected in the mathematical 
objects as in mirrors.° For the cognition of bodies, 
however, nature, impelled by their multiplicity, gave 
us five faculties and distinctive sense-organs ; and 
these do not detect all bodies, but many by reason 
of their minuteness elude sense-perception. More- 
over, just as in each of us, whose constituent parts 
are soul and body, the ruling and intellectual faculty 
is small, buried in the mass of flesh which is large,@ 
Proclus, In Primum Euclidis El. Lib., Ὁ. 4, 18-24 and p. 11, 
5-7 (friedlein) ; Anon. Proleg. to Platonic Philosophy viii, 
11-12 (p. 37 [Westerink] =Platonis Dialogi vi, p. 214, 1 
(Hermann]); Scholia in Rem Publicam 509 p (vi, p. 350, 30 
and p. 351, 2 [Hermann]). This notion that the objects of 
διάνοια are images of the ideas in the highest segment of the 
line still persists (cf. A. Wedberg, Plato’s Philosophy of 
Mathematics {Stockholm, 1955], p. 105), although Plato 
never says this but asserts rather that, while διάνοια employs 
as likenesses sensible figures in the third segment, its objects 
in this procedure are the idea of the square or the idea of the 
diagonal, which are νοητὰ μετὰ ἀρχῆς (Republic 510 pv 5— 
511 a 1 and 511 pv 2; cf. P. Shorey, Plato’s Republic ii 

{.C.L.], Ὁ. 116, note 6 and p. 206, note a). 
¢ ‘The souls that rise from the body after death, ἀχλύν τινα 
καὶ ζόφον ὥσπερ πηλὸν ἀποσειομένους (De Genio Socratis 591 
"). are said to be τὸν ὄγκον εὐσταλεῖς (De Sera Numinis 
lindicta 564 a, cf. Non Posse Suaviter Vivi 1105 p). Cf. 
...€ls τὸν ὄγκον τὸν παχὺν τοῦτον εἰσκρίνονται (Proclus, Jn 
Platonis Timaeum, iii, p. 297, 23-24 [Diehl]) ; ὁ δῆμος πλέον 
ἢ ὁ ἄρχων, Kat TO σῶμα πλέον ἢ ἡ ψυχή (Maximus of Tyre, 
Philos. vii, τὶ ἃ =p. 77, 10-11 [Hobein]); and what Plutarch 
41 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1002) μένον, οὕτως εἰκὸς ἔχειν ἐν τῷ παντὶ τὸ νοητὸν 
πρὸς τὸ αἰσθητόν." καὶ γὰρ ἄρχει τὰ νοητὰ τῶν 
σωματικῶν, ἀρχῆς δὲ πάσης πλέον τὸ ἐξ αὐτῆς καὶ 
μεῖζον. 

2. IIpos δὲ τοὐναντίον εἴποι τις ἂν πρῶτον ὅτι 
συγκρίνοντες (τὰ αἰσθητὰ τοῖς νοητοῖς τρόπον 
τινὰ τὰ θνητὰ τοῖς θείοις" ἐξισοῦμεν: ὁ γὰρ θεὸς 
ἐν τοῖς νοητοῖς. ἔπειτα πανταχοῦ δήπου τὸ 
περιεχόμενον ἔλαττόν ἐστι τοῦ περιέχοντος, ἡ δὲ 

C τοῦ παντὸς φύσις τῷ νοητῷ περιέχει τὸ αἰσθητόν" 
ὁ γὰρ θεὸς τὴν ψυχὴν εἰς τὸ μέσον θεὶς διὰ παντός 
τ᾽ ἔτεινε καὶ ἔτι ἔξωθεν" τὰ σώματα! αὐτῇ περιε- 
κάλυψεν, ἔστι δ᾽ ἀόρατος ἡ ψυχὴ καὶ πάσαις ταῖς 
αἰσθήσεσιν ἀναίσθητος ὡς ἐν τοῖς Νόμοις εἴρηται. 
διὸ καὶ φθαρτὸς ἡμῶν εἷς ἕκαστός ἐστιν, ὁ δὲ 

παντὶ τὸ αἰσθητὸν καὶ τὸ νοητόν -J, 

ὅτι -omitted by J, gz. 3 «τὰν μμἐὴ ἐὰν by Stephanus. 

θείοις -Stephanus ; θεοῖς -X, J, 8, €, Π : νοητοῖς -E, 1}. 

ἔτι ἔξωθεν -Hubert (cf. Timaeus 84. Β 4); ἐπέξωθεν -X, ; 


Ei, By Ἐπ ἔξωθεν -J, δ. 
8 τὸ σῶμα -Timaueus 34 Β 4. 


a ὦ Ὁ = 


a eee _—————— es 


says of the ἡγεμονικόν Rabe a to the Stoics (De Comm. 
Not. 1084 B). 

4 Kor the argument from microcosm to macrocosm cf. 
Plato, Philebus 29 a—30 a. 

> Cf. Sextus, Adv. Math. Χ, 251-253. 

¢ See 1003 εκ infra (τῆς μὲν ἀρχῆς ἐγγυτέρω τὸ ἔλαττον) and 
cf. De Comm. Not. 1077 κ-8 and Quaest. Conviv. 636 κ-ἰ : 
Aristotle, De Gen. Animal. 788 a 13-17 ; De Caelo 271 Ὁ 11- 
13; De Motu Animal. 701 b 24-28. 

4 See De An. Proc. in Timaeo 1016 B, where god is identi- 
fied with τῶν νοητῶν . . . τοῦ ἀρίστου of Timaeus 37 a 1 (cf, 
however, for the meaning of νοητῶν in this phrase of Plato’s 
Cherniss, Aristotle’s Criticism of Plato . .., p. 605 and 
Gnomon, xxv [1953], p. 372, n. 1). 


42 





PLATONIC QUESTIONS ru, 1002 


such in the sum of things is likely to be the relation 
of the intelligible to the perceptible. For in fact 
the intelligibles are principles of the corporeals,? 
and every principle is exceeded in number and size 
by that which comes from it.° 

2. To the contrary, however, one might say first 
that in comparing <the) perceptibles with the in- 
telligibles we are in a way putting mortal things on 
a level with the divine, for god is among the intel- 
ligible entities.¢ In the second place, what is en- 
compassed is in all cases surely less than that which 
encompasses ; and the nature of the sum of things 
encompasses the perceptible with the intelligible,¢ 
for god, having placed the soul in the middle, 
stretched it out through everything and further en- 
veloped the bodies with it on the outside,’ and the 
soul is invisible and imperceptible to all the senses, 
as has been said in the Laws.9 That is also why 
each one of us is subject to destruction but the 

ε Cf. Proclus, In Platonis Rem Publicam i, p. 289, 6-18 
(Kroll). 

7 Timaeus 34 B 3-4 (where διὰ παντός means through all 
the body of the universe, referred to by αὐτοῦ which Plutarch 
omits after εἰς τὸ μένον: as he changes τὸ σῶμα in Β 4 to τὰ 
σώματα [cf. 34 κα 2]); cf. De An. Proc. in Timaeo 1023 a 
infra. 

9 Laws 898 κε 1-2, where ἀναίσθητον πάσαις τοῦ σώματος 
αἰσθήσεσι is followed by νοητὸν δ᾽ εἶναι (for the meaning of 
which cf. Gnomon, xxv [1953], p. 372, ἢ. 1). The possible 
influence of this passage upon Plutarch’s treatment of the 
soul as ‘*‘ intelligible ’’ and upon the doxographical statements 
that Plato held the soul to be οὐσία νοητή ({Plutarch], De 
Placitis 898 ¢ = Dox. Graeci, p. 386 a 16; ef. p. 386 t 5 [Theo- 
doretus and Nemesius]) is overlooked by H. Dorrie, who 
asserts ‘‘ Niemals bezeichnet Platon die Seele als vonrov...” 
(Porphyrios’ “ Symmikta Zetemata”’ {Miinchen, 1959], p. 
187). 

43 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1002) κόσμος οὐ φθαρησόμενος" ἡμῶν μὲν γὰρ ἑκάστου" 
τὴν ζωτικὴν δύναμιν ἐντὸς περιέχει τὸ νητοει- 
δὲς καὶ διαλυτόν, ἐν δὲ τῷ κόσμῳ τοὐναντίον ὑπὸ 


τῆς κυριωτέρας ἀρχῆς" καὶ κατὰ ταὐτὰ ὡσαύτως 
ἐχούσης ἀεὶ σῴζεται τὸ σωματικὸν ἐν μέσῳ περι- 
ἐχόμενον. καὶ μὴν ἀμερές γεῖ λέγεται καὶ ἀμέ- 
ριστον τὸ μὲν σῶμα μικρότητι, τὸ δ᾽ ἀσώματον 
D καὶ νοητὸν ὡς ἁπλοῦν καὶ εἰλικρινὲς καὶ καθαρὸν 
ἁπάσης ἑτερότητος" καὶ διαφορᾶς. καὶ ἄλλως εὖ- 
ηθές ἐστι τοῖς σωματικοῖς τεκμαίρεσθαι περὶ τῶν 
ἀσωμάτων. τὸ γοῦν νῦν ἀμερὲς μὲν καλεῖται 
καὶ ἀμέριστον ἅμα δὲ πανταχοῦ ἐνέστηκε καὶ 
οὐδὲν αὐτοῦ" τῆς οἰκουμένης μέρος" ἔρημόν ἐστιν, 
ἀλλὰ καὶ πάθη πάντα καὶ πράξεις φθοραί τε 
πᾶσαι καὶ γενέσεις at’ ὑπὸ τὸν κόσμον" ἐν τῷ 
νῦν περιέχονται. κριτήριον δὲ τοῦ νοητοῦ" μόνον 
>? \ ¢ ~ e \ + \ ε bd \ 
ἐστὶν 6 νοῦς, ws φωτὸς dys, διὰ ἁπλότητα καὶ 
1 ἑκάστου -Stephanus ; ἕκαστος -MSS. ; ἑκάστῳ -Nogarola ; 
ἑκάστοις -Bernardakis. 
* ἀρχῆς -omitted by J, g. 
τε -J ; omitted by g. | : 
* ἑτερότητος -Apelt (Philologus, hxii [ 1903}, p. 287) 9 OTE- 
ρεότητος -MSS. 
αὐτοῦ -X, EF, B, €, ll 3 τι ~J, £. 
μέρος faces ie by g. 
αἱ -l, B; Kat “A, J £; Es nN. 
TOU κόσμου -΄, κ΄ (τ κοσμ “Be 
9 ποῦ νοητοῦ -with these words begin ds ‘Ay B, Bonon. 
C 3635, Voss. 16, Escorial T-11-5 (see app. crit. 999 c supra 


[title}]) ; also the first words on folio 606 recto of KF, where 
above them stands erased the title: ΛΘ πλατωνικὰ ζητή- 


ματα ὧν οὐχ εὑρέθη ἡ ἀρχή. 


our ὦῷ. oO 














¢ This reason why the universe will never Hie de eo ed is 
not that which is given in the Timaeus (41 4 7-3 6; cf. Plu- 
tarch, Quaest. Conviv. 720 B[6 θεὸς ... ἐποίησε καὶ ποιεῖ καὶ 


44. 


PLATONIC QUESTIONS 111, 1002 


universe is not going to be destroyed, for in our case 
what is subject to mortality and dissolution encom- 
passes the vital force that each one has within, 
whereas in the universe on the contrary what is cor- 
poreal is for ever preserved by the more sovereign 
and invariably identical principle, in the middle of 
which it is encompassed. Moreover, body is said 
to be without parts and indivisible because of 
minuteness but the incorporeal and_ intelligible 
because of its simplicity and purity and freedom 
from all diversity and difference.? And, besides, it 
is silly to judge of things incorporeal from things 
corporeal. At any rate, the now, while it is said to 
be without parts and indivisible,’ is present every- 
where simultaneously,? and no part of the whole 
world is devoid of it; but all incidents and actions, 
all cessations and commencements of being under 
heaven ὁ are encompassed in the now. It is because 
of the simplicity and similarity of the intelligible, 
however, that its sole criterion is the intelligence as 


φυλάττει διὰ παντὸς . .. τὸν Kdapov]) but may be an inference 
drawn from Timaeus 36 ¥ 2-5. 

δ ‘This is meant as a reply to the argument in 1001 p supra 
(ἡ yap ἀμέριστος οὐσία . . . εἰς βραχὺ συνηγμένη καὶ καθαρόν 

..)3 οὐ De An. Proc. in Timaeo 1022 & (chap. 91 init.). For 

the combination ἑτερότης καὶ διαφορά cf. De Virtute Morali 
446 πὶ (cited by Apelt); De An. Proc. in Timaeo 1015 Ἐ-Ὲ, 
1026 a andc; De Comm. Not. 1083 ©; Numa xvii, ὃ (71 c). 

¢ Cf. Aristotle, Physics 233 b 33—234 a 24 and Plutarch’s 
criticism of the Stoics, De Comm. Not. 1081 c. | 

@ Cf. Plato, Parmenides 131 B 3-5 (... ἡμέρα pia καὶ ἡ αὐτὴ 
οὖσα πολλαχοῦ ἅμα ἐστὶ ...}): Aristotle, Physics 218 Ὁ 13 and 
220 b 5-6 (ὁ χρόνος .. . καὶ ὁ αὐτὸς δὲ πανταχοῦ ἅμα). 

¢ Uf. ὑπὸ τὸν οὐρανόν in Timaeus 28 c 7-p 1; and for 
κόσμος in this sense ef. Isocrates, Panegyricus 179; Poly- 
bius, xii, 25, 7 (Timaeus); Sextus, Adv. Math. x, 174-175. 


45 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


/ \ \ \ \ 
(1002) ὁμοιότητα" τὰ δὲ σώματα, πολλὰς διαφορὰς ἔ- 
A 3 / ¥ ; 
χοντα καὶ ἀνομοιότητας, ἄλλα ἄλλοις κριτηρίοις 
σ > ’ ἔχ’ ’ 3 A A 
E ὥσπερ ὀργάνοις ἁλίσκεσθαι πέφυκεν. ἀλλὰ μὴν 
οὐδὲ τῆς" ἐν ἡμῖν νοητῆς καὶ νοερᾶς δυνάμεως 
A ᾽ “ A Ἁ > ᾿ / 
καταφρονοῦσιν ὀρθῶς" πολλὴ yap οὖσα Kat μεγάλη 
περίεστι παντὸς τοῦ αἰσθητοῦ καὶ μέχρι τῶν θείων 
ἐξικνεῖται. τὸ δὲ μέγιστον αὐτὸς ἐν Συμποσίῳ 
διδάσκων πῶς δεῖ" τοῖς ἐρωτικοῖς χρῆσθαι, μετ- 
ἄγοντα τὴν ψυχὴν ἀπὸ τῶν αἰσθητῶν καλῶν" ἐπὶ 
τὰ νοητά, παρεγγυᾷ μήτε σώματός τινος μήτ᾽ 
9 , NE ένα , , m_ ΒΗ 
ἐπιτηδεύματος μήτ᾽ ἐπιστήμης κάλλει μιᾶς" ὑπο- 
τετάχθαι καὶ δουλεύειν, ἀλλ᾽ ἀποστάντα τῆς περὶ 
ταῦτα μικρολογίας ἐπὶ τὸ πολὺ τοῦ καλοῦ πέλα- 
γος τρέπεσθαι. 


ZHTHMA A’ 
Te δήποτε," τὴν ψυχὴν ἀεὶ πρεσβυτέραν ἀποφαί- 
“- ~ 2 ’ ’ 
νων τοῦ σώματος αἰτίαν τε τῆς ἐκείνου γενέσεως 


| ἄλλοις ἄλλα -J (corrected by J*), g, Bonon. C 3635, Voss. 
16, Escorial T-11-5. 

τῆς -omitted by J, g. 

δὴ -a', ε- 

καλῶν -omitted by J (added in margin - ἢ), g. 

μηδεμιᾶς -Escorial T-11-5. 

δ τίδήποτε -with these words begin γ, Tolet. 51, 5 (ef. 

Class. Quart., xxi [1927], p. 167), Laurent. 80, 5 and 80, 22. 


aon Ὁ @ wy 











4 This answers the argument in 1002 a supra (ἔτι τῶν μὲν 
νοητῶν ἕν κριτήριον . . .); and, as the subsequent words show, 
διὰ ἁπλότητα Kat ὁμοιότητα refers to the homogeneity of the 
intelligible (cf. Adv. Colotem 1114. Ὁ [. . . ὁμοιότητι πρὸς αὑτὸ 
καὶ τῷ μὴ δέχεσθαι διαφορὰν . . .|) and not to a similarity of 
intelligence and intelligible or of vision and light. 

> The νοῦς is the νοερὰ δύναμις in us (cf. 1002 B supra: τὸ 


46 





PLATONIC QUESTIONS i11-1v, 1002 


that of light is vision *; but, since bodies have many 
differences and dissimilarities, different ones are 
naturally apprehended by different criteria, as it 
were by different instruments. But furthermore it 
is not right of them to be disdainful even of the in- 
telligible and intellectual faculty ὃ in us men, for 
because it is ample and stout it transcends all that 
is perceptible and reaches as far as things divine.¢ 
The most important point, however, is that, when 
in the Symposium4@ Plato explains how one must 
manage the matter of love by diverting the soul 
from the beautiful objects that are perceptible to 
those that are intelligible, his own injunction is 
not to subjugate oneself and play the slave to the 
beauty of a particular body or practice or of a single 
science but to desist from petty concern about these 
things and turn to the vast sea of the beautiful. ¢ 


QUESTION IV 


Wuyever, when he declares that the soul is always 
senior to the body and the cause and origin of the 


ἡγεμονικὸν Kat νοερόν), and Plutarch thinks that he has the 
authority of Plato for treating this itself as a νοητόν (see note 
g on 1002 c supra). There is therefore no reason to read into 
this passage the distinction between νοητή and νοερά for 
which it is cited by H. Dorrie (Porphyrios’ ‘* Symmikta 
Zetemata,” p. 189, n. 5). 

¢ Cf. Philo Jud., De Opificio Mundi 70-71 (i, pp. 23, 18-24, 
1 [Cohn]) and R. M. Jones, Class. Phil., xxi(1926), pp. 101 ff. 

¢ Symposium 210 Ὁ. 

¢ Plutarch conveniently cuts short his paraphrase of the 
passage, for the end and purpose of the whole progress in 
the Symposiuni is the ἐπιστήμη pia of the idea of beauty (210 
p6-—211 p 1; cf. Albinus, Epitome v, 5 {[Louis]=p. 157, 
14-18 [Hermann] and x, 6 { Louis] =p. 165, 24-29 [Hermann)]). 


47 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1002), 

Ff Καὶ ἀρχήν, πάλιν φησὶν οὐκ ἂν γενέσθαι ψυχὴν 
ἄνευ “σώματος οὐδὲ νοῦν ἄνευ ψυχῆς ἀλλὰ ψυχὴν 
μὲν ev" σώματι νοῦν δ᾽ ἐν τῇ ψυχῇ; δόξει γὰρ τὸ 
σῶμα καὶ εἶναι καὶ μὴ εἶναι, συνυπάρχον ἅμα τῇ 
ψυχῇ καὶ γεννώμενον ὑπὸ τῆς ψυχῆς. 

1008 “H? τὸ πολλάκις ὑφ᾽ ἡμῶν λεγόμενον ἀληθές 
ἐστιν; ἡ μὲν γὰρ ἄνους ψυχὴ καὶ τὸ ἄμορφον 
σῶμα συνυπῆρχον᾽ ἀλλήλοις ἀεὶ καὶ οὐδέτερον 
αὐτῶν γένεσιν ἔσχεν οὐδ᾽ ἀρχήν: ἐπεὶ δὲ ἡ ψυχὴ 
νοῦ μετέλαβε καὶ ἁρμονίας καὶ γενομένη διὰ OU 
φωνίας ἐμῴρων' μεταβολῆς αἰτία γέγονε" TH ὕλῃ 
καὶ κρατήσασα, ταῖς αὑτῆς" κινήσεσι τὰς ἐκείνης" 
ἐπεσπάσατο καὶ ἐπέστρεψεν, οὕτω τὸ σῶμα τοῦ 

1 ἐν -omitted by J}, g. 
2 ἦ -a. 
συνυπάρχοντα (τα superscript over ον) -J!; συνυπάρχον 
-Voss. 16 ; συνυπάρχουσιν -Escorial T-11-5. 
. ἔμφρον “J. 
5. αἰτία “γέγονε -omitted by J}, g. 
: κρατήσας αὐταῖς ταῖς -J}, g. 
ἐκείνας -Escorial T-11-5. 
ἐπέστρεψαν -J. 


5 Plato, Timaeus 34 8 10—35 a 1 and Laws 896 a ὅ- 8 
(with 892 a 2-c 6); see De An. Proc. in Timaeo 1013 Ἐ-Ὲ 
and 1016 a-8 (where Timaeus 34 8 10—35 a 1 is quoted). 

> Timaeus 30 B 3-5 (of. Albinus, 1 pitome xiv, 4 [Louis] = =p; 
170, 2-3 [Hermann]: ἴσως οὐχ οἵου τε ὄντος νοῦ ἄνευ ψυχῆς 
independ Here as elsewhere Plato does say that νοῦς can- 
not exist apart from ψυχή (Timaeus 46 τὸ 5-6, Sophist 249 a 
4-8, Philebus 30 c 9-10; cf. Cherniss, Aristotle's Criticism of 
Plato ..., pp. 606-607) but neither here nor anywhere that 
soul cannot exist without body. This is simply a false infer- 
ence from the statement that the demiurge did put soul into 
the body of the universe. 

¢ See note c on De Comm. Not. 1075 τ infra. 

@ With what follows cf. Qurstion II, 2 (1001 B-c) supra and 
De An. Proc. in Timaeo 1014 Β-Ὲ and 1017 a-s. In those 


48 


eo a 


PLATONIC QUESTIONS iv, 1002-1003 


latter's generation,* does he again say that soul could 
not have come to be without body or intelligence 
without soul either,? but soul in body and intelligence 
in soul? For it would seem that the body both 
exists and does not exist if it is at once coexistent 
with the soul and being generated by the soul. 

Or ¢ is that right which we frequently assert ? 4 
For soul without intelligence ὁ and amorphous body ἢ 
were always coexistent with each other, and neither 
of them had generation or origin; but, when the 
soul had partaken of intelligence and concord 9 and, 
grown rational through consonance, had become a 
cause of change for matter and had attracted and 
converted the motions of the latter” by having 
dominated them with its own motions,’ this is the 
passages god or the demiurge, who is not mentioned in the 
present Question, is the subject of statements which, here have 
for subject instead soul, 7.e. intelligent soul; but this latter 


according to 1001 c supra is not merely the work of god but 
also a part of him. 

ὁ Cf. Timaeus 44 a 8: κατ᾽ ἀρχάς τε ἄνους ψυχὴ γίγνεται, 
said, however, of the particular human soul when it enters the 
body. 

f ore 50 p 7 and 51 a 7 (see De An. Proc. in Timaeo 
1014 Ὁ [τὸ τὴν ὕλην ἀεὶ μὲν ἄμορφον καὶ ἀσχημάτιστον ὑπ᾽ αὐτοῦ 
λέγεσθαι . . .] and cf. Timaeus Locrus 94 4 [ἄμορφον δὲ καθ᾽ 
αὑτὰν καὶ ἀσχημάτιστον)]). 

9 See note a on 100] ὁ supra. 

% According to Plutarch’s own doctrine these could be 
only motions induced by disorderly soul not yet grown 
rational, for amorphous matter of itself would be δυνάμεως 
οἰκείας ἔρημον, ἀργὸν ἐξ αὑτοῦ, ἄμοιρος αἰτίας ἁπάσης (De An. 
Proc. in Timaeo 1014 r—1015 a, οὐ 1015 τ). 

* See the similar language used of the effect of νοῦς on 
ψυχή in De An. Proc. in Timaeo 1094. Ὁ : ἐγγενόμενος δὲ τῇ 
ψυχῇ καὶ κρατήσας εἰς ἑαυτὸν ἐπιστρέφει. . . (ef. ‘Thévenaz, 
L’ Ame du Monde, pp. 71-72); and cf. Timaeus 42 ¢ 4-ὸ 2 
with Cornford’s note ad loc. (Plato’s Cosmology, p. 144, n. 2). 


49 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1003) κόσμου γένεσιν ἔσχεν ὑπὸ τῆς ψυχῆς, καὶ κατα- 
σχηματιζόμενον καὶ συνομοιούμενον. οὐ γὰρ ἐξ αὑ- 


τῆς ἡ ψυχὴ τὴν τοῦ σώματος ἐδημιούργει φύσιν 


οὐδ᾽ ἐκ τοῦ μὴ ὄντος, ἀλλ᾽ ἐκ σώματος ἀτάκτου 
καὶ ἀσχηματίστου σῶμα τεταγμένον ἀπειργά- 
σατο καὶ πειθήνιον." ὥσπερ οὖν, εἰ φαίη τις ἀεὶ 
τὴν τοῦ σπέρματος" δύναμιν εἶναι μετὰ σώμα- 
τος" γεγονέναι μέντοι τὸ σῶμα τῆς συκῆς ἢ τῆς" 
ἐλαίας ὑ ὑπὸ σπέρματος, οὐδὲν ἐ ἐρεῖ διάφωνον" (αὐτὸ 
γὰρ τὸ σῶμα, κινήσεως αὐτῷ καὶ μεταβολῆς ὑπὸ 
τοῦ σπέρματος ἐγγενομένης, ἔφυ τοιοῦτο καὶ δι- 
εβλάστησεν) οὕτως ἡ ἄμορφος ὕλη καὶ ἀόριστος 
ὑπὸ τῆς ψυχῆς" ἐνούσης" σχηματισθεῖσα μορφὴν 
ἔσχε τοιαύτην καὶ διάθεσιν. 


ZHTHMA Μ΄ 


. Διὰ τί, τῶν μὲν εὐθυγράμμων τῶν δὲ κυκλι- 
κῶν σωμάτων καὶ σχημάτων ὄ ὄντων, τὰς τῶν εὐθυ- 
γράμμων"" ἀρχὰς" ᾿ ἔλαβε τὸ ἰσοσκελὲς τρίγωνον 

C καὶ τὸ σκαληνόν, ὧν τὸ μὲν τὸν κύβον συνέστησε 
γῆς στοιχεῖον ὄντα τὸ δὲ σκαληνὸν τήν τε πυρα- 
μίδα καὶ τὸ ὀκτάεδρον καὶ τὸ εἰκοσάεδρον, τὸ μὲν 


ἀπεργάσατο “XK. 
καὶ πειθήνιον ἀπειργάσατο -E}. 
σώματος -Ὑ: 
μετὰ τοῦ σώματος -Voss. 16, Escorial T-11-5. 
ἢ ~omitted by g. 
καὶ -Escorial = 11-5. 
διαφέρειν -J*3 διαφέρον -g (€pov over erasure); Siddopov 
(op superscript over wv) -B}. 
ὑπὸ τῆς νη: -omitted by X. 

9. ἐνούσας -Escorial T-11-5. 

τῶν δὲ κυκλικῶν . .. τῶν εὐθυγράμμων -Omitted by 4}, g. 


ἀρχὴν -J?, δ. 


J nao αὶ, ὦ ἢ »" 


10 
va 


50 





PLATONIC QUESTIONS τνον, 1003 


way in which the body of the universe got generated 
by the soul, in being fashioned by it and assimilated. 
For it was not out of itself that the soul fabricated 
the nature of body or out of what is non-existent 
either, but out of disorderly * and shapeless body it 
produced a well-ordered and disciplined ὃ one. There- 
fore, just as there would be nothing inconsistent in 
the assertion if one should say that the potency of 
the seed is always associated with body and yet the 
body of the fig or the olive has come to be by the 
agency of seed (for the body itself had such and 
such a growth and germination because by the 
agency of the seed motion and change arose in it °), 
so the amorphous and indefinite matter got such and 
such a shape and disposition when it was fashioned 
by the soul existing within it. 


QUESTION V 


1. Some bodies and figures being rectilinear and 
others circular,? what was his reason for taking as 
the principles of the rectilinear figures the isosceles 
triangle and the scalene, the former of which pro- 
duced the cube as element of earth while the scalene 
produced the pyramid and the octahedron and the 


» Cf. Quaest. Conviv. 720 B (ἡ μὲν ὕλη τῶν ὑποκειμένων 
ἀτακτότατόν ἐστι... .) and De An. Proc. in Timaeo 1024 a-p 
(οὔτε yap τὸ μὐνϑ εν» εἰλήχει τάξεως -. .). 

δ Cf. De An. Proc. in Timaeo 1029 Ἑ for the word, there 
applied to the soul; but for the notion here cf. Timaeus 48 4 
2-5 and 56 c 5-6. 

¢ Cf. [Plutarch], De Placitis 905 a = Dox. Graeci, p. 417 a 
2-5. 

4 Cf. Plato, Parmenides 137 pv 8-£ 6 and 145 B 3-5; 
Aristotle, De Caelo 286 b 13-16; Proclus, Jn Primum 
Euclidis El. Iib., p. 144, 10-18 (Friedlein). 


51 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1003) πυρὸς σπέρμα τὸ δ᾽ ἀέρος τὸ δὲ ὕδατος γενόμενον, 
τὸ δὲ τῶν κυκλικῶν᾽ ὅλως παρῆκε, καίτοι μνησθεὶς 
τοῦ σφαιροειδοῦς ἐν οἷς φησι τῶν κατηριθμημένων 
σχημάτων ἕκαστον σώματος περιφεροῦς εἰς ἴσα 
διανεμητικὸν εἶναι; 

Πότερον, ὡς ὑπονοοῦσιν ἔνιοι, τὸ δωδεκάεδρον 
τῷ σφαιροειδεῖ προσένειμεν, εἰπὼν ὅτι τούτῳ" 
πρὸς τὴν τοῦ παντὸς ὁ θεὸς κατεχρήσατο φύσιν 
ἐκεῖνο διαζῳγραφῶν; καὶ γὰρ μάλιστα τῷ πλήθει 
τῶν στοιχείων ἀμβλύτητι δὲ τῶν γωνιῶν τὴν 

D εὐθύτητα Staduyov* εὐκαμπές ἐστι, καὶ TH περι- 
τάσει καθάπερ at δωδεκάσκυτοι σφαῖραι κυκλο- 
τερὲς γίγνεται καὶ περιληπτικόν"" ἔχει γὰρ εἴκοσι 
γωνίας στερεάς, ὧν ἑκάστην ἐπίπεδοι περιέχουσιν 
ἀμβλεῖαι τρεῖς" ἑκάστη γὰρ ὀρθῆς ἐστι καὶ πέμπτου 
μορίου": συνήρμοσται δὲ καὶ συμπέπηγεν ἐκ δώδεκα 
πενταγώνων" ἱπργομμάῃθ καὶ ἰσοπλεύρων, ὧν ἕκα- 

1 κύκλων -Escorial T-11-5. 


2 ἕτεροι (νι superscript over τε) Ξξ. 3. τοῦτο -Voss. 16. 
* διέφυγεν -J1, 23 διαφυγῶν -Voss. 16}. 
© παραληπτικόν -J+, g. § πανταγώνων -J}. 


4 Timaeus 53 ὁ 4—55 ὁ 4 and 55 "ἢ 7—56 B 6. For Plu- 
tarch’s use of γῆς στοιχεῖον and πυρὸς σπέρμα in these lines 
cf. Timaeus 56 8B 5 (στοιχεῖον. καὶ σπέρμα) with Cornford’s 
note (Plato’s Cosmology, p. 223, .n. 1). 

ὁ Aristotle (De Caelo 286 Ὁ 27-33) interprets this as sup- 
porting evidence for his thesis that the sphere is the primary 
solid figure. 

¢ Timaeus 55 a 3-4. Plato’s words there are ὅλου περιφε- 
pots διανεμητικὸν εἰς ἴσα μέρη καὶ ὅμοια, and ὅλου περιφεροῦς 
means “ the whole circumference ”’ of the sphere in which the 
tetrahedron is inscribed. At this point in the Jimueus only 
this, ‘‘ the simplest solid figure,” has been constructed, though 
what is said of its division of the sphere in which it is inscribed 
is undoubtedly meant to apply also to the four regular solids 
mentioned immediately thereafter. 


52 





PLATONIC QUESTIONS v, 1003 


icosahedron, which became the seed of fire and of 
air and of water respectively,¢ but for disregarding 
altogether the question of the circular figures,’ even 
though he did mention the spherical in the passage 
where he says ¢ that each of the figures enumerated 
has the property of dividing into equal parts an en- 
circling body ? 

Did he, as some surmise, associate the dodeca- 
hedron with what is spherical,? since he said ¢ that 
god employed the former for the nature of the sum 
of things in tracing the design of this ? For, furthest 
withdrawn from straightness by the multitude of its 
elements 7 and obtuseness of its angles, it is flexible 
and like the balls that are made of twelve pieces of 
leather 9 by being distended becomes circular and 
circumscriptive,” for it has twenty solid angles each 
of which is contained by three plane angles that are 
obtuse, since each consists of a right angle and a 
fifth; and it has been assembled and constructed 
out of twelve equiangular and equilateral pentagons,’ 


¢ Cf. “ Timaeus Locrus”’ 98 πὶ (τὸ δὲ δωδεκάεδρον εἰκόνα 
τῶ παντὸς ἐστάσατο, ἔγγιστα σφαίρας ἐόν) and Philoponus, De 
Aeternitate Mundi xiii, 18 (pp. 536, 27-537, 2 [Rabe]). 

¢ Timaeus 55 c 4-6, more accurately quoted by Plutarch 
in De Defectu Orac. 430 5. 

Cf. De Defectu Orac. 427 B (μέγιστον δὲ καὶ πολυμερέ- 
στατον TO δωδεκάεδρον) : and for στοιχεῖον AS here used (the 
ultimate constituent triangles) cf. Timaeus 54 Ὁ 6-7, 55 a 8, 
55 B 3-4, and 57 c 9. 

9 Cf. Plato, Phaedo 110 B 5-7 and Proclus, Jn Platonis 
Timaeumi iii, Ὁ. 141, 19-24 (Diehl). 

Cf. De Defectu Orac. 428 pv (ἡ δὲ τοῦ δωδεκαέδρου φύσις 
περιληπτικὴ τῶν ἄλλων σχημάτων οὖσα... 

* Cf. Euclid, Hlements xiii, Prop. 18, Lemma (iv, p. 340, 
6-7 [Heiberg]}). 
i Cf. Euclid, Elements xi, Def. 28. 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1003) στον' ἐκ τριάκοντα τῶν πρώτων σκαληνῶν τρι- 
γώνων συνέστηκε" διὸ καὶ δοκεῖ τὸν ζῳδιακὸν 
ἅμα καὶ τὸν ἐνιαυτὸν ἀπομιμεῖσθαι ταῖς διανομαῖς 
τῶν μοιρῶν" ἰσαρίθμοις οὔσαις .ἡ 

ῷ, Ἢ πρότερόν ἐστι κατὰ φύσιν τὸ εὐθὺ τοῦ 
περιφεροῦς, μᾶλλον δὲ ὅλως πάθος τι τῆς εὐθείας 
E ἡ περιφερής; κάμπτεσθαι “γὰρ λέγεται τὸ ὀρθὸν 
καὶ ὁ κύκλος γράφεται κέντρῳ καὶ διαστήματι: 
τοῦτο δ᾽ ἐστὶν εὐθείας τόπος," ὑφ᾽ ἧς καὶ μετρεῖται: 
τὸ γὰρ" περιέχον ἐκ τοῦ μέσου πανταχόθεν ἴσον 
ἀφέστηκε. γεννᾶται δὲ καὶ κῶνος καὶ κύλινδρος 
ἀπ᾽ εὐθυγράμμων, ὁ μὲν τριγώνου περὶ" μίαν 
πλευρὰν μένουσαν τῇ ἑτέρᾳ πλευρᾷ καὶ τῇ βάσει 
περιενεχθέντος ὁ δὲ κύλινδρος παραλληλογράμμου 
ταὐτὸ τοῦτο παθόντος. ἔτι τῆς μὲν ἀρχῆς ἐγ- 
γυτέρω τὸ ἔλαττον, ἐλαχίστη δὲ πασῶν" ἡ εὐθεῖα: 
τῆς γὰρ περιφεροῦς τὸ μὲν LETT ἐστι κοῖλον 


. ἕκαστος -Escorial T-11-5'. * μυρίων -J, σ΄. 

3 οὕτως -FEscorial T-11-5. 3 τύπος -X, € Ii. 

5 γὰρ -omitted by J+, g. § περὶ -omitted by g. 

7 πεκονδότος -Escorial T-11-5 

8 ἔτι -Leonicus; ἔστι -Escorial T-11-5; ἐπεὶ -all other 
ne 9 παθῶν -X, a, A}, β' 96.ἢ 

10 «ἐντός» -added here by Bernardakis (. .. κοῖλον {τὸ 


ἐντὸς» -Leonicus). 


α This is erroneous (cf. Heath, Manual, pp. 177-178), and 
Plutarch seems to make Ammonius call attention to the fact 
in De Defectu Orac, 428 A (. . . τὸ τοῦ καλουμένου δωδεκαέδρου 
στοιχεῖον ἄλλο ποιοῦσιν, οὐκ ἐκεῖνο τὸ σκαληνὸν ἐξ οὗ τὴν 
πυραμίδα καὶ τὸ ὀκτάεδρον καὶ τὸ εἰκοσάεδρον ὁ Πλάτων 
συνίστησιν). Albinus in his Epitome xiii, 2 (p. 77 [Louis] = 
pp. 168, 37-169, 2 [Hermann]}) says that each of the twelve 
pentagons is divided into five triangles and each of these 
consists of six triangles, but it should be observed that he 
does not state what kind of triangles these are. 

> Neither Plutarch here nor Albinus in his Hp:tome xiii, 2 


54 





PLATONIC QUESTIONS v, 1003 


each of which consists of thirty of the primary scalene 
triangles,* and this is why it seems to represent at 
once the zodiac and the year in that the divisions 
into parts are equal in number.? 

2. Or is the straight naturally prior to the cir- 
cular ὁ or rather the circular line simply a modifica- 
tion of the straight line? For we do speak of the 
bending of what is straight ὁ and the circle is de- 
scribed by a centre and a distance, this latter being 
the location of a straight line by which it is measured 
as well,¢ for what contains the circle is at all points 
equally removed from the middle. Also, both cone 
and cylinder are generated by rectilinear figures, the 
former when one side and the base of a triangle are 
rotated about the other side, which remains fixed, 
and the cylinder when this same thing happens to a 
parallelogram.f Moreover, what is lesser is nearer 
to the principle 7; but the straight line is the least 
of all lines,” for the circular line has its <interior) 
(pp. 75-77 [Louis] =pp. 168, 34-169, 3 [Hermann]}) refers to 
any relation between the zodiac and the dodecahedron other 
than the numerical similarity that both of them (and the year) 
consist of twelve parts, each of which consists of thirty parts. 

¢ Cf. Proclus, In Primum Euclidis El. Lib., pp. 106, 20- 
107, 10 (Friedlein). 

4 Cf. Aristotle, De Incessu Animal. 708 Ὁ 22-24 and 
Meteorology 386 a 1-7. 

¢ Cf. Euclid, Hlements i, Post. 3 and A tpeie 4 Primum 
Euclidis El. Lib. Ρ. 185, 22-25 ((Friedlein) : - . διάστημα δὲ 
ἡ εὐθεῖα. ὅση γὰρ ἂν αὕτη τυγχάνῃ τοσοῦτο ἔσται τὸ ἀπόστημα 
τοῦ κέντρου πρὸς πάντα τὰ μέρη τῆς περιφερείας. 

7 Cf. Euclid, Hlements xi, Defs. 18 and 21. 

9 See 1002 B supra and note c there. 

» Cf. Archimedes, Opera Omnia iterum ed. J. L. Heiberg, 
i, p. 8, 3-43 Proclus, In Primum Euclidis El. Lib., Ὁ. 110, 
10-26 (Friedlein) ; Theon Smyrnaeus, pp. 111, 22-112. 1 
(Hiller). 

55 


(1003) 


F 


1004 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


κυρτὸν δὲ TO ἐκτός. ἔτι τῶν σχημάτων οἱ 
ἀριθμοὶ πρότεροι, καὶ γὰρ 7 μονὰς τῆς στιγμῆς" 
ἐστι γὰρ ἡ στιγμὴ μονὰς ἐν θέσει." καὶ μὴν ἡ 
μονὰς τρίγωνός ἐστι πᾶς yap τρίγωνος ἀριθμὸς 
ὀκτάκις γενόμενος καὶ μονάδα προσλαβὼν γίγνε- 
ται τετράγωνος" τοῦτο δὲ καὶ" τῇ μονάδι συμ- 
βέβηκε". πρότερον οὖν τοῦ κύκλου τὸ τρίγωνον" εἰ 
δὲ τοῦτο, καὶ εὐθεῖα τῆς περιφεροῦς. ἔτι τὸ στοι- 
χεῖον eis’ οὐδὲν διαιρεῖται τῶν συνισταμένων ἐξ 
αὐτοῦ, τοῖς δ᾽ ἄλλοις" εἰς τὸ στοιχεῖον ἡ διάλυ- 
σις. εἴ τοίνυν τὸ μὲν τρίγωνον εἰς οὐδὲν περιφε- 
ρὲς διαλύεται, τὸν δὲ κύκλον εἰς τέσσαρα" τρίγωνα 

1 +6 -omitted by J}, g. 

2 ἐνθέτως ~J}. 
3 καὶ -omitted by J}, g. 
* μονάδι ov ci δ θοῆς -ὃ.. 


ὡς -J, £. 
§ τοὺς δὲ ἄλλους -J!, δ΄. 
1 Alt δ. igs ΩΣ ε 
ETL “J, Ῥ. εἰς τα τέτταρα -ξ. 











2 Cf. Proclus, ln Primum Euclidis El. Lib., p. 106, 24-25 
{Friedlein) ; [Aristotle], Mechanica 847 Ὁ 23—848 a 3. 

> Cf. Hero Alexandrinus, Def. a’ (iv, p. 14, 13-19 [Hei- 
berg]); Theon Smyrnaeus, p. 111, 14-16 (Hiller) ; Proclus, 
In Primum Euclidis El. Lib., p. 95, 21-26 (Friedlein) ; 
Aristotle, Topics 108 b 26-31 and Metaphysics 1016 b 24-31 
with Cherniss, Aristotle’s Criticism of Plato ..., pp. 131-132 
and note 322 on p. 397. Contrast 1002 a supra, where unity 
is said to produce numbers and then to pass on into points, 
lines, and figures. 

¢ The unit, being the «ἀρχή of number and not itself ἃ 
number, is usually called “΄ potentially triangular,” 3 being the 
first triangular number as in De An. Proc. in Timaéo 1020 Ὁ 
(Theon Smyrnaeus, p. 33, 5-7 and p. 37, 15-19 [Hiller]; 
Nicomachus, Arithmetica Introductio, pp. 88, 23-89, 5 
{Hoche]; Iamblichus, In Nicomachi Arithmeticam Intro- 
ductionem, p. 62, 2-5 [Pistelli]). For triangular numbers ef. 


56 








PLATONIC QUESTIONS v, 1003-1004 


concave and its exterior convex. Moreover, 
numbers are prior to figures, for the unit is itself 
prior to the point because the point is a unit in 
position.” Now, the unit is triangular, for every 
triangular number multiplied by eight and with 
addition of a unit becomes a square number, and 
this is characteristic of the unit also.°. The triangle, 
then, is prior to the circle 4; and, if so, the straight 
line too is prior to the circular. Moreover, the 
element is divided into none of the things that are 
compounded out of it, whereas the other things are 
subject to resolution into the element. If, then, the 
triangle is resolved into nothing that is circular, 
whereas the two diameters of the circle divide it into 


Quaest. Conviv, 744 B (where 3 and 6 are the examples) ; 
Theon Smyrnaeus, p. 33, pp. 37, 7-38, 14, and p. 41, 3-8 
(Hiller); Nicomachus, Arithmetica Introductio II, viii (pp. 


87, 22-89, 16 [Hoche]). The algebraic formula is παι 


and 1 conforms to this, being half of the product of itself and 
2. The proposition that any triangular number multiplied 
by 8 becomes a square number when 1 is added is repeated by 
Iamblichus (In Nicomachi Arithmeticam Introductionem, 
p. 90, 18-19 [Pistelli]) but is not by him explicitly applied to 
the unit (cf, Heath, History i, p. 84 and ii, pp. 516-517 ; M.R. 
Cohen and I. E. Drabkin, 4 Source Book in Greek Science 
[New York, 1948], p. 9, n. 2). 

4 This does not follow, for not only is the unit “ square ”’ as 
well as “ triangular’ (De E' 391 a, De Defectu Orac. 429 τ ; 
Nicomachus, dArithmetica Introductio, Ὁ. 91, 4-5 [Hoche] ; 
Iamblichus, Jn Nicomachi Arithmeticam Introductionem, 
p. 60, 3-5 and p. 75, 11-13 [Pistelli]) but even its being tri- 
angular does not prove the triangle to be a unit prior to the 
circle, which can itself be regarded as analogous to the unit 
(Aristotle, De Caelo 286 Ὁ 33—287 a 2; Iamblichus, op. cit., 
p. 61, 6-24 and pp. 94, 27-95, 2 [Pistelli] ; Proclus, Jn Primum 
Euclidis El. Lib., pp. 146, 24-147, 5 and pp. 151, 20-152, 5 
[Friedlein]). 


3 


57 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1004) τέμνουσιν at δύο διάμετροι, πρότερον av τῇ φύσει 
καὶ στοιχειωδέστερον εἴη τοῦ κυκλικοῦ τὸ εὐθύ- 
γραμμον. ὅτι τοίνυν προηγούμενον μέν ἐστι τὸ 
εὐθύγραμμον" τὸ δὲ κυκλικὸν ἐπιγιγνόμενον" καὶ 
συμβεβηκὸς αὐτὸς ὁ Ἰ]λάτων ἐνεδείξατο: τὴν γὰρ 
γῆν ἐκ κύβων συστησάμενος, ὧν ἕκαστον" εὐθύ- 
γραμμοι" περιέχουσιν ἐπιφάνειαι,͵ σφαιροειδὲς αὐ- 
τῆς γεγονέναι τὸ σχῆμά" φησι καὶ στρογγύλον. 
ὥστ᾽ οὐδὲν ἔδει ποιεῖν τῶν περιφερῶν ἴδιον στοι- 
χεῖον, εἰ καὶ τοῖς εὐθυγράμμοις πρὸς ἀλληλά πως 
συναρμοττομένοις" ὁ σχηματισμὸς οὗτος ἐπιγίγνε- 
σθαι πέφυκεν. 

Β 8. Ἔτι, εὐθεῖα" μὲν ἢ τε μείζων ἥ τε pLKpo- 
τέρα τὴν αὐτὴν εὐθύτητα διατηρεῖ, τὰς δὲ τῶν 
κύκλων περιφερείας, ἂν ὦσι σμικρότεραι, καμπυ 
λωτέρας"" καὶ σφιγγομένας τῇ κυρτότητι μᾶλλον 
ὁρῶμεν, av δὲ μείζους, ἀνειμένας: ἱστάμενοι γοῦν 
κατὰ τὴν κυρτὴν περιφέρειαν οἱ μὲν κατὰ σημεῖον 





1 κύκλου -J}, δ. 

2 ὅτι τοίνυν. .. τὸ εὐθύγραμμον -omitted by a g£, Escorial 
T-11-5}. 

3 κυκλικόν ἐστι γινόμενον -J 
“Escorial T-11-5. 
* γῆν -omitted by J}, g. 
ἕκαστος -J', δ : ἕκαστοι -€. 
εὐθύγραμμον -J, Ε: Voss. 16. 7 ἐπιφαίνεται -J, ΕΒ. 
τὸ σχῆμα γεγονέναι -Escorial T-11-5. 
συναρμοττόμενος -J, g, Voss. 16], 
ἔστι yap εὐθεῖα -J, g. 11 καμπυλοτέρας -B, e. 


1 A \ 3 ἢ 
. 8; κυκλικὸν ἐπιγενόμενον 


ῳοῳω ὦ ὥ ὧν 


@ Since the bases of the triangles into which the circle is 
divided remain arcs of a circle, the conclusion here drawn 


58 





PLATONIC QUESTIONS v, 1004 


four triangles, the rectilinear would be naturally prior 
to the circular and more elementary than it.4 
Furthermore, that the rectilinear is antecedent and 
the circular supervenient and incidental was in- 
dicated by Plato himself, for after making the earth 
consist of cubes,’? each of which is contained by 
rectilinear surfaces, he says that the shape of it has 
turned out to be spherical or round.* Consequently 
there was no need to postulate an element peculiar 
to circuiar figures if this configuration does naturally 
supervene upon rectilinears conjoined with one an- 
other in a particular way. 

3. Moreover, while a straight line, whatever its 
length, keeps the same straightness throughout, we 
see that the circumferences of circles are more 
curved, that is are more highly concentrated in their 
convexity, if they are smaller, and more relaxed, if 
they are larger.¢ At any rate, when set up on their 
convex circumference, some circles touch the under- 


does not follow from the argument, with which cf. Nico- 
machus, <Arithmetica Introductio II, vii, 4 (p. 87, 7-19 
[Hoche]) and Simplicius, De Caelo, pp. 613, 30-614, 10 on 
Aristotle, De Caelo 303 a 31-b 1. 

> Timaeus 55 Ὁ 8—56 a 1. 

¢ Despite φησι this is not a quotation. In fact, in the 
Timaeus after 55 Ὁ 8—56 a 1 the sphericity of the earth is 
referred to only by implication in 62 p 12—63 a 3 (cf. Corn- 
ford, Plato’s Cosmology, p. 263, notes 1 and 2 with Phaedo 
108 x 4—109 a 7 and 110 b 5-7). Misguided attempts have 
been made to deny that even these passages refer to the 
earth’s sphericity (cf. Lustrum, IV [1959], Nos. 660-661 and 
V [1960], Nos. 1464 and 1465). 

¢ Cf. John Wallis, A Treatise of Angular Sections (Lon- 
don, 1684), p. 90: ‘. .. the lesser circumference is more 
crooked. For it hath as much of curvity in a shorter length. 
And therefore .. . it is more crooked intensively.” 


59 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


¢ \ A \ ¢ A Φ / 
(1004) ot δὲ κατὰ γραμμὴν ἅπτονται τῶν ὑποκειμένων 
ἐπιπέδων: ὥσθ᾽ ὑπονοήσειεν ἄν τις εὐθείας κατὰ 
μικρὰ πολλὰς συντιθεμένας" τὴν περιφερῆ γραμμὴν 
ἀποτελεῖν. 
4. Ὅρα δὲ μὴ τῶν μὲν" ἐνταῦθα κυκλικῶν καὶ 
- > 4 > > ? > at re / 
σφαιροειδῶν οὐδέν ἐστιν ἀπηκριβωμένον ἀλλ᾽ ἐντά- 
ce καὶ περιτάσει τῶν εὐθυγράμμων ἢ μικρότητι 
C τῶν μορίων τῆς διαφορᾶς λανθανούσης ἐπιφαίνεται 
τὸ στρογγύλον καὶ κυκλοειδές, ὅθεν οὐδὲ κινεῖται 
7 ~ 9 ~ / > / OA > > 
φύσει τῶν ἐνταῦθα σωμάτων ἐγκυκλίως οὐδὲν ἀλλ 
ρῶς. > / “ ‘ SP \ > 
em εὐθείας ἅπαντα" τὸ δ᾽ ὄντως σφαιροειδὲς οὐκ 
ἔστιν αἰσθητοῦ σώματος ἀλλὰ τῆς ψυχῆς καὶ τοῦ 
νοῦ στοιχεῖον, οἷς καὶ τὴν κυκλοφορητικὴν᾽ κίνη- 
σιν ὡς προσήκουσαν κατὰ φύσιν ἀποδίδωσιν. 


1 συντεθειμένας -F'scoria} T-11-5. 

2 μὲν -J4, g, Voss. 16, Bonon., Escorial T-11-5 ; omitted 
by all other mss. 

3 ἐντάσει -E, B, n, Escorial T-11-5; ἐνστάσει -all other 
MSS. 

4 κυκλοφορικὴν -E, B, n : κυκλοφορητικὸν -Escorial T-11-5. 


¢ This in fact has nothing to do with the preceding state- 
ment, for a circle however large will never touch the plane 
at a line unless both are material, and then it will do so 
however smal] it is (cf. Aristotle, Metaphysics 997 b 35— 
998 ἃ 4 and Alexander, Metaph., p. 200, 15-21). It does not 
then support the subsequent conclusion either, to which 
Plutarch himself should not have subscribed anyway, for he 
held that the curvature of a circle is uniform (cf. De Facie 
932 r and Class. Phil., xlvi [1951], p. 144). 

> Cf. Proclus, In Primum Euclidis El. Lib., p. 54, 11-13 


60 


PLATONIC QUESTIONS v, 1004 


lying planes at a point and others at a line. Con- 
sequently one might surmise that many straight 
lines when put together bit by bit produce the 


circular line. 

4. Consider too that none of the circular or 
spherical things in this world is exactly perfect ὃ but 
there is a superficial appearance of roundness and 
circularity, the difference being unnoticed because 
of the tension and distension of the rectilinears or 
the minuteness of their parts, this being the reason 
why none of the bodies in this world moves naturally 
in a circle either but all move in a straight line, 
whereas the really spherical is an element not of 
perceptible body but of soul and intelligence,’ to 
which he assigns as naturally befitting them circular 
motion as well.¢ 


(I*riedlein) ; [Plato], Epistle vii, 343 a 5-9; and Plato, 
Philebus 62 a 7-2 9. 

¢ Cf. Atticus, frag. vi (Baudry) = Eusebius, Praep. Evang. 
xv, 8, 7 (ii, p. 367, 13-18 [Mras]); Proclus, In Primum 
Luclidis El. Lib., Ὁ. 82, 7-12 and pp. 147, 22-148, 4 (Fried- 
lein). In calling the spherical, of which the natural motion is 
circular (cf. De E 390 a), τῆς ψυχῆς . . . στοιχεῖον, however, 
Plutarch seems to be perilously close to the identification of 
soul with the Aristotelian πέμπτη οὐσία κυκλοφορητική (cf. 
Cherniss, Arstotle’s Criticism of Plato ..., pp. 601-602; P. 
Moraux, R,-E. xxiv [1963], cols. 1248, 37-1251, 7). Even 

“ἢ materialists ’ like the Atomists and Chrysippus had 
assigned the spherical to soul (cf. Aristotle, De Anima 404 
a | 9 and 405 a 8-13; S.V.F. ii, frag. 815). 

@ Plato, Timaeus 94, A 1-4, 36 τ 2—37 c 8, 47 B 5-c 4 ἊΣ 
Laws 898 a 3-8 8 (cf. Cherniss, Aristotle's Criticism of Plato 

., pp. 404-405) ; ef. De An. Proc. in Timaeo 1024 c-p. 


61 


(1004) 


D 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


ZHTHMA ς΄ 


ὥς ποτ΄ ἐν τῷ αἰδρῳ λέγεται τὸ τὴν Too 
I] a: * Φαίδρῳ λέ > TY 
πτεροῦ φύσιν, ὑφ᾽ ἧς ἄνω TO ἐμβριθὲς ἀνάγεται," 
κεκοινωνηκέναι μάλιστα τῶν περὶ τὸ σῶμα τοῦ 
θείου ;* 

Πότερον ὅτι περὶ ἔρωτος ὁ λόγος ἐστί, κάλλους 
δὲ τοῦ περὶ τὸ σῶμα ὁ ἔρως, τὸ δὲ κάλλος ὁμοιό- 
THTL τῇ πρὸς τὰ θεῖα κινεῖ καὶ ἀναμιμνήσκει τὴν 
ψυχήν; ἰῇ μᾶλλον. οὐδὲν περιεργαστέον ἀλλὰ ἁπλῶς 
ἀκουστέον ὅτι, τῶν “περὶ τὸ σῶμα τῆς ψυχῆς δυνά- 
μεων πλειόνων" οὐσῶν, ἡ λογιστικὴ" καὶ διανο- 
ἡτικὴ μάλιστα τοῦ θείου κεκοινώνηκεν, ἣν τῶν 
θείων καὶ οὐρανίων ἔφησεν; ἣν οὐκ ἀπὸ τρόπου 
πτερὸν προσηγόρευσεν, ὡς τὴν ψυχὴν ἀπὸ τῶν 
ταπεινῶν καὶ θνητῶν ἀναφέρουσαν. 


ZHTHMA Z’ 


aA / € 4 A 3 U 
Πῶς ποτέ φησιν ὁ Πλάτων τὴν ἀντιπερίστα- 
σιν τῆς κινήσεως διὰ τὸ μηδαμοῦ κενὸν ὑπάρχειν 


1 τῷ -omitted by 4, g. 
2 τοῦ -omitted by Escorial T-11-5 (ἡ πτεροῦ δύναμις - Plato, 
aie 246 ἢ 6). 
ὁ ἄγεται -J1, αὶ (ἄγειν ἄνω -Plato, Phaedrus 246 0 6; but 
for ἀνάγειν ἄνω cf. Republic 533 pv 2-3). 
4 θείου -Kaltwasser (cf. 1004 p infra and Phaedrus 246 
D 8); θεοῦ -Μ88. 
5 πλειόνων -omitted by J}. 
® λογιστικὴ -Ziegler (2-H. xxi/i [1951], col. 748, 4); δια- 
λογιστικὴ -MSS. 
7 ἔφυσεν -Escorial T-11-5. 


@ Plato, Phaedrus 246 1 6-8. 

δ Cf. Phaedrus 249 ἢ 4-—251 a ἢ and 254 8 5-7; Plutarch, 
Amatorius 765 B, bp, F and 766 a, πον; Plotinus, nn. vi, 
vii, 22, lines 3-19. 


62 


PLATONIC QUESTIONS vi-vu, 1004 


QUESTION VI 


In what sense is it asserted in the Phaedrus@ that 
the pinion’s nature, by which what is heavy is raised 
on high, is among things of the body most closely 
akin to the divine ? 

Is it because the subject of the discourse is love 
and beauty of the body is the object of love and 
beauty by its similarity to things divine stirs the 
soul and makes it remember??® Or should one 
rather not labour the point at all but understand 
quite simply that, while there are a good many 
faculties of the soul concerned with the body,° the 
faculty of reason or thought, whose objects he has 
said are things divine and celestial, is most closely 
akin to the divine ?¢ This faculty he not inappro- 
priately called a pinion because it bears the soul 
up ὁ and away from the things that are base and 
mortal. 


QUESTION VII 


1. In what sense does Plato say’ that, because 
there is void nowhere, the cyclical replacement 5 of 


¢ Cf. the interpretation given by Hermias, Jn Platonis 
Phaedrum, p. 133, 25-30 (Couvreur). 

4 Cf. Phaedo 80 » 1-3 and 84 4 7-3 4; Symposium 211 £ 
3—212 a 2 with Phaedrus 247 ς 6-8, 248 B 7-c 2, and 249 ¢ 
4-6 and Republic 611 © 1-5; and also Philebus 62 a 7-8 for 
the ideas, the objects of reason or intelligence, as θεῖα. 

¢ Cf. An Seni Respublica Gerenda Sit 786 Ὁ. 

7 Timaeus 79 © 10—80 ς 8. 

9 The process is not called ἀντιπερίστασις by Plato, but 
Aristotle called it this (Physics 215 a 14-15 and 267 a 15-20 
[cf. Simplicius, Phys., p. 668, 32-34; p. 1350, 31-36; and 
p. 1351, 28-29]) as well as περίωσις (Parva Naturalia 472 
b 6). 


63 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1004) αἰτίαν εἶναι τῶν περὶ τὰς ἰατρικὰς σικύας" παθη- 
μάτων" καὶ τῶν περὶ τὴν κατάποσιν" καὶ τὰ ῥι- 
E πτούμενα βάρη καὶ τὰ τῶν ὑδάτων ῥεύματα καὶ 
΄ 
κεραυνοὺς τήν τε φαινομένην πρὸς ἤλεκτρα καὶ τὴν 
/ A ¢€ / 5 ¢ \ / ~A / 
λίθον τὴν “HpakdAciay ὁλκὴν τάς τε τῶν φθόγ- 
γων συμφωνίας ;" δόξει γὰρ ἀτόπως αἰτίαν (μίαν) 
παμπόλλων καὶ “ἀνομοίων. γένεσιν ἐπάγειν" παθῶν. 
2. Τὸ μὲν γὰρ περὶ τὴν ἀναπνοὴν ὡς γίγνεται 
τῇ ἀντιπεριστάσει τοῦ ἀέρος αὐτὸς" ἱκανῶς ἀποδέ- 
δειχε τὰ δὲ λοιπὰ πάντα φήσας θαυματουργεῖσθαι 
τῷ κενὸν," εἶναι μηδὲν περιωθεῖν θ᾽ αὑτὰ ταῦτ᾽ 
3 yw \ / \ \ e ~ e 
ets ἄλληλα Kai διαμείβεσθαι πρὸς τὰς αὑτῶν ἕδρας 
ἰόντα, τὴν καθ᾽ ἕκαστον ἐξεργασίαν ἡμῖν ἀφῆκε. 
8. Πρῶτον μὲν οὖν τὸ περὶ τὴν σικύαν᾽" τοιοῦ- 
,ὔ ? ε \ ες: 9 9 α΄ 12 A a 
Tov ἐστιν" ὁ περιληφθεὶς ὑπ᾽ αὐτῆς" πρὸς TH σαρ- 
F xu μετὰ θερμότητος ἀὴρ ἐκπυρωθεὶς καὶ γενόμενος 
3 σικήας “a, 8. 
4 μαθημάτων -], 
κατάστασιν -(}ἶἷ, 2. 

4 βάρη -X, J, 8. εν Ὦ : μέρη -all other Mss. 

5 Hubert τὴν λίθον τὴν Ἡράκλειον -Eseorial] ‘T-11-5; 
τὸν λίθον τὸν late -Voss. 16) Ἡράκλειον -all other mss. 

§ συμφθονίας -J?. 

7 «μίαν» -added by Fahse (implied by versions of Ainyot 
and Xylander) ; μίαν instead of αἰτίαν -Schellens (after Wyt- 
tenbach) ; αἰτίαν (aivi over erasure -a D παμπόλλων -MSS. 

8 ἐπάγειν -Turnebus, Xylander : ὑπάγειν -Mss. 

® αὐτοῦ -J, &- d 

10 H. C.3 καὶ τῷ κενὸν -Bernardakis; τε καὶ (ἰ.6. θαυμα- 
τουργεῖσθαί τε καὶ εἶναι) -MSS. 

11 σικήαν - ἶ, g. 

12 αὐτοῦ -", g. 


[2 





α It was Plato’s express purpose to banish ry from 
physical theory (Timaeus 80 c 2-3; cf. Cherniss, Arestotle’s 
Criticism of Plato .. ., n. 306 on p. 387 sub finem). This 
point is missed entirely in “ἢ Timaeus Locrus ” 101 p—102 a, 


64 





PLATONIC QUESTIONS vu, 100. 


motion is the cause of what happens in the case of 
medical cupping-instruments and in that of swallow- 
ing and of weights that are thrown and of flowing 
waters and of thunderbolts and of the apparent 
attraction * to amber and the loadstone and of the 
consonances of sounds ? For he would seem in extra- 
ordinary fashion to be proposing a <single) cause as 
the source of numerous and dissimilar occurrences. 
2. For, while in the case of respiration he has 
given an adequate exposition himself " of the way in 
which it comes about by the cyclical replacement of 
the air, for all the rest, after saying that these ap- 
parent wonders are produced because there is no 
void and these objects push themselves around into 
one another and interchange in going to their own 
positions,° he left it to us to work out the particulars. 
3. Well then, in the first place, the case of the 
cupping-instrument is like this. The air, which along 
with heat it has enclosed next to the flesh, having 
become fiery and finer in texture than the pores of 


where respiration occurs ἑλκομένω τῶ ἀέρος ἀντὶ τῶ ἀπορ- 
ῥέοντος, the cupping-instrument ἀπαναλωθέντος ὑπὸ τῶ 
πυρὸς τῶ ἀέρος ἐφέλκεται τὸ ὑγρόν (cf. Hero Alexandrinus, 
Pneumatica, Prooem., p. 16, 10-16 [Schmidt]), and amber 
ἀναλαμβάνει TO ὅμοιον σῶμα. 

Ὁ Timaeus 79 a 5-E 9. CF. Albinus, Epitome xxi (p. 107 
[Louis] =p. 175, 20-27 [Hermann]) and “* Timaeus Locrus ” 
101 p—102 a (see the last note supra) and the criticisms of the. 
exposition by Aristotle (Parva Naturalia 472 b 6-32) and by 
Galen (De Placitis Hippoc., et Plat. viii, 8=pp. 714, 14-720, 
16 [Mueller] and In Plat. Timaeum Comment. Frag. xvii- 
xix = pp. 22, 27-26, 2 ((Schréder]). 

¢ In this paraphrase of Timaeus 80 c 3-8 διακρινόμενα καὶ 
συγκρινόμενα (c 4-5) is omitted, an omission which affects 
the meaning of διαμειβόμενα in the original and obscures the 
connexion of the passage with Timaeus 58 B 6-c 2. 


65 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


aA al . A 
(1004) τῶν rod’ χαλκοῦ πόρων" ἀραιότερος ἐξέπεσεν 


1005 


2 ἢ \ , ἢ ἢ " εἰ ty ΑΝ ν νὴ 
οὐκ εἰς κενὴν χώραν (οὐ γὰρ ἔστιν) εἰς δὲ" τὸν 
a \ , 4 Ν 27 4 Rt ἢ 
περιεστῶτα τὴν σικύαν' ἔξωθεν ἀέρα, κἀκεῖνον ἀπ- 
, e A A \ e A \ - U 
ἔωσεν; ὁ δὲ τὸν πρὸ αὑτοῦ" καὶ τοῦτο πάσχων 
> \ \ μὰ ἃ ᾿ τ eo 
ἀεὶ καὶ δρῶν" ὁ ἔμπροσθεν ὑποχωρεῖ, τῆς κε- 
’ / ~ 
νουμένης γλιχόμενος χώρας ἣν ὁ πρῶτος ἐξέλιπεν᾽ 
Ὁ ~ 
οὕτω δὲ TH σαρκὶ περιπίπτων, ἧς ἡ σικύα᾽ δέ- 
t's , δ΄ , 1 oe ἢ 
δρακται, καὶ ἀναπιέζων" ἅμα" συνεκθλίβει τὸ ὑγρὸν 
εἰς τὴν σικύαν.᾽" 
Ἥ \ / ’ \ >? A / 
δὲ κατάποσις γίγνεται τὸν αὐτὸν τρόπον'᾽ 
αἱ γὰρ περὶ τὸ στόμα Kal” τὸν στόμαχον κοι- 
λότητες ἀέρος ἀεὶ πλήρεις εἰσίν. ὅταν οὖν ἐμ- 
~ aA Ly \ ~ 
πιεσθῇ TO σιτίον ὑπὸ τῆς γλώττης, ἅμα καὶ τῶν 
4 > / 5 , e 2 ἣ 4 
παρισθμίων ἐνταθέντων, ἐκθλιβόμενος ὁ ἀὴρ πρὸς 
~ ~ A 
τὸν οὐρανὸν" ἔχεται τοῦ ὑποχωροῦντος καὶ συν- 
επωθεῖ τὸ σιτίον. 
\ 
5. Ta δὲ ῥιπτούμενα βάρη τὸν ἀέρα σχίζει μετὰ 
πληγῆς ἐμπεσόντα'" καὶ διίστησιν: ὁ δὲ περιρ- 
~ > 15 
ρέων ὀπίσω τῷ" φύσιν ἔχειν ἀεὶ THY ἐρημουμένην 


τοῦ -omitted by J, £. 
πόρων ws -K 5 σωρῶν -J', g. 
οὐδὲ -ε. 

σικήαν -{", 


8 

δρῶν᾽ -W yttenbach ; ἄγων -MSS. 
neh np «ὁ δ᾽ ὄπισθεν emywpet> -Wyttenbach. 
σικῆα - 
pate: -E ‘mperius (Op. Philol., p. 340); ἀναξέων -J, 
x3 ἀναζέων -all other mss. 

" ἅμα -omitted by n. 

80 σικῆαν -J}, g. 

ἊΣ τὸ στόμα καὶ -omitted by J}, 

12 τὸν οὐρανὸν -Nogarola, Shep aids: a! (5); τὸ ἦκον -a’, 


or δ᾽ ὦ ὦ ὦ BS »" 





PLATONIC QUESTIONS vu, 1004-1005 


the bronze escapes not into empty space (for there 
isn't any) but into the air surrounding the cupping- 
instrument from without and pushes this air aside, 
as this air does that before itself ; and at every step 
thus acted upon and acting the air that is in front 
gives way, making for the vacated space which the 
first had left, and so, falling upon the circumference 
of the flesh gripped by the cupping-instrument and 
pressing it up, it simultaneously squeezes the liquid 
out into the cupping-instrument.* 

4. Swallowing occurs in the same way, for the 
cavities of the mouth and the oesophagus are always 
full of air. So, when the food is pressed in by the 
tongue, the fauces too having been stretched taut 
at the same time, the air, being squeezed out against 
the palate, follows closely upon that which gives 
way and helps to push the food on.” 

5. Weights that are thrown cleave the air and se- 
parate it because of the impact with which they have 
fallen upon it; and the air because of its nature 
always to seek out and fill up the space left empty 


« Asclepiades of Bithynia, who compared the mechanism 
of respiration with the action of cupping-instruments, must 
have explained the latter also by a kind of περίωσις without 
the intervention of ὁλκή ({Plutarch], De Placitis 903 Ἐ-Ὲ = 
Dox. Graeci, pp. 412, 31-413, 1; cf. R. A. Fritzsche, Rhein. 
Mus., N.F. lvii [1902], p. 384). 

» Cf. the view opposed by Galen (De Naturalibus Facul-_ 
tatibus iii, chap. 8=pp. 176-177 [Kiihn]) that in deglutition 
the food is merely pushed down from above without any 
ὁλκή. 

















n; τὸ εἶκον -all other mss. (τὸ omitted by Voss. 16, Escorial 
T-11-5). 
18. All mss. (pace Hubert); ἐκπεσόντα -Aldine, Basil. 
14 γὸ -J. * ἐρημωμένην 1, 
67 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


io / \ > A / A 5 
(1006) χώραν διώκειν καὶ ἀναπληροῦν συνέπεται τῷ ἀφ- 
4 1 \ 
ιεμένῳ᾽ τὴν κίνησιν συνεπιταχύνων .ἦ 
t 
e \ ~ - Vd ‘ ? \ ε, 
B 6. At δὲ τῶν κεραυνῶν πτώσεις καὶ αὐταὶ ρί- 
ΕΝ ὦ 3 “- A \ A 3 A 
yeow ἐοίκασιν: ἐκπηδᾷ yap ὑπὸ πληγῆς ἐν TO 
νέφει γενομένης τὸ πυρῶδες εἰς τὸν ἀέρα, κἀκεῖνος 
ἀντιρραγεὶς ὑποχωρεῖ καὶ πάλιν εἰς ταὐτὸ" συμπί- 
” ἢ Ἄ ͵ \ , 4 9 , 
πτων ἄνωθεν ἐξωθεῖ κάτω παρὰ Pvaw* ἀποβιαζό- 
μενος τὸν κεραυνόν. 
7. To δ᾽ ἤλεκτρον οὐδὲν ἕλκει τῶν παρακει- 
/ ef % \ ¢ “a ͵ 3 \ 
μένων ὥσπερ οὐδὲ ἡ σιδηρῖτις λίθος, οὐδὲ προσ- 
- ὔ > > ς A ~ / > \ € 
πηδᾷ TL τούτοις ἀφ᾽ αὑτοῦ τῶν πλησίον: ἀλλὰ ἡ 
\ , \ > 1 hn ΡΥ > a \ 
μὲν λίθος τινὰς ἀπορροὰς" ἐξίησιν ἐμβριθεῖς καὶ 
πνευματώδεις, αἷς ὁ συνεχὴς ἀναστελλόμενος ἀὴρ 
ὠθεῖ τὸν πρὸ αὑτοῦ: κἀκεῖνος ἐν κύκλῳ περιιὼν 
καὶ ὑπονοστῶν αὖθις ἐπὶ τὴν κενουμένην χώραν 
> / ‘ / A / \ 3 
Ο ἀποβιάζεται καὶ συνεφέλκεται τὸν σίδηρον. τὸ ὃ 





1 ἐφιεμένῳ - ἷ, g, Voss. 16, Escorial T-11-5. 
mf . ’ 
2 ἐπιταχύνων -E, B, Escorial T-11-5. 
8 > \ Κα | 
εἰς TavTa -τὦὁ, 2. 
παρὰ τὴν φύσιν -J', δ. 
8 708 ἤλεκτρον . - - συνεφέλκεται τὸν σίδηρον -omitted by ε- 
ὃ Bernardakis ; ἀπορροίας -MSS. 
7 ὑπὸ -Χ. 


4 


| 


¢ Cf. Simplicius, Phys., p. 668, 25-32 on Aristotle, Physics 
215 a 14-15 and the objections of Aristotle (Physics 207 a 
15-20) and of Philoponus (Phys., pp. 639, 12—641, 6). No- 
thing is said in the Timaeus of the acceleration to which 
Plutarch refers (cf. A. E. Taylor, 4 Commentary on Plato’s 
Timaeus, Ὁ. 572 on 80 a 1-2; F. Wehrli, Die Schule des 
Aristoteles, Heft v?, p. 63 on Strato, frag. 73). 

> Cf. Aristotle’s explanation of the downward motion of 
the thunderbolt contrary to its nature ( Meteorology 342 a 12- 
16 and 369 a 17-24). 

° i.e. τὴν λίθον τὴν “Hpaxreiay of 1004 E supra called ἡ 
σιδηρῖτις as here by Plutarch in De [side 376 w and Quaest. 


68 





PLATONIC QUESTIONS vir, 1005 


flows around behind and follows along with the object 
discharged, helping to accelerate its motion. 

6. The falling of thunderbolts itself also resembles 
the hurling of missiles, for the impact that has oc- 
curred in the cloud makes the fiery substance leap 
out into the air, and the latter gives way when it has 
been rent asunder and, falling back together again, 
expels the thunderbolt from above, forcing it back 
downwards contrary to its nature.? 

7. Amber does not attract any of the objects 
placed near it as the loadstone ὁ does not either, nor 
does any of the things in their neighbourhood spring 
to them of itself; but the loadstone emits certain 
effluvia which are heavy and like wind, and the con- 
tiguous air, forced back by these, pushes the air 
that is before itself, and that air, moving around in 
a circle and settling again upon the vacated space, 
forces the iron back and drags it along with itself.¢ 
Conviv. 641 c; cf. Plato, Jon 533 Ὁ 3-5 and Pliny, N.H. 
xxxvi, 127, 

¢ The similarity of the ancillary cause of the iron’s motion 
given by Lucretius (vi, 1022-1041) led R. A. Fritzsche to 
assume a common source and to identify this as Asclepiades 
of Bithynia, who is known to have denied the occurrence of 
ὁλκή in nature (Rhein. Mus., N.F. lvii [1902], pp. 369-373 and 
pp. 386-389) ; but cf. M. Bollack, Rev. Etudes Latines, xli 
(1963 [1964]), pp. 171-173 and pp. 183-184. Plutarch’s. 
συνεφέλκεται here and ἐφέλκεται in the next sentence are 
unfortunate expressions at least, for, although they refer to 
*“‘ traction ’’ by the air which is driven from behind and not 
to any “ attraction ’’ by the magnet or amber, they might be 
thought to compromise the denial of ὁλκή, the original prin- 
ciple of the theory (cf. οὐδὲν ἕλκει at the beginning of this 
paragraph), and to represent a contamination with the Epi- 
curean notions expressed by ducitur ex elementis (Lucretius, 


vi, 1012) and by συνεπισπᾶσθαι τὸν σίδηρον (Epicurus, frag. 
293 [Usener, Hpicurea, p. 208, 26-27)}). 


69 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


ms U \ “Ἃ / 
(1005) ἤλεκτρον ἔχει μέν te’ φλογοειδὲς ἢ πνευματικόν, 
3 /; ἃ “- 2 aA b Ἢ κι 
ἐκβάλλει δὲ τοῦτο τρίψει" τῆς ἐπιφανείας, τῶν 
> , 5 \ \ \ 
πόρων ἀναστομωθέντων᾽ τὸ δὲ ταὐτὸ μὲν ἐκπεσὸν 
aA A3 “- , ? / \ A ,ὔ 
ποιεῖ τῷ" τῆς σιδηρίτιδος, ἐφέλκεται δὲ τῶν πλησίον 
τὰ κουφότατα καὶ ξηρότατα διὰ λεπτότητα καὶ 
3 / > 4 > > 1 2Q> » / 

ἀσθένειαν: οὐ yap ἐστιν ἰσχυρὸν οὐδ᾽ ἔχει βάρος 
οὐδὲ ῥύμην πλῆθος ἀέρος ἐξῶσαι δυναμένην, ᾧ τῶν 
μειζόνων, ὥσπερ ἡ σιδηρῖτις, ἐπικρατήσει. πῶς οὖν 
Μ / 3 να φ 3Ἃ 3 ᾿ / x / 
οὔτε λίθον οὐτε ξύλον ὁ ἀὴρ ἀλλὰ μόνον τὸν σί- 
dnpov* ὠθεῖ καὶ προσστέλλει" πρὸς τὴν" λίθον; αὕ- 
τὴ δ' ἐστὶ μὲν ἀπορία κοινὴ πρός τε τοὺς" ὁλκῇ 
Τῆς. λίθου καὶ τοὺς" φορᾷ τοῦ σιδήρου τὴν σύμ- 
πῆξιν οἰομένους γίγνεσθαι τῶν σωμάτων, εἴη λύσις 
D δ᾽ ἂν οὕτως ὑπὸ τοῦ [ἰλάτωνος.᾽ ὁ σίδηρος οὐτ᾽ 
ἄγαν ἀραιός ἐστιν ὡς ξύλον οὔτ᾽ ἄγαν πυκνὸς ὡς 
4 n } 2\\> » / 4 ἢ 11 \ 
χρυσὸς ἢ λίθος ἀλλ ἔχει πόρους καὶ οἰμους"" καὶ 
τραχύτητας διὰ τὰς ἀνωμαλίας τῷ ἀέρι συμμέτρους, 
ὥστε μὴ ᾿ ἀπολισθαίνειν ἀλλὰ ἕδραις τισὶν ἐνισχό- 
μενον καὶ ἀντερείσεσι' ἡ περιπλοκὴν σύμμετρον ἐχού- 


- μέντοι ~A, Escorial T-11-5. 
τῇ τρίψει -Α", B, y, BF, "Ὁ, Voss. 16, Escorial T-11-5, 
Bonon. 3 +6 -J, g, Voss. 16. 


bn 


* τὸν σίδηρον μόνον -J, g. 

ἡ 3 προστέλλει -Μ88. 

6 Wyttenbach ; τὸν -Mss. 

7 τῇ -J, g. 

8 τῆς -Bernardalcis:: : τοῦ -MSS. 

9 τῇ -ἃ, 6. 

τ; ; σωμάτων εἰλυσπᾶν οὕτως ὑπὸ τοῦ ἸΙλάτωνος -X, 
ε. Ὡ: σωμάτων. .. νᾶ. 18 (erased)... ὁ σίδηρος -a3 σωμά- 
των . . « Vac. 4... ὁ σίδηρος (with ἰλυσπᾶν οὕτως ὑπὸ τοῦ 
Πλάτωνος added in . margin) -B; σωμάτων ... vac. 11 to 
16... 6 σίδηρος ~-A, E, B; between σωμάτων and ὁ σίδη- 


pos: Ἰλυαπᾶν -Voss. 16, καὶ ey -lscorial T-11-5, ἰλυσπᾶν 
(with οὕτως ὑπὸ τοῦ Πλάτωνος deleted) -Βοποη. : σωμάτων: ὁ 


τὸ 





PLATONIC QUESTIONS vir, 1005 


Amber contains a substance like flame or wind which 
it ejects when its pores have been opened by friction 
of its surface; and this substance, when it has 
escaped, has the same action as that from the load- 
stone has but because of its tenuousness and weak- 
ness drags along the lightest and driest of the things 
in the neighbourhood, for it is not strong and does 
not have weight or impetus capable of expelling an 
amount of air with which to master the larger objects 
as the loadstone does. How is it then that the air 
pushes and presses against the loadstone neither 
stone nor wood but only iron? This, to be sure, is a 
difficulty that confronts equally those who think that 
the cohesion of the bodies comes about by the load- 
stone’s attraction and those who think that it comes 
about by conveyance of the iron, but Plato might 
provide a solution in the following way. Iron is 
neither exceedingly loose in texture like wood nor 
exceedingly close like gold or stone but has pores 
and passages and corrugations which by reason of 
their irregularities conform to the air; and the 
result is for the air, however in its motion to the 
loadstone it may fall upon the iron, not to slip off 
but, intercepted by certain lodgements and counter- 


4 i.e. by the iron’s being “ carried’ or propelled to the | 
magnet as in Plutarch’s own explanation; φορᾷ does not 
here refer to any “ impulse ” of the iron itself, for such an 
explanation (as e.g. in Alexander, Quaestiones, p. 74, 24-30 
[Bruns]) would not be confronted by this difficulty. 











pai (without lacuna) ~J, 8. ὧν: εὐλητὸς δ᾽ ἂν οὕτως ὑπὸ 
(or μετὰ) τοῦ Πλάτωνος “Hubert ; ἐλύετο δ᾽ ἄν οὕτως ὑπὸ τοῦ 
Πλάτωνος -Bernardakis. 

11 X, 6, 13 οἴμας -all other mss. 

12 Diibner ; μήτε -Mss. 

18 ἀντερείσεσι καὶ -J, g. 


71 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


\ 3 \ A ἢ / «ἢ 
(1006) σαις, ὡς ἂν ἐμπέσῃ πρὸς τὴν λίθον φερόμενος, ἀπο- 
βιάζεσθαι καὶ προωθεῖν τὸν σίδηρον. τούτων μὲν 
οὖν τοιοῦτός τις" ἂν εἴη λόγος. 
ξεν 93 e / 

8. Ἣ δὲ τῶν" ἐπὶ γῆς ὑδάτων ῥύσις οὐχ ὁμοίως 
εὐσύνοπτον ἔχει τὸν τῆς ἀντιπεριώσεως τρόπον." 
ἀλλὰ χρὴ καταμανθάνειν τὰ λιμναῖα τῶν ὑδάτων 
ἀτρεμοῦντα καὶ μένοντα τῷ περικεχύσθαι καὶ συν- 

ΕΗ αγαγεῖν πανταχόθεν αὑτοῖς" ἀκίνητον ἀέρα, μηδα- 
μοῦ κενὴν ποιοῦντα χώραν. τὸ γοῦν ἐπιπολῆς 
ὕδωρ ἔν τε ταῖς λίμναις καὶ ἐν τοῖς πελάγεσι δο- 
νεῖται καὶ κυμαίνεται τοῦ ἀέρος σάλον λαμβάνον- 
τος" ἕπεται γὰρ εὐθὺς μεθισταμένῳ καὶ συναπορρεῖ" 
διὰ τὴν ἀνωμαλίαν" ἡ γὰρ κάτω πληγὴ τὴν κοιλό- 
τηταὰ ποιεῖ τοῦ κύματος ἡ δ᾽ ἄνω τὸν ὄγκον, ἄχριΐ 
οὗ" καταστῇ καὶ “παύσηται, “τῆς περιεχούσης" τὰ 
ὑγρὰ χώρας ἱσταμένης.᾽ αἱ ῥύσεις οὖν τῶν" φερομέ- 
νων ἀεὶ τὰ ὑποχωροῦντα τοῦ ἀέρος διώκουσαι τοῖς 
δ᾽ ἀντιπεριωθουμένοις " ἐλαυνόμεναι τὸ ἐνδελεχὲς 

\ 9 / » A \ ’, “-- ¢ 
καὶ ἀλώφητον ἔχουσι. διὸ Kat φέρονται θᾶττον οὗ 

x , 1. ὦ x op a ι i 

F ποταμοὶ πληθύοντες“- ὅταν δ᾽ ὀλίγον ἡ καὶ κοῖλον, 

>\7 re has δὲ ‘tees 5 , δι. ὁ , 15 
(ἀνλ)ίεται" τὸ ὑγρὸν ὑπ᾽ ἀσθενείας, οὐχ ὑπείκοντος 


_Diibner (after Wyttenbach supra); τὸν -Μ88. 
τις omitted by J}, g, ε. 
TOU -£.- 4 τόπον -J, δ. 
Escorial T-11-5 ; αὐτοῖς -all other mss. 
συναπορεῖ -X, ε: τὰ συναπορρεῖται “J, 8. 
Bernardakis ; 3 ἄχρις -MSS. οὖν -Ἡ. 
“περιούσης -J}, g, β (superscript over Bhs ek 3 Tepi- 
εχούσας -Escorial] wis (a (ons Over σας -Ccorr. 

10 ἱστάμενος -J1, Voss. 16, Escorial T-11-5, Bonon.corr- (os 
superscript over a 3 ἱστάμενα 83 ἐνισταμένης (“ impediente’’) 
-Wyttenbach, τοῦ -Escorial T-11-5. 

12 τοῦ δ᾽ ἀντιπεριπεριωθουμένου Εασες T-11-5. 

18. πληθύνοντες -J, g, Voss. 16, Escorial T-11-5. 


on aon ὦ wh ν» 


72 





PLATONIC QUESTIONS vu, 1005 


pressures with meshes that conform to it, to force 
the iron back and push it on before itself.* Well 
then, of these phenomena there might be some such 
explanation. 

8. It is not similarly easy to comprehend the way 
in which cyclical propulsion is involved in the flowing 
of waters upon the earth. It must be observed, how- 
ever, that the water of pools is calm and at rest 
because it has spread and collected about itself from 
all sides motionless air that nowhere leaves an 
empty space. At any rate, the water on the surface 
in pools and in seas is agitated and undulates when 
the air begins to surge, for it straightway follows 
the latter as it changes position and flows off along 
with it because of the irregularity, the downward 
impact ὃ producing the trough of the wave and the 
upward impact the swell until it has settled down 
and stopped as the space that encompasses the 
waters comes to rest. The streams of running 
waters, then, always pursuing the air that gives 
way and being driven on by that which is pushed 
around in turn, flow perpetually and unremittingly. 
This is also why rivers run more swiftly when they 
are full; but, when the water is low and shallow, it 
grows slack from feebleness, as the air does not 

α Uf. Lucretius, vi, 1056-1064 with R. A. Fritzsche, Rhein. 
Mus., N.F. lvii (1902), p. 370 and p. 372, ἢ. 14; and especi- 
ally for the terminology cf. the use of the theory of effluvia, 
pores, and corrugations of a surface in Plutarch, Quaest. 
Naturales 916 p-F. 

δ 4,6, the impact of the air on the water. 


14 Wyttenbach ; ἴεται -X, 3 £, β. Β, €é, M$ ἵεται -all 
other mss.; ἵσταται -Wyttenbach, Apelt (Philologus, Ixii 
[1903], p. 287). 15 ὑπήκοντος -J, €, N. 

Te 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


a A 4 3 
(1000) τοῦ ἀέρος οὐδὲ πολλὴν ἀντιπερίστασιν λαμβάνοντος. 
Ἁ \ A ~ / a 
οὕτω δὲ Kal τὰ πηγαῖα τῶν ὑδάτων avayKaiov” 
ἐστιν ἀναφέρεσθαι, τοῦ θύραθεν ἀέρος εἰς τὰς κενου- 
, 9 3 1θ / 2Φ 4 “ \ λ 4 
μένας" ev Baber χώρας" ὑποφερομένου Kai πάλιν θύ- 
3 ω 3 / ” \ / 
1006 pate τὸ ὕδωρ ἐκπέμποντος. οἴκου δὲ βαθυσκίου 
καὶ περιέχοντος ἀέρα νήνεμον᾽ ὕδατι ῥανθὲν" ἔδαφος 
πνεῦμα ποιεῖ καὶ ἄνεμον, μεθισταμένου τοῦ ἀέρος 
ἐξ ἕδρας παρεμπίπτοντι τῷ ὑγρῷ καὶ πληγὰς 
λαμβάνοντος.“ οὕτως ἐξωθεῖσθαί θ᾽ ὑπ᾽ ἀλλήλων 
\ 3 ’ὔ 3 ὔ Yd 3 δ 
καὶ ἀνθυπείκειν ἀλλήλοις πέφυκεν, οὐκ οὔσης κε- 
, > eQr ¢ Vg iy , = ἢ 
νότητος ἐν ἡ θάτερον ἱδρυθὲνἷ οὐ μεθέξει τῆς θατέ- 
ρου μεταβολῆς. 
ἢ ‘ \ 1 Ae , a Me ” 
9. Kai μὴν τὰ περὶ τῆς" συμφωνίας αὐτὸς εἴς- 
ρηκεν ὃν τρόπον ὁμοιζοπαθεῖς αἱ κινήσεις ποιν"οῦσι 
τοὺς φθόγγους. ὀξὺς μὲν γὰρ 6 ταχὺς γίγνεται 
βαρὺς δὲ ὁ «βραδύς""" - διὸ καὶ πρότερον κινοῦσι' ᾿ τὴν 
αἴσθησιν οἱ ὀξεῖς" ὅταν δὲ τούτοις 767"? μαραινομέ- 
13 ae) , ε πὰ i , > , 
vois® καὶ ἀπολήγουσιν ot βραδεῖς ἐπιβάλωσιν ἀρχό- 
Β μενοι, τὸ κραθὲν αὐτῶν διὰ ὁμοιοπάθειαν ἡδονὴν 
τῇ ἀκοῇ παρέσχεν, ἣν συμφωνίαν καλοῦσιν. ὅτι 
δὲ τούτων ὄργανον 6 dnp ἐστι ῥάδιον συνιδεῖν ἐκ 
τῶν προειρημένων. ἔστι γὰρ ἡ φωνὴ πληγὴ τοῦ 


1 τὰ πηγαῖα τῶν ἀναγκαίων -ιἶ", g. 
κενουμένας =A wah gis «01. 
χώρας ἐν βάθει - 
Wyttenbach (ἢ vena -Leonicus, N ogarola) s ἀέρα ἢ 
ἄνεμον -MSS. 5 ῥαθὲν -}. 
δ λαμβάνοντι -J*, 5. 
ee Sophie -all other mss. 
8 γὰς -Voss. 16, Escorial T-11-5, Bonon. 


Ὁ» © 1τὉ 


9 <...> -added by Pohlenz ; ὁμοιοῦσι -Μ85. 5 ὁμολογοῦσι οἱ 
φθόγγοι -Nogarola. 10 βαρύς -ὦ1, 
τ: Keven: πρότερον οὐ κινοῦσι -all other Mss. (but οὐ evased 
in α and cancelled in A). 12 ἤδη -omitted by «. 


τά 





PLATONIC QUESTIONS vu, 1005-1006 


yield and does not undergo much cyclical replace- 
ment. It must be in this way too that the waters of 
fountains run upwards, the air from outside running 
down into the vacated underground spaces and 
thrusting the water forth again. In a darkened 
house where the air enclosed is still sprinkling the 
floor with water produces a draught or breeze, as 
the air shifts from its position before the moisture 
when it intervenes and is subjected to its impacts. 
Thus the two are naturally expelled by each other 
and yield to each other in turn, for there is no vacuity 
in which the one could be situated and so not par- 
take of the change in the other. 

9. And now as to the subject of consonance, he 
has himself stated 5 how the sounds (are made con- 
gruous by the motions). For the sound that is swift 
turns out to be high, and that which is slow to be 
low, which is also why the sense is set in motion 
sooner by the high sounds ; and, when these as they 
are already fading out and dying away are over- 
taken by the slow sounds just beginning,’ the pro- 
duct of their blending because of the congruity affords 
the hearing pleasure which men call consonance. 
That the air is the instrument of this process is easy 
to see from what was previously stated.° Sound, in 

« Timaeus 80 a 3-8 8. Of the genuine problems involved 
in this passage Plutarch appears not to have been aware. 
‘They are stated but not persuasively resolved by Cornford 
(Plato’s Cosmology, pp. 320-326) and Moutsopoulos (La 
Musique... de Platon, pp. 36-42). 

> νοι just beginning to affect the percipient by setting the 
sense in motion. 

¢ Timaeus 67 8 2-6; cf. Plutarch, De Fortuna 98 8, De EF 
390 8, and De Defectu Orac. 436 v. 





75 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1006) αἰσθανομένου δι᾽ ὦτων ὑπ᾽ ἀέρος" πλήττει yap: 
rae ὁ ἀὴρ ὑπὸ τοῦ κινήσαντος, ἂν μὲν 7 ἡ σφο- 
δρόν, ὀξέως, ἂν δ᾽ ἀμβλύ, ἌΣ, ὁ 67° 
σφόδρα" καὶ συντόνως πληγεὶς" προσμίγνυσι τῇ 
ἀκοῇ πρότερος, εἶτα περιιὼν πάλιν" καὶ καταλαμ- 
βάνων tov" βραδύτερον συνέπεται καὶ συμπαραπέμ- 


8 A ” 
mer τὴν αἴσθησιν. 


ZHTHMA H’ 

Πῶς λέγει τὰς ψυχὰς ὁ 0 Τίμαιος εἴς τε γῆν καὶ 

Sr as καὶ τἄλλα ὁ ὅσα ὄργανα. χρόνου σπαρῆναι; ; 
Ο [Πότερον οὕτως" ἐκίνει τὴν γῆν ὥσπερ, ἥλιον καὶ 
σελήνην καὶ τοὺς πέντε πλάνητας, οὕς ὄργανα 
χρόνου διὰ τὰς τροπὰς προσηγόρευε,᾽ καὶ ἔδει τὴν 
γῆν ἰλλομένην"" περὶ τὸν διὰ πάντων πόλον τεταμέ- 
νον" μεμηχανῆσθαι By * συνεχομένην καὶ μένουσαν 


3 


ἀλλὰ στρεφομένην" καὶ ἀνειλουμένην νοεῖν, ὡς 


1 τετὶ, δ: τε superscript over γὰρ -X}. 

2 8 ba xX, J, g, fey y, i, De ὁ δὲ -N. 

3. σφοδρὸς -Ῥ. 4 σύντονος πληγὴ -J, δ. 
ὃ πρότερον -}, g. πάντα -J}, 5. 
? πὸ ᾷ", δ, ε: 

8 παραπέμπει -Voss. 16, Escoria! T-11-5, 

: ὄντως = 


δ σελήνην ἢ ἢ -J}, 

προσηγόρευσε J, 1" g. 

ἰλλομένην . .. ἀνειλουμένην -omitted by J}, 5": εἰλλουμένην 

(ει and ov superscript over, and ο) -Βοοττγ, ; εἰλουμένην -Voss. 

16, Escorial T-11-5. 

> 18. πεταγμένον -a, A, β' (y erased -f), y, E, B, e, n, Escorial 
11-5. 

14 δὲν B?, Bonon., Voss. 16, Escorial T-11-5; μὴ μεμηχανῆ- 
σθαι -all other Μ588.: [μεμηχανῆσθαι] -Hartman (De Plutar- 
cho, p. 585). 

15 συστρεφομένην -Χ. 

76 





PLATONIC QUESTIONS vu-vu, 1006 


fact, is the impact made by air through the ears 
upon the percipient, for the air, when struck by the 
agent that moved it, strikes sharply if that agent is 
vehement and more softly if it is dull. The air, then, 
that has been struck vehemently and intensely comes 
upon the hearing sooner and then, moving around 
again and catching up the slower air,* accompanies 
it and with it conveys the sensation. 


QUESTION VIII 


1. WHat does ‘Timaeus mean by saying ὃ that the 
souls were sowed in earth and moon and all the rest 
of the instruments of time ? 

Was he giving the earth motion like that of sun 
and moon and the five planets, which because they 
reverse their courses © he called instruments of time ; 
and ought the earth coiling about the axis extended 
through all? be understood to have been devised 
not as confined and at rest but as turning and whirl- 


α This seems to contradict the statement just above, ὅταν 
δὲ τούτοις . . . οἱ βραδεῖς ἐπιβάλωσιν ἀρχόμενοι . . ., and is 
certainly not in accord with 7%maeus 80 a 6--8 4. 

δ Plato, Timaeus 42 pv 4-5 (see also 41 κε 4-5); οἷ. [Plu- 
tarch|, De Fato 573 x. 

¢ Cf. Timaeus 39 Ὁ 7-8 (... τῶν ἄστρων ὅσα δι᾽ οὐρανοῦ 
πορευόμενα ἔσχεν τροπάς .. .) and 40 B 6-7 (τὰ δὲ τρεπόμενα καὶ 
πλάνην τοιαύτην ἴσχοντα . . .) With Proclus, In Platonis Ti- 
maeum iii, pp. 127, 31-128, 1 (Diehl). 

4 Timaeus 40 8 8—c 2. Plutarch’s μεμηχανῆσθαι represents 
Plato’s ἐμηχανήσατο. Instead of διὰ πάντων (i.e. all the 
planetary orbits) the mss. of Plato have διὰ παντός, δι᾽ ἅπαν- 
tos, Or διὰ τοῦ παντός ; and instead of ἐλλομένην two of them 
(W, Y) have εἰλουμένην, while two (A, P) have εἱλλομένην (or 
εἰλλ-) τὴν (cf. Cornford, Plato’s Cosmology, Ὁ. 120, n. 13; and 
for the textual tradition of Aristotle, De Caelo 293 Ὁ 31-82 
cf. P. Moraux, J/ermes, Ixxxii [1954], pp. 176-178). 


mi 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1006) ὕστερον ᾿Αρίσταρχος καὶ Σέλευκος ἀπεδείκνυσαν, ὁ 
μὲν ὑποτιθέμενος μόνον ὁ δὲ Σέλευκος καὶ ἀποφαι- 
νόμενος; Θεόφραστος δὲ καὶ προσιστορεῖ τῷ 
Πλάτωνι πρεσβυτέρῳ γενομένῳ μεταμέλειν ὡς οὐ 
προσήκουσαν ἀποδόντι τῆ γῇ τὴν μέσην χώραν 
τοῦ παντός. 

2. Ἢ τούτοις μὲν ἀντίκειται πολλὰ τῶν ὁμολο- 
D γουμένως' ἀρεσκόντων τῷ ἀνδρί, μεταγραπτέον δὲ 
τὸ “χρόνου ᾽᾿ “χρόνῳ, λαμβάνοντας" ἀντὶ τῆς 
γενικῆς" τὴν δοτικήν, καὶ δεκτέον ὄργανα μὴ τοὺς 
ἀστέρας ἀλλὰ τὰ σώματα τῶν ζῴων δλέγεσθαι 

4 3 ’ ς / \ \ > 
καθάπερ ᾿Αριστοτέλης ὡρίσατο τὴν ψυχὴν ἐντε- 
᾿ ὁμολογουμένων -J! (final ν remade ἴος -J?), g. | 
2 X, J', g, 8, Bonon., Voss. 16, Escorial T-11-5¢or-. ; eon 

Bavovros ~y, Escorial 'T- “3 δὶ; λαμβάνοντα -a, A, ἰδ, B, e, π 

γενητικῆς αὐ τ 
« Cf. Plutarch, De Facie 923 a with the references in my 
note ad loc. (L.C.L. xii, p. 54, note a). 

δ Cf. Heath, Aristarchus of Samos, pp. 305-307 ; 5. Pines, 
“ἢ fragment de Séleucus .. ,, Rev, @llistoire des 

. Sciences, xvi (1963), pp. 193-209; and N. Swerdlow, /sis, 

Ixiv (1973), pp. 242-243 in his review of B. L. van der 
Waerden, 7bid., pp. 239-243. 

¢ Theophrastus, Phys. Opin., frag. 22 (Dox. Wraeci, Ὁ. 
494, 1-3); cf. Plutarch, Numa xi, 3 (67 pb). 

4 Like Chalcidius (Platonis Timaeus, Ὁ. 187, 4-13 [Wro- 
bel] =p. 166, 6-12 [Waszink]) Plutarch here recognizes only 
two possible interpretations of ἐλλομένην περὶ τὸν . . . πόλον : 
one, that the earth is stationary at the centre (with συνεχομέ- 
νην καὶ μένουσαν cf. Proclus, In Platonis Timaeum iii, p. 137, 
6-7 and 13-20 [Diehl] and Plutarch’s own usage in Quaest. 
Conviv. 728 ©: ἰλλομένην τὴν ὅπα καὶ καθειργομένην). and 
the other, that the earth revolves like a planet around the 
axis common to all the planetary orbits (with στρεφομένην 
καὶ ἀνειλουμένην cf. Proclus, In Platonis Timaeum iii, p. 138, 
7-8 [Diehl]: εἱλουμένην καὶ στρεφομένην; cf. εἱλουμένων 
[Simplicius, Phys., p. 292, 28-29] and ἀνείλησιν [Simplicius, 
78 











PLATONIC QUESTIONS vin, 1006 


ing about in the way set forth later by Aristarchus @ 
and Seleucus,? by the former only as an hypothesis 
but by Seleucus beyond that as a statement of fact ἢ 
In fact Theophrastus even adds the observation ¢ that 
Plato, when he had grown older, repented of having 
assigned to the earth as not befitting her the mid- 
most space of the sum of things.4 

2. Or is this in opposition to many of the opinions 
that the man admittedly held ; and must we change 
‘of time ” to read “ in time,’’ adopting the dative 
instead of the genitive, and take instruments to 
mean not the stars but the bodies of living beings 
in the way that Aristotle defined the soul as actuality 


De Caelo, p. 499, 15}).. The way in which the second alterna- 
tive is limited by the comparison with the hypothesis of 
Aristarchus is made clear by what ‘Theophrastus is reported 
to have said and doubly clear by the reference in Numa xi, 
where .. . τῆς γῆς ws ἐν ἑτέρᾳ χώρᾳ καθεστώσης ... shows it 
to be incompatible with the “ more genuinely ’’ Pythagorean 
theory of Simplicius which Cornford sought to identify as its 
true basis (Plato’s Cosmology, pp. 127-129; Kk. Gaiser, 
Platons ungeschriebene Lehre [Stuttgart, 1963], p. 184, n. 155 
[pp. 385-387]) but which is itself certainly post-Aristotelian 
(cf. W. Burkert, Weisheit und Wissenschaft [Niirnberg, 
1962], pp. 216-217). Vlutarch’s two alternatives silently 
exclude the possibility that the Timaeus refers to a central 
earth with axial rotation (Aristotle, De Caelo 293 b 30-32 and 
296 a 26-27) or with any sort of vibratory or oscillatory 
motion, discredited modern fantasies recently revived by k. 
Gaiser (op. cit., Ὁ. 183, n. 153 [pp. 381-385]) in the form of 
“ wobbling motion about the axis... to produce a kind of 
nutation ’ and account for precession-—which was unknown 
to Plato. On Timaeus 40 B 8—-c 3, Aristotle’s statements in 
the De Caelo, and the remark by Theophrastus ef. Cherniss, 
-lristotle’s Criticism of Plato, pp. 545-564: 1. Diiring, 
Gnomon, xxvii (1955), pp. 156-157 ; F. ΔΤ, Brignoli, Giornale 
ltaliano di Filologia, xi-(1958), pp. 246-260; W. Burkert, 
Weisheit und Wissenschaft, p. 305, n. 17. 


79 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1006) A€yerav’ σώματος φυσικοῦ" ὀργανικοῦ δυνάμει 
ζωὴν ἔχοντος, ὥστε τοιοῦτον εἶναι τὸν λόγον" αἱ 
ψυχαὶ εἰς τὰ προσήκοντα ὀργανικὰ σώματα ἐν 
χρόνῳ κατεσπάρησαν ; ἀλλὰ καὶ τοῦτο παρὰ τὴν 
δόξαν ἐστίν: οὐ γὰρ ἅπαξ ἀλλὰ πολλάκις ὄργανα 
χρόνου τοὺς ἀστέρας εἴρηκεν, ὅπου καὶ τὸν ἥλιον 
αὐτὸν εἰς διορισμὸν καὶ φυλακὴν ἀριθμῶν χρόνου" 

E γεγονέναι φησὶ μετὰ τῶν ἄλλων πλανήτων. 
8. ΓΑριστον οὖν τὴν γῆν ὄργανον ἀκούειν χρόνου, 
μὴ κινουμένην ὥσπερ τοὺς ἀστέρας, ἀλλὰ τῷ" 
περὶ αὑτὴν μένουσαν ἀεὶ παρέχειν ἐκείνοις φερο- 
μένοις ἀνατολὰς καὶ δύσεις, αἷς τὰ πρῶτα μέτρα 
τῶν χρόνων, ἡμέραι καὶ νύκτες, ὁρίζονται" διὸ 
καὶ φύλακα καὶ δημιουργὸν αὐτὴν ἀτρεκῆ νυκτὸς 
καὶ ἡμέρας προσεῖπε": καὶ γὰρ ot τῶν ὡρολογίων 
γνώμονες οὐ συμμεθιστάμενοι ταῖς σκιαῖς ἀλλὰ 
ἑστῶτες ὄργανα χρόνου καὶ μέτρα γεγόνασι, μι- 
᾿μούμενοι τῆς γῆς τὸ ἐπιπροσθοῦν τῷ ἡλίῳ περὶ 
1 ἐνδελέχειαν - ἷ, δ᾽ ; ἐντελέχειαν -all other mss. ; «πρώτην» 
ἐντελέχειαν -Bernardakis. 


2. ψυχικοῦ -J, δ. 
3 περὶ -J . 


ω 
4 χρόνου -J1, 23 χρόνου X13 χρόνω -all other mss. 
Tots -ὐ΄, δ. 
δ προσῆκε τῷ, 8. t 


΄ 


α 
7 Pohlenz; καὶ μέτρα χρόνου -ἃ ; καὶ χρόνου μέτρα -all 
other mss. 


@ Aristotle, De Anima 412 a 27-28 and 412 b 5-6 are here 
conflated. In both the ἐντελέχεια is specified as ἡ πρώτης but 


80 





PLATONIC QUESTIONS ναι, 1006 


of body that is natural, instrumental, and potentially 
possessed of life,* so that the meaning is like this : 
the souls in time were disseminated in the appro- 
priate ὃ instrumental bodies ? This too, however, is 
contrary to his thought, for it is not once but fre- 
quently that he has called the stars instruments of 
time, since he even says ὁ that the sun itself along 
with the other planets came into being to distinguish 
and preserve the numbers of time. 

3. It is best, then, to understand that the earth 
is an instrument of time not by being in motion as 
the stars are but by remaining always at rest as they 
revolve about her and so providing them with risings 
and settings, which define days and nights, the 
primary measures of times.¢ That is also why he 
called her strict guardian and artificer of night and 
day,’ for the pins of sun-dials too have come to be 
instruments and measures of time not by changing 
their position along with the shadows but by standing 
still, imitating the earth’s occultation of the sun when 


Plutarch need not therefore have written πρώτην ἐντελέχειαν 
(cf. Dox. Graeci, p. 387 a 14-15 as against a 1-3). The crucial 
word for Plutarch here, ὀργανικοῦ, comes from the second 
passage and in order to support the proposed interpretation of 
ὄργανα in Timaeus 42 pv 4-5 shouid be taken to mean not 
** furnished with instruments ”’ (cf. De Anima 412 a 28-b 4) 
but “ instrumental.” 

> Cf. Timaeus 41 £ 5. 

¢ Timaeus 38 c 5-6. 

@ Cf. ** Timaeus Locrus " θῖν (γᾶ δ᾽ ἐν μέσῳ ἱδρυμένα. κὰν 
ὧρός τε ὄρφνας καὶ ἁμέρας γίνεται δύσιάς τε καὶ ἀνατολὰς 
γεννῶσα - - .): Proclus, In Platonis Timaeum iii, pp. 139, 
93-140, 5 (Diehl). 

ε Timaeus 40 c 1-2; ef. Plutarch, De Facie 937 © and 
938 © with my notes ad loc. (L.C_D. xii, p. 157, note ¢ and p. 
165, note c). 


81 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1006) αὐτὴν ὑποφερομένῳ, καθάπερ εἶπεν ᾿Εμπεδοκλῆς 


, \ A ἢ € Ae , 
νύκτα δὲ γαῖα τίθησιν, ὑφισταμένη" φαέεσσι. 


ὡς ι 5 , » ι + 7 
F τοῦτο μὲν οὖν τοιαύτην ἔχει τὴν ἐξήγησιν. 


1001 


3 A A = Ν plain. \ A 
4. ᾿Εκεῖνο de? μᾶλλον av tis ὑπίδοιτο,, μὴ παρὰ 
3 e ἰ κέ ΄ 
τὸ εἰκὸς ὁ ἥλιος καὶ ἀτόπως λέγεται" μετὰ τῆς 
, \ ~ 4 > 
σελήνης καὶ τῶν “πλανήτων εἰς διορισμὸν χρόνου 
’ 
γεγονέναι. καὶ γὰρ ἄλλως μέγα τοῦ ἡλίου τὸ ἀξί- 
\ 
wpa καὶ ὑπ᾽ αὐτοῦ Πλάτωνος ἐν Πολιτείᾳ βασι- 
λεὺς ἀνηγόρευται παντὸς τοῦ αἰσθητοῦ καὶ κύριος, 
-“ “- ~ 3 
ὥσπερ τοῦ νοητοῦ τἀγαθόν: ἐκείνου γὰρ᾽ ἔκγονος" 
/ a - a 
λέγεται, παρέχων τοῖς ὁρατοῖς μετὰ τοῦ φαίνεσθαι 
τὸ γίγνεσθαι, καθάπερ ἀπ᾽ ἐκείνου τὸ εἶναι καὶ τὸ 
γιγνώσκεσθαι τοῖς νοητοῖς ὑπάρχει. τὸν δὴ τοι- 
αύτην φύσιν ἔχοντα καὶ δύναμιν τηλικαύτην θεὸν 
ὄργανον χρόνου γεγονέναι καὶ μέτρον ἐναργὲς τῆς 
/ “ ~ 
πρὸς ἀλλήλας" βραδυτῆτι Kal τάχει τῶν ὀκτὼ 
σφαιρῶν διαφορᾶς οὐ πάνυ δοκεῖ πρεπῶδες οὐδ᾽ 
Μ »Ψ φ ε , > \ e 5 , 
ἄλλως εὔλογον εἶναι. ῥητέον οὖν τοὺς ὑπὸ τούτων 
* ἐφισταμένη -Scaliger; ὑφισταμένοιο φάεσσι -Dicls (Po- 
eturum Philos. Fragmenta [1901], p. 126). 
2 EKEL δὲ -} (corrected J*) 2 
3 ὑπείδοιτο - 1 (before Aided Z; ὑπόδοιτο -Voss. 16 (6 
over erasure). 


4 λέγεται -N 3 λέγηται -all other Mss. 
: δε -J}, g. 
᾿ sii -X1; ἔκγονος -as € ND, Escorial T-11-5 ; ἔγγονος 
nd other Mss. 
7 τῆς -omitted by X, J?, g, a (but added superscript by 
X?! and a!). 
᾿ 1 ἀλλήλαις -X (a ἘΡΘΗΠΗΡΕ over αἱ cis ° 








2 Empedocles, frag. B 48 (D.-K.). There is no good reason 
to emend ὑφισταμένη (cf. Aeschylus, Persae 87 ; Thucydides, 
vii, 66, 2) as Scaliger and Diels did ; but rank who retains 


82 


PLATONIC QUESTIONS vit, 1006-1007 


he moves down around her, as Empedocles said 


Night is produced by the earth when she stands in the way 
of the daylight.¢ 


Such, then, is the explanation of this point. 

4. One might rather have misgivings about that 
other point, whether it is not unlikely and absurd to 
assert of the sun that along with the moon and the 
planets he came into being to distinguish time.® 
Yor the sun is generally rated high in dignity and 
especially by Plato who himself in the Republic ¢ has 
proclaimed him king and sovereign of all that is per- 
ceptible just as the good is of the intelligible, for of 
that good he is said to be the offspring, affording to 
things visible with their coming to light their coming 
to be even as that good is for things intelligible the 
source of their being and of being known. Now 
certainly for the god with such a nature and so much 
power to have come to be as an instrument of time 
and evident measure of the relative difference in 
speed and slowness of the eight spheres ὦ seems to 
be not very proper and to be unreasonable besides. 
It must be stated, then, that because of ignorance 
it, is mistaken in insisting that it must imply motion of the 
earth (Rhein. Mus., c [1957], pp. 122-124). 

> i.e. Timaeus 38 ς 5- 6, which was appealed to at he end 
of section 2 supra (1006 pb sub finem). 

¢ Republic 506 © 3—507 a 4, 508 a 4-6, 508 B 12-c 2, 509 
B 2-8, and 509 p 1-4; see also Plutarch, Ve Facie 944 © with 
my note ad loc. (L.C.L. xii, p. 213, note g). 

4 Timaeus 39 5 2-5, where Plato says φοράς, however, and 
not “ὁ spheres ” (cf. Cornford, Plato’s Cosmology, pp. 78-79 
and 119; Cherniss, Aristotle’s Criticism of Plato, p. 555). 
So the “ circles ” of Republic 617 8 4-7 are called “ spheres Ὁ 
by Plutarch in Quaest. Conviv. 745 c and in De An. Proc. in 
Timaeo 1029 c.. Cf. also Albinus, Epitome xiv, 7 (p. 87, 1-8 
[Louis] =pp. 170, 36-171, 7 [Hermann)]). 

83 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


, 3 » 4 he , 
(1007) ταραττομένους δι᾿ ἄγνοιαν οἴεσθαι τὸν ypovov" 
,͵ > UA Moar A 
μέτρον εἶναι κινήσεως καὶ ἀριθμὸν κατὰ πρότερον 
. Ψ 2 3 , > ‘ 
Kal ὕστερον, ws ᾿Αριστοτέλης εἶπεν, ἢ TO ἐν 
ὔ ’ 4 "A a‘ / 
Β κινήσει ποσόν, ws Σπεύσιππος, ἢ διάστημα κι- 
΄ ” 3 S74 207 et os A a > 4 
νήσεως ἄλλο οὐδέν, ὡς ἔνιοι τῶν Στωικῶν ἀπὸ 
συμβεβηκότος" ὁριζόμενοι τὴν δ᾽ οὐσίαν αὐτοῦ καὶ 
τὴν δύναμιν οὐ συνορῶντες, ἣν ὅ ye® Ilivdapos 
ἔοικεν οὐ φαύλως ὑπονοῶν εἰπεῖν 
" 7 \ , : , ; 8 
ἄνακτα, τὸν πάντων ὑπερβάλλοντα χρόνον" pa- 
κάρων 
Ὁ / > A / / > / \ 
ὃ τε Πυθαγόρας, ἐρωτηθεὶς τί χρόνος ἐστί, τὴν 
τοὐρανοῦ" ψυχὴν εἰπεῖν. οὐ γὰρ πάθος οὐδὲ συμ- 
βεβηκὸς ἧς ἔτυχε κινήσεως ὁ χρόνος ἐστίν, αἰτία 
δὲ καὶ δύναμις καὶ ἀρχὴ τῆς πάντα συνεχούσης τὰ 
γιγνόμενα συμμετρίας καὶ τάξεως, ἣν ἡ τοῦ ὅλου 
φύσις ἔμψυχος οὖσα κινεῖται. μᾶλλον δὲ κίνησις 
1 τῶν χρόνων -{, 5. : 
κατὰ τὸ πρότερον καὶ τὸ ὕστερον ~Escorial T-11-5; κατὰ 
᾿ «τὸ πρότερον καὶ ὕστερον -Bernardakis. 
ἄλλα -J*, g. * δὴ -8- 
συμβεβηκότα -J*. 
nv ye -J1, B3 ἣν 6 τε -Stephanus. 
Heyne; dva-J, £3 ἀνὰ -all other ss. 


τῶν eee χρόνων -J, 8. 
Turnebus ; τούτου -MSS. ; τοῦ ὅλου -Nogarola. 


oor aan ὦ 


α Physics 219 Ὁ 1-2 and 220 a 24-25 (ἀριθμὸς κινήσεως κατὰ 
τὸ πρότερον καὶ ὕστερον), 220 Ὁ 32—221 a 1 and 221 b 7 
(μέτρον κινήσεως) : cf. Plotinus, Enn. 1, vii, 9, lines 1-2 
and J. F. Callahan, Four Views of Time in Ancient Philo- 
sophy (Harvard Univ. Press, 1948), pp. 50-53. 

> Speusippus, frag. 53 (Lang). Cf. Strato’s τὸ ἐν ταῖς 
πράξεσι ποσόν (Simplicius, Phys., pp. 789, 34-35 and 790, 1-2 
=Strato, frag. 76 [Wehrli]). 

¢ §.V.F. ii, frag. 5153 cf. ii, frags. 509-510 and i, frag. 93 
and Dow. Graeci, p. 461, 15-16 (Posidonius). 


84 





PLATONIC QUESTIONS, ναὶ, 1007 


those who are disturbed by these considerations 
think time to be a measure or number of motion 
according to antecedent and subsequent, as Aristotle 
said,? or what in motion is quantitative, as Speusippus 
did,® or extension of motion and nothing else, as did 
some of the Stoics,° defining it by an accident and not 
comprehending its essence and potency,? of which 
no mean surmise seems to have been expressed 
by Pindar in the words, 


The lord, the lofty, time, who excels all the beatified gods,¢ 


and by Pythagoras, when asked what time is, in the 
reply, the soul of the heavens.f For time is not an 
attribute or accident of any chance motion? but 
cause and potency and principle of that which holds 
together all the things that come to be, of the sym- 
metry and order in which the nature of the whole 
universe, being animate, is in motion; or rather, 


4 Cf. Proclus, In Platonis Timaeum iii, p. 20, 10-15 and 
p- 95, 7-20 (Diehl) ; V. Goldschmidt, Le systéme stoicien, pp. 
41-42. 

¢ Pindar, frag. 33 (Bergk, Schroeder, Snell) =24 (Turyn) 
= 14 (Bowra). 

7. Assigned to the Pythagorean ’Axovopara by A. Delatte 
(tudes sur la littérature pythagoricienne [Paris, 1915], p. 
278); but cf. Zeller, Phil. Griech. i/1, Ὁ. 524, n. 2 and p. 546, 
n. 2. A fanciful interpretation is given by R. B. Onians, 
Origins of European Thought . . . (Cambridge, 1954), pp. 
250-251; but the definition here ascribed to Pythagoras 
might be connected with the theory mentioned by Aristotle 
(frag. 201 [Rose]), for which cf. Cherniss, Crit. Presoc. Phil., 
pp. 214-216. 

¢ Contrast Aristotle, Physics 251 Ὁ 28 (...6 χρόνος πάθος 
τι κινήσεως), 219 b 15-16, and 220 Ὁ 24-28 ; and cf. Proclus, 
In Platonis Timaeum iii, Ὁ. 21, 5-6 (Diehl): οὐκ ἄρα ἀκολου- 
θητέον τοῖς ev ψιλαῖς ἐπινοίαις αὐτὸν ἱστᾶσιν ἢ συμβεβηκός τι 
ποιοῦσιν. ; 


8 


(1007) 
C 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


Or \ , \ ; 
οὖσα καὶ τάξις αὐτὴ Kal συμμετρία χρόνος Ka- 
λεῖται, 

4 
πάντα γὰρ δι᾿ ἀψόφου 
4 ? \ 4 \ MO Pe ek 
βαίνων κελεύθου κατὰ δίκην τὰ θνήτ᾽ ayer. 

\ A ¢ ~ 3 ’, A \ 4 3 
καὶ γὰρ ἡ ψυχῆς οὐσία κατὰ τοὺς παλαιοὺς ἀρι- 
θμὸς ἦν αὐτὸς ἑαυτὸν κινῶν. διὸ δὴ καὶ Πλάτων 
ἔφη χρόνον ἅμα μετ᾽ οὐρανοῦ γεγονέναι κίνησιν δὲν 
καὶ πρὸ τῆς τοῦ" οὐρανοῦ" γενέσεως. χρόνος δ᾽ ἢ 

> * 291 ἢ , 6 201 , γῶν ΩΝ 
οὐκ ἦν" οὐδὲ γὰρ τάξις" οὐδὲ μέτρον οὐδὲν οὐδὲ 
διορισμὸς ἀλλὰ κίνησις ἀόριστος ὥσπερ: ἄμορφος 
ὕλη χρόνου καὶ ἀσχημάτιστος: ἐφελκύσασα δὲ 


1 Hartman (De Plutarcho, p. 586), implied by the versions 
of Amyot and Xylander ; dir -X ; αὕτη -all other mss. 

2 δὲ -omitted by J}, g. 

3 τοῦ -omitted by β, Voss. 16, Escorial T-11-5, Bonon. 


* avou (ἰ.ε. ἀνθρώπου) -J. 
5 δ᾽ -omitted by J}, g. 6 χάξεις -}. 


ἃ This practical identification of time with the activity of 
the rational world-soul prefigures the doctrine of Plotinus 
(e.g. Enn. 111, vii, 12, lines 1-3 and 20-25; ef. HI. Leisegang, 








| Die Begriffe der Zeit und Ewigkeit im spdteren Platonismus 


[ Miinster i.W., 1913], pp. 9 and 23-24; Thévenaz, L’.4Ame 
du Monde, p. 96). It is with a very different emphasis upon 
the Platonic contrast of time and eternal being that Plutarch 
in De Iv 392 © makes his teacher, Ammonius, say: κινητὸν 
γάρ τι καὶ κινουμένῃ συμφανταζόμενον ὕλῃ . . - ὁ χρόνος, 
οὗ γε δὴ τὸ μὲν ἔπειτα καὶ τὸ πρότερον . . . αὐτόθεν ἐξομολόγη- 
ais ἐστι τοῦ μὴ ὄντος (cf. C. Andresen, Logos und Nomos 
{Berlin, 1955], pp. 284-287). 

> Euripides, T'roiades 887-888, adapted by Plutarch in De 
Tside 381 8 also (ἄγεις -Euripides). 

¢ The definition is ascribed to Pythagoras in [Plutarch], 
De Placitis 898 c= Dox. Graeci, p. 386 a 13-15 (cf. 386 8 8-11 
(‘‘ Pythagoras ... and similarly also Xenocrates ’’| and W. 
Burkert, Weisheit und Wissenschaft [Niirnberg, 1962], p. 57, 
n. 73); but Plutarch himself, ascribing it to Xenocrates, 
rejects it as a misinterpretation of the Timaeus (De An. Proce. 


86 


PLATONIC QUESTIONS vu, 1007 


being motion and order itself and symmetry, it is 
called time,? 


For all that mortal is, 
Going his noiseless path, he guides aright.° 


In fact, the ancients even held that the essence of 
soul is number itself moving itself.° That is just the 
reason too why Plato said that time had come to be 
simultaneously with heaven? but there had been 
motion even before the generation of the heaven.¢ 
Time there was not, however, for there was not 
order either or any measure or distinction’ but mo- 
tion indeterminate, amorphous and unwrought mat- 
ter, as it were, of time’; but providence,” when 


in Timaeo 1012 p-F = Xenocrates, frag. 68 [Heinze] and 1013 
c-pD), which may account for his vague ascription of it to 
‘* the ancients ”’ here where he cites it as testimony in support 
of an interpretation (ef. Thévenaz, L’ Ame du Monde, p. 96). 

4 Timaeus 38 Β 6. 

e This refers, of course, to Timaeus 30 a 3-5 and 52 p— 
53 a3 cf. De An. Proc. in Timaeo 1014 8, 1016 p-F, and 
1024 c. 

* Cf. Macrobius, Sat. 1, viii, 7 (“. . . cum chaos esset, 
tempora non fuisse, siquidem tempus est certa dimensio 
quae ex caeli conversione colligitur’’); and contrast the 
formula of Atticus (Proclus, In Platonis Timaeum iii, p. 37, 
12-13 [Diehl]) : Χρόνος μὲν ἦν καὶ πρὸ οὐρανοῦ γενέσεως, τεταγ- 
μένος δὲ χρόνος οὐκ ἦν. 

σ In view of C. Andresen’s misinterpretation (Logos und 
Nomos [Berlin, 1955], p. 285 and n. 28) it must be empha- 
sized that χρόνου depends upon ὕλη, which is modified by 
ἄμορφος καὶ ἀσχημάτιστος (cf. De An. Proc. in Timaeo 1014 
F: τὸ τὴν ὕλην ἀεὶ μὲν ἄμορφον καὶ ἀσχημάτιστον ὑπ᾽ αὐτοῦ 
λέγεσθαι). 

h Cf. ἐκ προνοίας (De Facie 926 τ᾿ κατὰ θαυμασιωτάτην 
πρόνοιαν (Albinus, Epitome xii, 1 =p. 67, 90 [Louis] =p. 167, 
10 [Hermann]); and [Plutarch], De "Placitis 884 F (Dox. 
Graeci, p. 321 a 10-11) with Proclus, Jn Platonis Timaeum i, 
p. 415, 18-20 (Diehl). 


87 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1007) πρόνοια' καὶ καταλαβοῦσα" τὴν μὲν ὕλην σχήμασι 
τὴν δὲ κίνησιν περιόδοις τὴν μὲν κόσμον ἅμα τὴν 
δὲ χρόνον ἐποίησεν. εἰκόνες" δ᾽ εἰσὶν ἀμῴφω τοῦ 

D θεοῦ, τῆς μὲν οὐσίας ὁ κόσμος τῆς δ᾽ ἀιδιότητος 
(ὁ " χρόνος ἐν κινήσει καθάπερ ἐ ἐν γενέσει θεὸς ὁ δ 
κόσμος. ὅθεν ὁμοῦ γεγονότας φησὶν ὁμοῦ καὶ λυ- 
θήσεσθαι πάλιν," ἂν τις αὐτοὺς καταλαμβάνῃ λύσις" 
οὐ γὰρ οἷόν τ᾽ {εἶΐναι)" χωρὶς χρόνου τὸ γενητὸν 
ὥσπερ οὐδὲ τὸ νοητὸν αἰῶνος," εἰ μέλλει τὸ μὲν" 
ἀεὶ μένειν τὸ δὲ μηδέποτε διαλύεσθαι γιγνόμενον. 
οὕτως οὖν" ἀναγκαίαν πρὸς τὸν οὐρανὸν ἔχων 
συμπλοκὴν καὶ συναρμογὴν ὃ χρόνος οὐχ ἁπλῶς 
ἐστι" κίνησις ἀλλὰ ὥσπερ εἴρηται κίνησις ἐν τάξει 
μέτρον ἐχούσῃ καὶ πέρατα καὶ περιόδους: ὧν ὁ 

1H. ( ; ἐπικλύσασα δ᾽ ἐν χρόα (δ᾽ ἐν χρόνω ad ty δ) "δ᾽ 
ἡ τάξις -Fscorial T-11- δ) -MSS.3 ἐπικλώσασα δὲ Μοῖρα -Em- 
perius (Op. Philol., p. 340) ; ἐπικλύσασα δ᾽ ἡ χορεία -Apelt 


(Philologus, )xii [1903], p. 287): «ἣν ὁρίσασ᾽ ἡ ψυχή,Σ ἐγ- 
κλείσασα δ ἐν χώρᾳ -Pohlenz. 
β 


5 proper aks -X13; περιβαλοῦσα -Escorial Hi 11-53; κατα- 
βαλλοῦσα -D; i -all other mss. pero ghdace 
-Pohlenz. 

8 Leonicus ; εἰκότως -MSS. 
<6> -added by Stephanus. 
πάντα -J13 πάντας -&: 

«εἶναι -Δααεα by Wyttenbach. 
ye τὸν -J, δ. 8 ἄνευ αἰῶνος ~Escorial T-11-5. 

® μὲν -B? (added superscript), Bonon., Voss. 16, Escorial 
T-11-5 ; omitted by all other mss. 

10 οὖν -omitted by g. 


11 ἔστι -omitted by a, A, β' (but added superscript), γ, 


4 
5 
8 
7 


FE, B, €, ἢ. 
« Cf. Quaest. Conviv. 119 © (. . . τοῦ λόγου καταλαμβά- 


νοντος auTnv....) and 1001 B-c supra with note f there. 
> This like {Plutarch}, De Placitis 881 a (Dox. Graeci, p. 
299 a 11-12) suggests a misinterpretation of Timaeus 92 c 7 


88 





PLATONIC QUESTIONS vir, 1007 


she took in tow and curbed matter with shapes 4 
and motion with revolutions, simultaneously made 
of the former a universe and of the latter time. 
They are both semblances of god, the universe of his 
essence ὃ and time a semblance in motion of his 
eternity,° even as in the realm of becoming the uni- 
verse is god.¢ Hence he says ὁ that, as they came 
into being together, together they will also be dis- 
solved again if any dissolution overtake them, for 
what is subject to generation cannot (be) apart from 
time just as what is intelligible cannot apart from 
eternity either if the latter is always to remain fixed 
and the former never to be dissolved in its process 
of becoming.’ Time, then, since it is thus neces- 
sarily implicated and connected with the heaven, is 
not simply motion but, as has been said, motion in 
an orderly fashion that involves measure and limits 


or even the reading ποιητοῦ there instead of νοητοῦ (though 
the latter is implied by De Iside 373 B, . . . εἰκόνα τοῦ νοητοῦ 
κόσμου αἰσθητὸν ὄντα) possibly supported by the misinterpre- 
tation of Timaeus 29 Ἐ 3 (cf. De Sera Numinis Vindicta 550 
Ὁ and De An. Proc. in Timaeo 1014 5 [. . . πρὸς αὐτὸν 
ἐξομοίωσιν ...|); but it may also have been inferred that, 
since γένεσις is aN εἰκὼν οὐσίας ἐν ὕλῃ (De Iside 372 F), if, as 
Plutarch proceeds to assert, the universe is god in the realm 
of γένεσις (see note ὦ infra), that of which it is the semblance 
must be god in the realm of οὐσία. 

¢ Of. Timaeus 37 ὃ 5-7. Plutarch himself in De Defectu 
Orac. 422 B-c assigns eternity to the ideas (περὶ αὐτὰ τοῦ αἰ- 
ὥνος ὄντος οἷον ἀπορροὴν ἐπὶ τοὺς κόσμους φέρεσθαι τὸν χρόνον) ; 
cf. Albinus, Epitome xiv, 6 (p. 85, 5-6 [Louis] =p. 170, 21-23 
{Hermann]). 

4 Cf. Timaeus 34 a 8-3 1 and B 8-9, 92 ὁ 4-9, and Critias 
106 a 3-4 (one of the passages cited by Plutarch himself in 
De An. Proc. in Timaeo 1017 c). 

¢ Timaeus 38 B 6-7. 

7 Cf. Timaeus 27 Ὁ 6—28 a 4 and 38 ὁ 1-3. 


89 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1007) ἥλιος ἐπιστάτης ὧν Kal σκοπὸς᾽ ὁρίζειν Kat βρα- 
E βεύειν καὶ ἀναδεικνύναι καὶ ἀναφαίνειν μεταβο- 

Ἁ \ a a ld ’ al 3 ’ 
Ads καὶ ὥρας, at πάντα φέρουσι καθ᾽ “Ἡράκλειτον, 
2 Ἂ δὲ ἢν ἀλλὰ A , \ 
οὐ" φαύλων οὐδὲ μικρῶν adda τῶν μεγίστων Kal 
κυριωτάτων τῷ ἡγεμόνι καὶ πρώτῳ" θεῷ γίγνεται 

συνεργός. 


ZHTHMA Θ΄ 


1. Περὶ τῶν τῆς ψυχῆς" δυνάμεων ἐν Ἰ]ολιτείᾳ 
Πλάτωνος τὴν τοῦ λογιστικοῦ καὶ θυμοειδοῦς 
καὶ ἐπιθυμητικοῦ συμφωνίαν ἁρμονίᾳ" μέσης καὶ 
ὑπάτης καὶ νήτης εἰκάσαντος ἄριστα διαπορήσειεν 
ἄν τις πότερον κατὰ τῆς μέσης τὸ θυμοειδὲς ἢ 
τὸ λογιστικὸν ἔταξεν: αὐτὸς" γὰρ ἔν γε τούτοις 
οὐ δεδήλωκεν. ἡ μὲν οὖν κατὰ τόπον" τῶν μερῶν 

F τάξις εἰς τὴν τῆς μέσης χώραν τίθεται τὸ θυμο- 
ewes τὸ δὲ λογιστικὸν εἰς τὴν τῆς ὑπάτης. τὸ 
γὰρ ἄνω καὶ πρῶτον ὕπατον οἱ παλαιοὶ προσ- 

1 (ἐπιταχθεὶς ἐπέδσκοπος -Reinhardt (Hermes, Ixxvii 
[1949], p. 229, n. 1). 


2 οὐδὲ -J? (δὲ added superscript), a, A, β᾽ (δὲ erased -β3), 
y, E, B, en 
3 καὶ πρώτῳ -omitted by ¢€3; καὶ mpwricrw -Escorial 
T- δ -ὅ. 
ὶ τῆς το τῶν -J1, δ: περὶ -deleted by Hartman 
(De 2 Platarho, 586). 
5 ernabdlalaes : λογικοῦ -MSS. 
ἡ ονίαν -Β. β «λογικὸν -X, €, ἢ. 
8 Writenbach (cf. 1001 p supra); οὗτος -MSS. 
® κατὰ τὸν τόπον -Voss. 16, Escorial T-11-5. 


« Cf. Homeric Hymn ii (Demeter), 62, cited by Hubert for 
σκοπός used of Helios. 

> Heraclitus, frag. B 100 (D.-K. and Walzer) =frag. 34 
(Bywater) with G. S. Kirk, Heraclitus: The Cosmic Frag- 
ments (Cambridge, 1954), pp. 294-305. 


90 








PLATONIC QUESTIONS vit-1x, 1007 


and revolutions. The sun, being overseer and 
sentinel? of these for defining and arbitrating and 
revealing and displaying changes and seasons which 
according to Heraclitus ὃ bring all things, turns out 
to be collaborator with the sovereign and primary 
god ὁ not in paltry or trivial matters but in those 
that are greatest and most important. 


QUESTION IX 


1. Azour the faculties of the soul in the Republic, 
where ὦ Plato likened excellently well the conson- 
ance of the rational and mettlesome and appetitive 
to a concord of intermediate and topmost and nether- 
most strings,* one might raise the question whether 
it is the mettlesome or the rational that he gave the 
rank of intermediate, for in this passage he has not 
made it clear himself. Now, the local disposition 
of the parts does put the mettlesome in the position 
of the intermediate and the rational in that of the 
topmost string. For what is above and first the 
ancients styled topmost,f even as Xenocrates calls 


¢ Cf. τὸν ἀνωτάτω θεόν (1000 © [Question II init.] supra). 

4 Republic 443 vp 5-7. 

¢ The note of lowest pitch in the scale was called “ top- 
most’ (scil. string); and its octave, that of highest pitch, 
was called “ nethermost”’’: cf. Nicomachus, //armonices 
Man. 3 (Musici Scriptores Graeci, p. 241, 19-23 [Jan]) ; 
Theon Smyrnaeus, p. 51, 12-14 (Hiller); Chalcidius, Platonis 
Timaeus, p. 111, 7-11 (Wrobel) =p. 93, 8-11 (Waszink) ; and 
Plutarch, De An. Proc. in Timaeo 1021 a infra(... βαρύτερον 
ny dca ws ὑπάτη πρὸς νήτην. . . ὀξύτερον ὡς νήτη πρὸς 
ὕὉπατΤῊὴν 

f "CF. [Aristotle], De Mundo 397 Ὁ 24-26; Aristides 
Quintilianus, De Musica i, 6 (p. 8, 8-9 and 27- 28 { Winning- 


ton-Ingram)]). 
91 


(1001) 


1008 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


, 1 L= , ’ \ > \ 
nyopevov’ 7' Kat Eevoxpatns Δία τὸν ἐν μὲν 
a S 
τοῖς" κατὰ ταὐτὰ καὶ ὡσαύτως ἔχουσιν ὕπατον κα- 
λ im , \ eo ae ae ,ὕ 5 / 6 \ 
εἶ veatov δὲ Tov* ὑπὸ σελήνην, πρότερον" δὲ 


“ \ aA 3 7 A A “ 
Ὅμηρος τὸν τῶν ἀρχόντων ἄρχοντα θεὸν ὕπατον 


“ \ ~ 
κρειόντων προσεῖπε. Kat’ δικαίως τῷ Kpati- 
9 ͵, \ ” 8 , ε PrP e 
στῳ ἀποδέδωκε τὴν ἄνω “χώρον ἡ φύσις, ὥσπερ 
κυβερνήτην ἐνιδρύσασα TH κεφαλῇ τὸν λογισμὸν 
ἔσχατον δὲ καὶ νέατον ἀποικίσασα πόρρω τὸ 
ἐπιθυμητικόν. ἡ γὰρ κάτω νεάτη προσαγορεύεται 
τάξις, ὡς δηλοῦσιν αἱ τῶν νεκρῶν κλήσεις νερτέρων 
καὶ ἐνέρων προσαγορευομένων" ἔνιοι δὲ «καὶ τῶν 
ἀνέμων φασὶ τὸν κάτωθεν ἐκ τοῦ ἀφανοῦς πνέοντα 

ἐδ ἣ -omitted by J}, 
᾿ ἐόν μὲν ἐν τοῖς J} ἢ Flin : τὸν μὲν τοῖς HB: 
3 καὶ -omitted by X ; κατὰ αὐτὰ καὶ He κατὰ τὰ αὐτὰ 
καὶ -all other MSS. 4 TO ΕἼ: 5 τὴν σελήνην ἢ, Β. 
δ πρότερον OY PTE 1: πρῶτον ἘΠ’ δ ; πρότερος -all 
other mss. 
7 καὶ -omitted by Jj g. 8. τὴν ἄνω -omitted by 9, g 











» 


α Xenocrates, frag. 18 (Ifeinze). ‘* Nethermost Zeus ”’ is 
the chthonian Zeus or Hades (cf. Aeschylus, Supplices 156- 


(158 and 230-231 [with E. Fraenkel on Agamemnon 1386- 


1387]; Euripides, frag. 912, 1-3 and 6-8 [Nauck, Trag. 
Graec. Frag.”, p. 658] ; Pausanias, ii, 24, 4 with Proclus, /n 
Platonis Cratylum, pp. 83, 24-84, 1 [Pasquali]), whose 
domain, however, is no longer subterranean but is the whole 
sublunar region of the universe (cf. De Facie 942 ν and 948 c 
[L.C.L. xii, p. 195, note d and p. 201, note c]; P. Beyancé, 
Rev. Etudes Grecques, \xv [1952], pp. 334-335 ; W. Burkert, 
Weisheit und Wissenschaft |Niirnberg, 1962], pp. 344-346). 
By ‘“‘ topmost Zeus’ Xenocrates may have meant to refer 
to the monad which he is said to have given the station of 
father reigning ἐν οὐρανῷ, to have styled Zeus and νοῦς, and 
to have regarded as πρῶτος θεός (frag. 15 [Heinze] =Dow. 
Graeci, p. 304 αὶ 1-7). To establish strict correspondence 
between the present passage (frag. 18) and frags. 15 and 5, 
however, one must assume that Xenocrates posited a Ζεὺς 


92 


PLATONIC QUESTIONS rx, 1007-1008 


Zeus who is among things invariable and identical 
topmost but nethermost him who is beneath the 
moon“ and earlier Homer styled the god who is 
ruler of rulers topmost of lords.® Nature has also 
duly assigned the position above to what is most ex- 
cellent by establishing the reason like a pilot in the 
head and making the appetitive part dwell last and 
nethermost in distant banishment.¢ For the station 
underneath is styled nethermost, as is made clear 
by the appellations of the dead, who are styled 
nether and infernal ; and some people say that of 
the winds too it is the one blowing from underneath 
out of the unseen pole? that has been named 


μέσος also (cf. A. B. Krische, Die theologischen Lehren 
der griechischen Denker [Géttingen, 1840], p. 324; H. J. 
Kramer, Der Ursprung der Geistmetaphysik [Amsterdam, 
1964], p. 37, ἢ. 58 and p. 82, n. 209; H. Happ, Parusia- 
Festgabe fiir Johannes Hirschberger [Frankfurt am Main, 
1965], p. 178, n. 101) ; and, had he done so, it is unlikely that 
Plutarch would have omitted mention of it in this context. 
In Quaest. Conviv. 745 8 the Deltphian muses are said to have 
been named Ὑπάτη. Méon, and Neary from the regions of 
the universe guarded by each of them and not—as, in fact, 
is asserted by Censorinus (frag. 12 =p. 65, 13-15 (Hultsch])— 
from the musical notes or strings ; but, even if this passage 
too derived from Xenocrates (Ileinze, Xenokrates, p. 76), the 
latter may well have treated Zeus only in his two commonly 
ee aspects as ὕψιστος and χθόνιος (cf. Pausanias, ii, 
2, 8). 

δ Tliad viii, 31; Odyssey i, 45 and 81 and xxiv, 473. 

¢ From Timaeus 44 τὸ 3-6 and 69 ἢ 6—71 a 3(n.b. 70 κε 
6-7), but the figure of reason as a pilot comes from Phaedrus 
247 c 7-8; cf. Albinus, Hpitome xxiii (p. 111 [Louis] =p. 176, 
9-19 [Hermann]) and Apuleius, De Platone i, 13 (p. 97, 2-12 
[Thomas]) and Philo Jud., Leg. Allegor. iii, 115-118 (i, pp. 
138, 27-139, 17 [Cohn)}). 

4 Cf. [Aristotle], De Mundo 394 Ὁ 31-32 ; Joannes Lydus, 
De Mensibus iv, 119 (p. 157, 14-15 [Wuensch]). 


09 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


, ἢ , ἃ 3 Si sa ” | 
(1008) νότον ὠνομάσθαι. ἣν οὖν τὸ ἔσχατον ἔχει πρὸς 
“ 9 / \ \ / \ A 7 
TO πρῶτον ἀντίθεσιν καὶ TO νέατον πρὸς TO ὕπα- 
τον ταύτην τοῦ ἐπιθυμητικοῦ πρὸς τὸ λογιστικὸν 
ἔχοντος, οὐκ ἔστιν ἀνωτάτω μὲν εἶναι καὶ πρῶτον 
“ A ‘9 Ff A ik fas ay cD ae 4 
ὕπατον δὲ μὴ εἶναι τὸ λογιστικὸν ἀλλὰ ἕτερον. 
Β οἱ γὰρ ὡς κυρίαν δύναμιν αὐτῷ τὴν τῆς μέσης 
ἀποδιδόντες. ἀγνοοῦσιν ὅτι τὴν κυριωτέραν ἀφαι- 
ροῦνται THY? τῆς ὑπάτης, μήτε τῷ θυμῷ μήτε τῇ 
ἐπιθυμίᾳ προσήκουσαν: ἑκάτερον γὰρ ἄρχεσθαι 
καὶ ἀκολουθεῖν οὐδέτερον δ᾽ ἄρχειν ἢ" ἡγεῖσθαι 
τοῦ λογιστικοῦ πέφυκεν. ἔτι δὲ “μᾶλλον τῇ φύσει 
φανεῖται τὸ θυμοειδὲς τῷ τόπῳ τὴν μέσην ἔχον 
ἐκείνων τάξιν". εἴ ye δὴ τῷ μὲν" λογιστικῷ τὸ 
ἄρχειν τῷ δὲ θυμοειδεῖ τὸ ἄρχεσθαι καὶ τὸ ἄρχειν 
κατὰ φύσιν ἐστίν, ὑπηκόῳ μὲν ὄντι τοῦ λογισμοῦ 
κρατοῦντι δὲ καὶ κολάζοντι τὴν ἐπιθυμίαν ὅταν 
’ ἔχει καὶ -J}, g. 
2 μὴ -omitted by J?, 
3 λογικὸν -J, δ. 
© Atter these words at the end of folio 6 v the remainder 
of ἢ from οἱ γὰρ is by a different hand. 
τὴν -omitted by J, g (ἀφαιροῦντα τὴν -Bonon.). 
ἢ -omitted by J, g. 
<> τῷ τόπῳ -Hubert. 
τάξιν -omitted by Voss. 16, Escorial T-11-5. 
μὲν -omitted by J}, 'g 
ἄρχεσθαι Kai τὸ ΚΑΛῸΝ by J}, g 


---  --- -..-.-..-.Ξ--.  -μΞ.. 


α The derivation of νότος (the “ moist ” wind or rain-w ind) 
from véaros, as false as would be that of ‘‘ thunder” from 
“under,” is probably reflected in τοῦ νότου πνέοντος ἀπὸ 
τῶν κάτω τόπων Of Heracliti Quaestiones Homericae 47 (cf. 
Hermias, In Platonis Phaedrum, p. 29, 7-8 {(Couvreur]) and 
n “ Auster... qui et Notus, ex humili flans, .. .᾽ of Isidore 
(De Natura Rerum xxxvii, 3) and persists in the etymological 
verses of Johannes Mauropus (R. Reitzenstein, Geschichte der 
griechischen Etymologika | Leipzig, 1897], p. 174, lines 37-38). 


04 


on nn on 


~ 
ΦΦ 


PLATONIC QUESTIONS 1x, 1008 


thunder-gust.*_ Since, then, the opposition of last 
to first and of nethermost to topmost is the relation 
in which the appetitive part stands to the rational, 
it is not possible for the rational to be furthest above 
and first and yet for another than it to be topmost. 
For those who assign it the réle of the intermediate 
on the ground that this is a sovereign function ὃ fail 
to understand that they are eliminating the more 
sovereign function of the topmost, which befits 
neither mettle nor appetite, for to be ruled and to 
follow is natural to either of these but to rule or to 
lead the rational is natural to neither.¢ From their 
nature it will be still more apparent that the mettle- 
some part has the locally intermediate station among 
them,? if in fact ruling is natural to the rational but 
being ruled and ruling to the mettlesome, which, 
while obedient to the reason, dominates and chastises 
the appetite whenever it disobeys the reason.? Also, 

Cf 1009 A infra: τὴν δὲ πρώτην ἔχει Kal κυριωτάτην 
δύναμιν ὡς μέση. .. 

¢ Cf. De Virtute Morali 442 a with Plato, Republic 441 
rE 4—442 p1; and De Virtute Morali 442 σ (τὸ δὲ παθητικὸν 

τοῦ λογιζομένου καὶ φρονοῦντος εἰσακούειν . . . καὶ ὑπείκειν 
.. « πέφυκεν) with Aristotle, Lth. Nic. 1102 Ὁ 25-31, with 
Eth. Eud, 1219 Ὁ 28-31, and with Iamblichus, Protrepticus, 
p. 41, 20-22 (Pistelli). 

4 The argument, which hitherto has turned on the meaning 
of ὕπατον and νέατον, now is based upon the nature of the 
parts of the soul; but its purpose is still to prove that the 
mettlesome part is in the locally middle position of the three. 
Hubert was mistaken, therefore, in wishing to construe τῷ 
τόπῳ 85 an “ instrumental ’’ in comparison with τῇ φύσει and 
in emending the text to this end. 

« Cf. Proclus, In Platonis Rem Publicam i, pp. 211, 7-212, 
20 (Kroll) and Stobaeus, Mel. i, 49, 27 (p. 355, 10-12 [Wachs- 
muth]); and for the characterization of the mettlesome part 
ef. Plato, Republic 441°e 5-6 and Timaeus 70 a 2-7. 


95 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1008) ἀπειθῇ τῷ λογισμῷ. καὶ" καθάπερ, ἐν γράμμασι 
τὰ ἡμίφωνα μέσα" τῶν ἀφώνων ἐστὶ καὶ τῶν 
C φωνηέντων τῷ πλέον ἐκείνων ἠχεῖν" ἔλαττον δὲ 
τούτων, οὕτως ἐν τῇ ψυχῇ τοῦ ἀνθρώπου τὸ θυμο- 
ewes οὐκ ἀκράτως παθητικόν ἐστιν ἀλλὰ φαντα- 
σίαν καλοῦ πολλάκις ἔχει μεμιγμένην ἀλόγῳ" τῇ" 
τῆς τιμωρίας" ὀρέξει." καὶ Πλάτων αὐτὸς εἰκάσας 
συμφύτῳ ζεύγει καὶ ἡνιόχῳ τὸ τῆς ψυχῆς εἶδος 
ἡνίοχον μέν, ὡς παντὶ δῆλον, ἀπέφηνε τὸ λογιστι- 
κὸν τῶν δὲ ἵππων τὸ μὲν περὶ τὰς" ἐπιθυμίας 
ἀπειθὲς καὶ ἀνάγωγον παντάπασι περὶ ὦτα λά- 
cov,’ κωφόν, μάστιγι μετὰ κέντρων μόγις" ὑπεῖ- 
\ \ \ + es \ \ 7! ~ 
Kov To δὲ θυμοειδὲς εὐήνιον τὰ πολλὰ τῷ λογισμῷ 
καὶ σύμμαχον. ὥσπερ οὖν συνωρίδος οὐχ ὁ 
« / ᾽ὔ 3 3 ~ A ’ ᾽ὔ 9 Ἁ ~ 
Ὁ ἡνίοχός ἐστιν ἀρετῇ καὶ δυνάμει μέσος ἀλλὰ τῶν 
σ ς / \ ~ e / / \ 
ἵππων ὁ φαυλότερος μὲν τοῦ ἡνιόχου βελτίων δὲ 
τοῦ ὁμοζύγου, οὕτω τῆς ψυχῆς οὐ τῷ" κρατοῦντι 
τὴν μέσην" ἀπένειμε τάξιν ἀλλὰ ᾧ πάθους μὲν 
καὶ -omitted by J}, g, a 
καὶ (instead of vite) -J}, 1 g. 
Leonicus ; ἔχειν -Mss. 
Xylander, Stephanus ; : ἀλόγως -MSS. 
τῇ -omitted ae J+, g,n 
μωρίας -A, 8, E, B, Voss. 16, Escorial T-11-5, Bonon. 
ἕξει : 
τὰς -omitted by g. 
περὶ ᾧ fae -J ; περὶ τὰ ὦτα λάσιον -γ. 
10 μόγις -J, g (so Plato, Phaedrus 258 Ἑ 4): μόλις -all 
other Mss. 
11 καὶ σύμμαχον τῷ λογισμῷ -B ; καὶ λογισμῷ σύμμαχον -N. 
12 οὕτω N. : 
3 γὴν τῆς μέσης -\, J, g, β. 


’ 
eo ὦ - oan Pe © Ὁ ep 








$ Cf. Quaest. Conviv. 738 D-E ; Plato, Philedus 1S B 8-c 6 
(n.b. τά τε ἄφθογγα καὶ ἄφωνα ... καὶ τὰ φωνήεντα Kal τὰ 


μέσα) With Cratylus 424. ¢ 5-8 and Theaetetus 203 κ 2-7. 
06 





PLATONIC QUESTIONS 1x, 1008 


just as among letters the semivowels are inter- 
mediate between the mutes and the vowels by having 
more sound than the former and less than the latter,* 
so in the soul of man the mettlesome part is not 
purely affective but frequently has a mental image 
of what is fair,» though one commingled with what 
is irrational, the yearning for retribution.¢ Plato 
too, when he likened the structure of the soul to a 
composite of team and charioteer,* represented, as 
is clear to everyone, the rational part as charioteer 
and in the team of horses represented as shaggy 
about the ears, deaf, scarcely yielding to whip and 
goads ὁ the contumacy and utter indiscipline of the 
appetites but the mettlesome part as mostly tract- 
able to the reason and allied with it.f Now, as in the 
car and pair it is not the charioteer that is inter- 
mediate in virtue and function but that one of the 
horses which is worse than the charioteer but better 
than its yoke-fellow, so in the soul Plato allotted the 
intermediate station not to the dominant part but 

> Cf. ὁ θυμὸς ὑπερορᾷ μὲν σώματος εἰς ἀσώματον δὲ ἀγαθὸν 
βλέπει τὴν τιμήν (Proclus, Jn Platonis Rem Publicam, i, p. 
235, 16-18 [Kroll] with i, p. 211, 25-26 and p. 225, 27-30 and 
p. 226, 13-17 [Kroll]). 

¢ Of. ὄρεξις τιμωρητική (Proclus, In Platonis Rem Publicam 
i, p. 208, 14-18 [Kroll]) and τὸ ἀντιλυπήσεως ὀρέγεσθαι (ibid.) 
with Plutarch, De Virtute Morali 442 B (ὄρεξιν ἀντιλυπήσεως) 
and Aristotle, De Anima 403 a 30-31, 

ἃ Phaedrus 246 a 6-7. 

¢ Phaedrus 253 π 4-5, 

t In Phaedrus 247 8 2 the vehicles of the gods are called 
εὐήνια and in Republic 441 © 5-6 the mettlesome part of the 
soul is characterized as ὑπήκοον καὶ σύμμαχον τοῦ λογιστικοῦ 
(see note 6 on 1008 B supra); but in the Phaedrus these terms 
are not used of the nobler horse, though he is said to be 
εὐπειθὴς τῷ ἡνιόχῳ (Phaedrus 254 a 1) and to be guided 
κελεύσματι μόνον καὶ λόγῳ (253 D T-£ 1). 

97 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


nv ~ aA 3 9 r 
(1008) ἧττον᾽ ἢ τῷ (τρίτῳ μᾶλλον δ᾽ THY πρώτῳ 
λόγου δὲ μᾶλλον ἢ τῷ τρίτῳ (feroy δ᾽ 7 τῷ 
πρώτῳ" μέτεστιν. αὕτη γὰρ ἡ τάξις καὶ τὴν 
τῶν συμφωνιῶν ἀναλογίαν φυλάττει, τοῦ μὲν θυμο- 
ειἰδοῦς πρὸς τὸ λογιστικὸν' ὡς ὑπάτην τὸ διὰ τεσ- 
σάρων πρὸς δὲ τὸ ἐπιθυμητικὸν ὡς νήτην τὸ διὰ 
πέντε τοῦ δὲ λογιστικοῦ πρὸς" τὸ ἐπιθυμητικὸν 
ὡς ὑπάτη" πρὸς νήτην τὸ διὰ πασῶν. ἐὰν δὲ τὸν 
λογισμὸν εἰς τὸ μέσον ἕλκωμεν, ἔσται πλέον ὁ 
\ Ua ey y , ag » om 
E θυμὸς ἀπέχων τῆς ἐπιθυμίας, ὃν" ἔνιοι τῶν φιλο- 
σόφων ἐπιθυμίᾳ ταὐτὸν εἶναι διὰ ὁμοιότητα νο- 
μίζουσιν. 
a) \ \ a / . ’ 9 \ a 
2. Ἢ τὸ μὲν τοῖς τόποις ἀπονέμειν" τὰ πρῶτα 
καὶ τὰ μέσα καὶ τὰ τελευταῖα γελοῖόν ἐστιν, αὐτὴν 
τὴν ὑπάτην ὁρῶντας ἐν μὲν λύρᾳ" τὸν ἀνωτάτω" 
καὶ πρῶτον ἐν δ᾽ αὐλοῖς τὸν κάτω καὶ τὸν τελευ- 
1 πλέον ἌΡ ΔῊ (Op. Philol., p. 340). 
2 <...> -added by W yttenbach. 
3 ζ. . .> -added by Wyttenbach. 
᾿ ΡΝ -a, A, Bi, E, B; e. 
5 δὲ -omitted by J}, gies 
4 πρὸς -omitted by aL £3 .τὸ de λογιστικὸν πρὸς -Escoria] 
11-5. ὑπάτην - 
~*~ ὧν -n, Voss. 16, Bonon. 
: νέμειν -X. 
ἐν μὲν τῇ λύρᾳ -J, δ. 
ἀνώτερον -J', δ᾽ : τερον superscript over wrd -Ν΄. 


T- 


10 


4 Proclus (dn Platonis Rem Publicam i, pp. 212, 26-213. 
16 [Kroll]) also makes the mettlesome part intermediate ; ; but 
according to him its relation to the rational part is that of the 
fifth and to the appetitive that of the fourth, which implies 
that the appetitive part is ὑπάτη and the rational part νήτη 
(cf. e.g. De An. Proc. in Timaeo 1019 Ὁ-Ὲ infra), the argument 
for this being that, while it makes the interval between 
mettlesome and rational greater than that between mettle- 


98 





PLATONIC QUESTIONS 1x, 1008 


to that in which the affective component is less than 
in the <third but greater than in the) first and the 
component of reason greater than in the third (but 
less than in the first). The fact is that this disposi- 
tion also preserves the proportion of the conson- 
ances, of the mettlesome to the rational as topmost 
string the fourth and to the appetitive as nethermost 
the fifth and of the rational to the appetitive as top- 
most to nethermost the octave *; but if we pull the 
reason into the middle, it will remove to a greater 
distance from the appetite the mettle, which because 
of its similarity to appetite some of the philosophers 
believe to be identical with it.? 

2. Or © is it ridiculous to allot to local positions 
the status of first and intermediate and last, seeing 
that the topmost itself, while on the lyre it occupies 
the position furthest above and first, on the pipes 
occupies the one underneath and last ¢ and that the 


some and appetitive, it preserves the greater consonance of 
the mettlesome with the rational, the fifth being μᾶλλον 
συμφωνία than the fourth. Yet elsewhere, in the divine ἁρμονία 
of mind, soul, and body it is σῶμα that is νήτη and νοῦς that 
is ὑπάτη to the μέση of soul (/n Platonis Rem Publicam ii, 
p. 4, 15-21 [Kroll]). 

> Cf. De Virtute Morali 442 B (’ApiororéAns .. . τὸ μὲν 
θυμοειδὲς τῷ ἐπιθυμητικῷ προσένειμεν ws ἐπιθυμίαν τινὰ τὸν θυμὸν 
ὄντα...). Itis ita πεν that Plutarch had in mind here such 
classifications as those of S.V.F. iii, frag. 396, to which 
Hubert refers, especially since what he emphasizes as 
characteristic of Stoic doctrine is the denial that τὸ παθητικὸν 
καὶ ἄλογον is distinct from τὸ λογικόν (De Virtute Morali 
441 c-p and 446 r—447 a, De Sollertia Animalium 961 pv, 
De An. Proc. in Timaeo 1025 pv). 

¢ See note c on 1003 a supra and note c on De Comm. Not. 
1075 F infra. 

4 Cf. Aelian Platonicus quoted by Porphyry, Jn Ptole- 
maei Harmonica, p. 34, 22-28 (Diiring). 

99 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


Ως 


(1008) ταῖον- én dyowoart ire, δὲ ὴθιφοόδη ἡρίδη dl Ὁ ΤΣ 
atov ἐπέχουσαν᾽ ETL ὃὲ τὴν μέσην, ἐν ᾧ τις ἂν 
/ ἴω 7 ,ὔ e , ς Ἂ 
χωρίῳ τῆς λύρας θέμενος ὡσαύτως ἁρμόσηται," 
/ 3 7 ‘ Ὁ f , 
φθεγγομένην ὀξύτερον μὲν ὑπάτης βαρύτερον δὲ 
/ \ \ > θ λ \ ? 3 \ / \ 
νήτης ; καὶ yap ὀφθαλμὸς οὐκ ἐν παντὶ ζῴῳ τὴν 
αὐτὴν ἔχει τάξιν, ἐν παντὶ δὲ καὶ πανταχοῦ 
κείμενος κατὰ φύσιν ὁρᾶν ὁμοίως πέφυκεν. ὥσπερ 
IF οὖν ὁ παιδαγωγὸς οὐ πρόσθεν ἀλλ᾽ ὄπισθεν βαδίζων" 
ἄγειν λέγεται, καὶ 6 τῶν Γρώων στρατηγὸς 
ek , \5 , , 
ὁτὲ μέν τε μετὰ πρώτοισι φάνεσκεν 
” 3.53 , ’ 
ἄλλοτε δ᾽ ἐν πυμάτοισι κελεύων 
ς / 6 o> “4 ὡς \ A ͵ , 
ἑκατέρωθι" δ᾽ ἣν πρῶτος καὶ τὴν πρώτην δύναμιν 
εἶχεν, οὕτω τὰ τῆς ψυχῆς μόρια δεῖ μὴ τοῖς τόποις 
’ὔ’ \ A ἈΠῸ > \ 4 / 
καταβιάζεσθαι μηδὲ Tots ὀνόμασιν ἀλλὰ τὴν δύνα- 
\ \ > ’ > / \ \ “A 4 
1009 μιν Kal τὴν ἀναλογίαν ἐξετάζειν. τὸ yap TH θέσει 
~ “Ἐ Α “A ~ 
πρῶτον ἱδρῦσθαι τὸ λογιστικὸν ἐν TH σώματι τοῦ 
x 
ἀνθρώπου κατὰ συμβεβηκός ἐστι" THY δὲ πρώτην 
, 
ἔχει Kal κυριωτάτην δύναμιν ὡς μέση πρὸς ὑπάτην 
ὶ \ las 
μὲν τὸ ἐπιθυμητικὸν νήτην δὲ TO θυμοειδές, TH’ 
χαλᾶν καὶ ἐπιτείνειν καὶ ὅλως συνῳδὰ καὶ σύμ- 
aA \ A 
φωνα ποιεῖν ἑκατέρου τὴν ὑπερβολὴν ἀφαιρῶν καὶ 
πάλιν οὐκ ἐῶν ἀνίεσθαι παντάπασιν οὐδὲ κατα- 
δαρθάνειν' τὸ γὰρ μέτριον καὶ τὸ" σύμμετρον 
τελευταῖον, ἀποφαίνοντα -N. 
ἑνώση ἂν -", g. ; 
θοῖτο ὡσαύτως ἁρμόσεται -Escorial T-11-5. 
ἀλλ᾽ ἔμπροσθεν βαδίζειν -J*, 6. 
ὁτὲ... vac. 5... μετὰ -ϊ; ὁτὲ μετὰ -g (no lacuna 
icated); ὁτὲ μὲν μετὰ -Β. } 
ἑκατέρωθεν -ε: Escorial T-11-5 ; ἑκατέρωθε -n, Voss. 16. 


TO -J; &> Qs A, Ys Ee B, €- 
τὸ -omitted by g. 


in 


oun ΦΩ͂ σι νι ὦ we 


100 


PLATONIC QUESTIONS 1x, 1008-1009 


intermediate moreover, wherever it is located on the 
lyre, if tuned in the same way, sounds higher than 
the topmost string and lower than the nethermost ? 4 
For the situation of the eye too is not the same in 
every animal; but, as in all and everywhere it is 
naturally placed, seeing is similarly natural to it.? 
As, then, the children’s tutor is said to lead, though 
he walks behind them and not before, and the general 
of the Trojans 

Now would appear in the foremost ranks of the battle, 

Then in the rearmost, urging them forward,° 

but in either place was first and had the foremost 
function, so the parts of the soul must not be con- 
strained by location or by nomenclature but their 
function and their proportion must be scrutinized. 
In fact it is incidental that in the body of man the 
rational part has been situated as first in local posi- 
tion ; but the foremost and most sovereign function 
belongs to it as intermediate in relation to the ap- 
petitive as topmost and to the mettlesome as nether- 
most inasmuch as it slackens and tightens and 
generally makes them harmonious and concordant 
by removing the excess from either and again not 
permitting them to relax entirely and to fall asleep,4 
for the moderate and the commensurate 6 are 


α Of. De Virtute Morali 444 e-r; Aristotle, Physics 224 
Ὁ 33-34; Chalcidius, Platonis Timaeus, Ὁ. 106, 13-17 
(Wrobel) =p. 89, 10-14 (Waszink). 

> Cf. De Facie 927 p—928 Β. 

¢ Iliad xi, 64-65. 

4 Cf. De Virtute Morali 444 c; Plato, Republic 441 = 9— 
442 a 2. 

e Cf. Plato, Philebus 64 © 6 (μετριότης Kai συμμετρία) and 
66 a 6-8 1 (summarized by Plutarch, De FH 391 c-p), where 
τὸ μέτριον is prior to τὸ σύμμετρον. 


101 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1009) ὁρίζεται μεσότητι. μᾶλλον δὲ τοῦτο" τέλος" ἐστὶ 
τῆς τοῦ λόγου δυνάμεως, μεσότητας" ἐν τοῖς 
7 - [2] e Ἁ a 4 5 
πάθεσι ποιεῖν, as ἱερὰς καλοῦσι Covv)ovatas, 
bs “ \ A x” \ \ / \ \ 
Β ἐχούσας τὴν τῶν ἄκρων πρὸς Tov λόγον καὶ πρὸς 
" \ ral , , 6 ’ \ ε 
ἄλληλα διὰ τοῦ λόγου σύγκρασιν" οὐ γὰρ ἡ 
συνωρὶς μέσον ἔχει τῶν ὑποζυγίων τὸ κρεῖττον, 
0" Ἁ iY ts 9 , - id > \ / 
οὐδὲ τὴν ἡνιοχείαν ἀκρότητα θετέον ἀλλὰ μεσότητα 
τῆς ἐν ὀξύτητι καὶ βραδυτῆτι τῶν ἵππων ἀμετρίας, 
“ e μ᾿; / 7 , > ie 
ὥσπερ ἡ τοῦ λόγου δύναμις ἀντιλαμβανομένη 
κινουμένων ἀλόγως τῶν παθῶν καὶ συναρμότ- 
\ εν > \ , 9.ϑ } ͵ \ 
τουσα περὶ αὑτὴν εἰς TO μέτριον, ἐλλείψεως Kal 
ὑπερβολῆς μεσότητα, καθίστησιν. 
1 μεσότητα -J', g. ; 
2 δὲ αὐτὸ τοῦτο -Ὦ, Voss. 16, Escorial T-11-5, Bonon.; 
αὐτό τε (Superscript after τοῦτο) -βὥ. 
3 γέλος implied by Amyot’s version, Wyttenbach (αὐτὸ 
τοῦτο τέλος) ; ἀτελές (ἀταλές -Voss. 16) -Mss. 
4 δυνάμεως, ὡς μεσότητας E, 
᾿ς 5. H. C.3 καλοῦσιν οὐσίας -Μ58. ; καλοῦσι καὶ ὁσίας -Em- 
perius (Op. Philol., p. 340), and implied by Amyot’s version. 
8 συγκρίνειν -8. _ 7 ἡλίου -J*, δ. 
8 ἀντιλαμβανομένους -n, Voss. 16, Escorial 'T-11-5. 
9 τὸ μέτριον -deleted by Hartman (De Plutarcho, p. 586). 


ee ee ee eee eee | 


@ Of. Albinus, Epitome xxx, 6 (p. 151, 4-7 [Louis] =p. 184, 
27-30 [Hermann]). 
> Cf. De Virtute Morali 443 c-p (. . . τοῦ λόγου . . . ὅρον 


A \ Ud 3 ’ os. A ‘ \ ᾽ ‘ 3 , 
τινὰ καὶ τάξιν ἐπιτιθέντος αὐτῷ καὶ τὰς ἠθικὰς ἀρετάς, .. . συμ- 





102 





PLATONIC QUESTIONS 1x, 1009 


defined by a mean ?—or rather this is the purpose of 
the faculty of reason, to produce in the affections 
means,® which are called ὁ sacred unions because 
they involve the combination of the extremes with 
the ratio and through the ratio with each other.¢ 
For in the case of the car and pair it is not the 
better of the yoked beasts that is intermediate, and 
the management of the reins must be reckoned not as 
an extreme but as a mean between the immoder- 
ate keenness and sluggishness of the horses, just as 
the faculty of reason, laying hold of the affections 
when they are in irrational motion and ranging 
them in concord about herself, reduces them to mo- 
deration,¢ a mean between deficiency and excess.’ 


μετρίας παθῶν Kai μεσότητας, ἐμποιοῦντος) and 444 ¢ (. . . ἐμ- 
ποιεῖ τὰς ἠθικὰς ἀρετὰς περὶ TO ἄλογον . . . μεσότητας οὔσας). 

¢ [ am unable to identify the subject of καλοῦσι. 

4 Cf. Proclus, In Platonis Timaeum ii, p. 22, 22-26 (Diehl) : 
τοῦτο (scil. τὸ μέσον) γάρ ἐστι δι᾽ οὗ πᾶσα ἀναλογία συνέστηκε, 
συνάγον τοὺς ἄκρους κατὰ τὸν λόγον καὶ διαπορθμεῦον τὸν λόγον 
ἀπὸ τῆς ἑτέρας δυνάμεως ἐπὶ τὴν λοιπήν . . . δι᾿ αὐτοῦ γὰρ ἡ 
ἀναλογία συνδεῖ τοὺς ἄκρους. 

¢ Cf. De Virtute Morali 444 B, 445 a (... εἰς τὸ μέτριον... 
καθιστᾶσα τῶν παθῶν ἕκαστον), 451 F(... ἐγγενομένης ὑπὸ λόγου 
ταῖς παθητικαῖς δυνάμεσι καὶ κινήσεσιν ἐπιεικείας καὶ μετριότητος). 

7 Cf. [Plato], Dejinitions 415 a 4 bcbecine hese 
ὑπερβολῆς Kai ἐλλείψεως) : Aristotle, De Part. Animal. 652 
b 17-19 and Politics 1295 b 4; Plutarch, Quomodo Quis 
Suos in Virtute Sentiat Profectus 84 a (. .. εἰς τὸ μέσον 
καθίστασθαι Kai μέτριον). 


108 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1009) ZHTHMA I’ 
1, Διὰ τί Πλάτων εἶπε τὸν λόγον ἐξ ὀνομάτων 
\ € ’ A 
καὶ ῥημάτων κεράννυσθαι; δοκεῖ yap πάντα 
\ A / A / ~ / / 
πλὴν δυεῖν τούτων τὰ μέρη τοῦ λόγου [᾿ἰλάτωνα 
μὲν μεθεῖναι “Ὅμηρον δὲ καὶ" νεανιευσάμενον εἰς 
ἕνα στίχον ἐμβαλεῖν ἅπαντα τοῦτον 


‘§ 


΄ 


> \ mex 3 , A \ / + 3 ἰοὺ 

αὐτὸς ἰὼν" κλισίηνδε, τὸ σὸν γέρας: ὀφρ᾽ εὖ 
εἰδῇς."ἡ 

καὶ γὰρ ἀντωνυμία καὶ μετοχὴ καὶ ὄνομα καὶ 

ῥῆμα καὶ πρόθεσις καὶ ἄρθρον καὶ σύνδεσμος καὶ 

ἐπίρρημα ἔνεστι" τὸ γὰρ “ de’? μόριον νῦν ἀντὶ 

τῆς “ εἰς ᾿᾿ προθέσεως τέτακται" τὸ yap “ κλι- 

, }} ma Ff > e Ὁ) i242 "a }) 45 
ainvoe ’’ τοιοῦτόν ἐστιν οἷον τὸ “᾿᾿Αθήναζε.᾽᾽ τί 
δὴ ῥητέον ὑπὲρ τοῦ Ι]λάτωνος ; 

Ἢ" ὅτι “ πρῶτον᾽ λόγον ᾿᾿ οἱ παλαιοὶ τὴν τότε 

1 πάντα -omitted by g. . 

2-H. Cy (μεθεῖναι -R. G. Bury, Proc. Cambridge Philol. 
Soc. for 1950-1951, N.S. 1, p. 31)3 λόγου μηθὲν Ὅμηρον δὲ 
καὶ -J, £3 λόγου μερῶν μηθὲν ἅμα καὶ -X, B, e, n, Voss. 16, 
.Bonon. ; λόγου μερῶν μηθὲν ἅμα ee VR. Pa εἰν καὶ -E; 
λόγου ... vac. 32 -a (erasure), 27 -A, 28 -y, 34 -B... καὶ: 
λόγου παραλιπόντα μηθὲν καὶ -Escorial T-11-5. : 

3 αὐτὸς δὲ ἰὼν -J. 4 εἰδὼς -X. 

5 76 -J', ὦ 6 ἢ -mss.; ἢ -Diibner. 

7 πρῶτον -omitted by J1, 8; πρῶτον ὅτι -B", τι, Voss. 16, 
Bonon., Escorial T-11-5. 

α This question is translated and discussed by J. J. Hart- 
man in De Avondzon des Heidendoms (Leiden, 1910), ii, 
pp. 22-30 and translated in part by A. von MoGrl in Die 
Grosse Weltordnung (Berlin/Wien/Leipzig, 1948), ii, pp. 
85-89 ; it is commented on in detail by O. Géldi, Plutarchs 
sprachliche Interessen (Diss. Ziirich, 1922), pp. 2-10. 

δ Sophist 262 c 2-7; ef. Cratylus 425 a 1-5 and 431 B 5-c 
1, Theaetetus 206 ἢ 1-5, and [Plato], Hpistle vii, 342 n 6-7 and 
$43 5 4-5; O. Apelt, Platonis Sophista (Lipsiae, 1897), 


104 





PLATONIC QUESTIONS x, 1009 


QUESTION X « 

1. Wuar was Plato’s reason for saying δ that speech 
is a blend of nouns and verbs? For it seems that 
except for these two Plato dismissed all the parts 
of speech whereas Homer in his exuberance went so 
far as to pack all together into a single line, the 
following : 


Tentward going myself take the guerdon that well you 
may know it.° 

In this there are in fact a pronoun and participle 
and noun and verb and preposition and article and 
conjunction and adverb,? for the suffix “ ward ”’ has 
here been put in place of the preposition “ to,” the 
expression “ tentward ”’ being of the same kind as 
the expression “ Athensward.’’ ¢ What, then, is to 
be said on behalf of Plato ? 

Or’ is it that the ancients styled “ primary 


p. 189 and F. M. Cornford, Plato’s Theory of Knowledge 
(London, 1935), pp. 307-308. 

¢ Iliad i, 185. 

¢ For these eight parts of speech cf. Dionysius 'Thrax, Ars 
Girammatica ὃ 11 (p. 23 1-2 [Uhlig]). As the Homeric line 
containing all of them the grammarians cite /liad xxii, 59 
(Scholia in Dionysii Thracis Artem Grammaticam, p. 58, 
13-19 and p. 357, 29-36 [Hilgard] ; Eustathius, Commentarc: 
ad Homeri Iliadem 1256, 60-61); and there the noun is 
δύστηνον, for the adjective (‘noun adjective” in older 
grammars {cf. O.E.D. s.v. “ noun ” 3]) was considered to be 
a kind of noun, ὄνομα ἐπίθετον (Dionysius Thrax, op. cit., 
§ 12 [p. 33, 1 and pp. 34, 3-35, 2] with Scholia. . ., p. 233, 
7-33 and p. 553, 11-17; ef. H. Steinthal, Geschichte der 
Sprachwissenschaft bei den Criechen und Rémern’*, ii [Ber- 
lin, 1891], pp. 251-256). 

e Cf. Etym. Magnum 761, 30-32 and 809, 8-9 (Gaisford) 
and further for μόριον as “ prefix” or “ suffix”? 141, 47-52. 

f See 1003 a and 1008 © supra and note 6 on De Comm. 
Not. 1075 ¥ infra. 

105 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


/ us > ral J 
(1009) καλουμένην πρότασιν' viv δ᾽ ἀξίωμα mpoonyo- 
ρευον, ὃ πρῶτον λέγοντες ἀληθεύουσιν ἢ ψεύδον- 
“- 3 > ἢ 
ται; τοῦτο δ᾽ ἐξ ὀνόματος καὶ ῥήματος συνέ- 
ἷΐ᾿ \ Ξ ¢ \ \ \ 
στῆηκεν, ὧν TO μὲν πτῶσιν οἱ διαλεκτικοὶ TO δὲ 
D κατηγόρημα καλοῦσιν. ἀκούσαντες γὰρ ὅτι Σω- 
7 aA \ 7 Ὁ / / 
κράτης φιλοσοφεῖ καὶ πάλιν ὅτι Σωκράτης πέτε- 
2 \ \ 3 A ’ 5 A \ a 
Tat, Tov μὲν ἀληθῆ λόγον εἶναι τὸν δὲ ψευδῆ 
"4 > A ¥ x / \ \ 
φήσομεν, οὐδενὸς ἄλλου προσδεηθέντες. καὶ yap 
εἰκὸς ἀνθρώπους ἐν χρείᾳ λόγου τὸ πρῶτον" καὶ 
φωνῆς ἐνάρθρου γενέσθαι, τάς τε πράξεις καὶ 
τοὺς πράττοντας αὐτὰς καὶ τὰ πάθη καὶ τοὺς 
͵ 3 ’ A μ᾿ > , 
πάσχοντας ἀλλήλοις διασαφεῖν καὶ ἀποσημαΐίνειν 
~ e 
βουλομένους. ἐπεὶ Towvy TH μὲν ῥήματι τὰ 
1 πρόφασιν -J}, δ. 5 πέτεται -Pohlenz : τρέπεται -MSS. 
τὸ πρῶτον ἐν χρείᾳ λόγου -J', δ ; τὸ πρῶτον -omitted 
by al. 


¢ Plato, Sophist 262 c 6-7 (τῶν λόγων 6 πρῶτός τε Kal 
σμικρότατος) and 9-10 (λόγον . . . ἐλάχιστόν τε καὶ πρῶτον) : : 
ef. hate hie De Interpretatione, p. 67, 20-30 and pp. 78, 
| 29-79, 9. | 
> Cf. [Apuleius], Περὲ ἑρμηνείας i (pp. 176, 15-177, 2 | 
[Thomas]); Galen, Institutio Logica i, 5 (with J. Mau’s note 
ad loc., Galen, Einfiihrung in die Logik [Berlin, 1960], pp. 
3-4) ; and Proclus, In Primum Euclidis El. Lib., pp. 193, 
18-194, 4 (Friedlein). For πρότασις used in the general sense 
of “ proposition” cf. Albinus, Epitome vi, 1 and 8 (p. 29, 
1-4 and 19-20 [Louis] =p. 158, 4-7 and 21-22 [Hermann]) and 
Aristotle himself (Anal. Prior. 24 a 16-17 with Alexander, 
Anal. Prior., Ὁ. 44, 16-23) ; and for ἀξίωμα as the Stoic term 
for this cf. besides the passage of Proclus just cited Ammo- 
nius, De Interpretatione, p. 2, 26 and Mates, Stoic Logic, 
pp. 27-33 and p. 132, 5.υ. ἀξίωμα. 
¢ Plato, Sophist 262 © 8-9 and 263 a 11-B 3; ef. [Apu- 
leius], Tlepi ἑρμηνείας iv (p. 178, 1-7 [Thomas]) and Ammo- 
nius, De Interpretatione, p. 18, 2-22 and pp. 26, 31-27, 4, It 


106 








PLATONIC QUESTIONS x, 1009 


speech ᾿᾿ 4 what then was called a pronouncement 
and now is called a proposition,® that in the enuncia- 
tion of which a truth or falsehood is first expressed ? ¢ 
And this consists of a noun and a verb, the former 
of which the dialecticians call subject and the latter 
predicate. For upon hearing “ Socrates philoso- 
phizes ’’ and again “ Socrates flies ’’ we should say 
without requiring anything else besides that the 
former is true speech and the latter false.e More- 
over, it is likely that men first felt need of speech 
and articulate sound / in desiring to designate and 
make quite clear to one another actions and their 
agents and patients and what they undergo. Since, 
then, with the verb we do make adequately clear 


was express Stoic doctrine that every proposition is either 
true or false (cf. Mates, Stoic Logic, pp. 28-29). 

4 Cf. [Apuleius], Περὶ ἑρμηνείας iv (p. 178, 12-15 
{Thomas]); Martianus Capella, iv, 393; and Mates, Stoic 
Logic, pp. 16-17 with notes 34-41 and p. 25 with notes 79-81. 
Notice the difference between Diogenes Laertius, vii, 58 and 
Plutarch’s statement (Mates, p. 16, ἢ. 34); and with πτῶσις 
as used by Plutarch here cf. besides Sextus, Adv. Math. xi, 
29 (Mates, p. 17, n. 40) Clement of Alexandria, Stromata 
vill, ix, 26, 4-5, cited by Pearson (Fragments, p. 75) in con- 
nexion with Stobaeus, Ecl. i, 12, 3 (p. 137, 3-6 [Wachsmuth]) 
=8.V.F. i, p. 19, 24-26. of διαλεκτικοί in the present passage 
as in [011 a and 1011 pb infra are the Stoics (cf. Aulus 
Gellius, xvi, viii, 1 and 8; Sextus, Pyrrh. Hyp. ii, 146 and 
247 and Adv. Math. viii, 93; Cicero, Acad. Prior. ii, 97; 
and see note d on De Stoic. Repug. 1045 r infra). 

¢ Plato, Sophist 263 a 8- 3. 

f i.e. λόγος in the sense of speech. Cf. De Sollertia 
Animalium 973 a (προφορικοῦ λόγου Kai φωνῆς ἐνάρθρου) with 
S.V.F. ii, p. 43, 18-20 (τῷ προφορικῷ λόγῳ -- ἐνάρθρους φωνάς 
[but in S.V.F. iii, p. 215, 35-36 ἡ σημαίνουσα ἔναρθρος 
φωνή, With which cf. S.V.F. ii, frag. 143]); and De An. 
Proc. in Timaeo 1026 a (λόγος δὲ λέξις ἐν φωνῇ σημαντικῇ 
διανοίας). ; 


107 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


/ τ οὐ / Pn. Mee i . \ 7, 
(1009) πράγματα καὶ τὰ πάθη τῷ δ᾽ ὀνόματι τοὺς πράτ- 
> / > / ~ 

TOVTAS αὐτὰ καὶ πάσχοντας ἀποχρώντως δηλοῦμεν, 
ὡς" αὐτὸς εἴρηκε, ταῦτα σημαίνειν ἔδοξε". τὰ δ᾽ 
ἄλλα φαίη τις ἂν οὐ σημαίνειν, οἷον οἱ στεναγμοὶ 
E καὶ oAoAvypot τῶν ὑποκριτῶν᾽ καὶ νὴ Δία πολ- 
λάκις' ἐπιμειδίασις" καὶ" ἀποσιώπησις ἐμφαντι- 
κώτερον ποιεῖ τὸν λόγον, οὐ μὴν ἀναγκαίαν" ἔχει" 
πρὸς τὸ σημαίνειν ὡς τὸ ῥῆμα καὶ τοὔνομα 
δύναμιν ἀλλ᾽ ἐπίθετόν τινα ποικίλλουσαν τὸν λόγον" 
ὥσπερ τὰ στοιχεῖα ποικίλλουσιν οἱ τὰ πνεύματα 
καὶ τὰς δασύτητας αὐτῶν ἐκτάσεις τε καὶ 
συστολὰς ἐνίων αὐτὰ καθ᾽ αὑτὰ" στοιχεῖα τιθέμε- 
, ~ » \ ὙΠ ΕΥΙ \ 
vot, πάθη μᾶλλον ὄντα καὶ συμβεβηκότα" καὶ 
\ 12 , e Ως. 7 ¢ 113 
διαφορὰς" στοιχείων, ws ἐδήλωσαν ot παλαιοὶ 


\ A ς ’ , 3 , 114 
διὰ τῶν ἑκκαίδεκα φράζοντες ἀποχρώντως Kal 


γράφοντες. 


” / \ 7 ~ 4 
ἔπειτα σκόπει μὴ παρακούωμεν Tod [ἰλάτω- 
F vos, ἐκ τούτων κεράννυσθαι τὸν λόγον οὐ διὰ 


1 +4 -omitted by J}, g. 
* Καὶ τε. 3 ἔγδοξος -J}, g. 
* δία πολλὰ πολλάκις -Ν. > ἐπι δα Ξ} Ὁ, 
‘ καὶ -X, a, ε: omitted by all other Mss. 
7 ἀνάγκην -J, 8: 8 ἔχειν -J. 
ἐκστάσεις -J}, g. 
10 καθ᾽ αὑτὰ (ἑαυτὰ -X) τὰ ἐπ a, A, y, E, B, 
11 συμβεβηκότως -J. 12 διαφθορὰς ig 
18 πολλοὶ -. 14 καὶ -omitted by g. 


== a i .- 5 Ὸο΄“ΠσΠρΠρΠς5΄“ΠΠΠὖΠὖΠὖὅὖὅΠἷΠ΄Πὖ ΄΄΄.......-ο-οθὖσ5ὖθϑοϑοϑ ῸἝὖ΄΄5ἕ͵'. :-Ὸτ τς... “΄“ΠῤΡᾷῸ΄΄΄Γ΄΄Γ΄͵-.- ὦἝὦ͵ ...... ὖὃΘῸΞ-Ὁ5.-ΠἐΠἐὀυὈΠῃ᾿... 


: « Sophist 262 a 3-7, B 6, and B 10-c 1; but Plato here 
speaks only of πράξεις and πράττοντες as signified by verbs 
and nouns. For Plutarch’s substitution of πράγματα for 
πράξεις cf. Scholia in Dionysii Thracis Artem Grammaticam, 
p. 215, 28-30 (Hilgard); Apollonius Dyscolus, De Con- 
structione i, 130 and iii, 58 (p. 108, 11-14 and pp. 323, 9-324, 


9 [Uhlig]). 
108 





PLATONIC QUESTIONS x, 1009 


acts and what is undergone and with the noun the 
agents and patients, as Plato has said himself, it 
seemed that these signify, whereas one might say 
that the rest like the groans and shouts of actors do 
not signify ; and, by heaven, suddenly falling silent 
with a smile often makes speech more expressive 
and yet has not the force requisite for signifying as 
do the verb and the noun but a certain supplementary 
force embellishing speech in the way that the letters 
are embellished by those who make independent 
ones of their breathings and aspirates and in some 
cases of their long and short quantities,? although 
these are rather modifications and incidental char- 
acteristics and variations of letters,° as the ancients 
showed by adequately expressing themselves in 
actually writing with sixteen letters.¢ 

2. In the second place, take care lest we fail to 
heed what Plato has said, that speech is a blend of 


> τὰ πνεύματα are the two “ breathings,” δασὺ καὶ ψιλόν 
(cf. Dionysius Thrax, Ars Grammatica, Suppl. i, p. 107, 4 
| Uhlig] and for the argument that such marks are letters cf. 
Scholia in Dionysi Thracis Artem Grammaticam, pp. 187, 
26-188, 21 and p. 496, 11-13 [Hilgard]) ; but τὰς δασύτητας 
refers to the aspirates 9, ¢, x (ef. Dionysius Thrax, -4rs 
Grammatica ὃ 6, p. 12, 5 [Uhlig]; Sextus, ddv. Math. i, 
103; Priscian, /nst. Grammatica i, 24-25=i, p. 19, 3-8 
[Ifertz]) and ἐκτάσεις τε καὶ συστολὰς ἐνίων to the distinction 
of η from ¢ and of w from ο (ef. Sextus, ddv. Math. i, 115). 

¢ Cf. Scholia in Dionysii Thracis Artem Grammaticam, 
p. 496, 19-24 (Hilgard). 

4 Cf. Plutarch, Quaest. Conviv. 738 r; Demetrius of 
Vhaleron, frag. 196 (Wehrli); Varro, De Antiquitate Lit- 
terarum, frag. 2 (Funaioli, Grammaticae Romanae I’rag- 
mentai, Ὁ. 184; ef. pp. 2 and 120 for L. Cincius, frag. 1 and 
Cn. Gellius, frag. 1); Pliny, V.H. vii, 192; Tacitus, Anz. 
xi, 14; Scholia in Dionysii Thracis Artem Grammaticam, 
pp. 34, 27-35, 13 and pp. 184, 7-12 and 185, 3-7 (Hilgard). 

109 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1009) τούτων εἰρηκότος, εἶθ᾽ ὥσπερ ὁ' τὸν λέγονταἶ τὸ 
φάρμακον ἐκ κηροῦ μεμῖχθαι καὶ χαλβάνης συκο- 
φαντῶν, ἐπεὶ τὸ πῦρ παρέλιπε καὶ τὸ ἀγγεῖον ὧν 
χωρὶς οὐκ ἐνῆν μεμῖχθαι, καὶ ἡμεῖς ὁμοίως ἐγκα- 
λῶμεν" ὅτι _guvdeopous καὶ προθέσεις καὶ τὰ 
τοιαῦτα παρῆκεν" οὐ γὰρ ἐκ τούτων ὁ λόγος ἀλλ᾽, 
εἴπερ ἄρα, διὰ τούτων καὶ οὐκ ἄνευ τούτων κεράν- 

{{ 


, 
1010 νυσθαι πέφυκεν. οὐ γάρ, ὥσπερ ὁ τὸ “᾿ τύπτει ᾽᾿" 


, Ἂ ΨΥ ae , 195 \ , ‘ 
φθεγξάμενος ἢ τὸ “τύπτεται ᾿" καὶ πάλιν τὸ 


, Ἂ \ 6 / j 
᾿ Σωκράτης ᾿ ἢ τὸ “ Ilv@ayopas” ἁμωσγέπως 
΄ \ ~ 
νοῆσαί τι Kat διανοηθῆναι παρέσχηκεν, οὕτω 
~ (( PES TINTS NA Fe Pusey POI CIEE fy) θ᾽ δὴ ἐΝ 
τοῦ “μέν ἢ “yap” ἢ “περί Kal? αὐτὸ 
/ A 
ἐκφωνηθέντος" ἔστιν ἔννοιάν τινα λαβεῖν" ἢ mpdy- 
> νὴ - \ 
ματος ἢ σώματος" ἀλλ᾽ ἐὰν μὴ περὶ ἐκεῖνα Kal 
> , 4 / ~ ld 
μετ᾽ ἐκείνων ἐκφέρηται, ψόφοις κενοῖς καὶ ἤχοις 
a > 
ἔοικεν: ὅτι ταῦτα μὲν οὔτε καθ᾽ αὑτὰ σημαίνειν 
5 4 3 na 
οὔτε pet ἀλλήλων οὐδὲν πέφυκεν, ἀλλ᾽ ὅπως ἂν 
> \ 
συμπλέκωμεν ἢ μιγνύωμεν εἰς ταὐτὸ συνδέσμους 
5 A 
καὶ ἄρθρα Kat προθέσεις, ἕν τι" πειρώμενοι κοινὸν 
3 " “A a 171 ’ ἀλλ wv ὃ λέ 
ἐξ αὐτῶν ποιεῖν," τερετίζειν ἐξ ον 7 διαλέγε- 
1 ὁ -omitted by J}, 
3 λέγον Ἣν and τα ΠΑΝ τς -α'. 
" ἐγκαλοῦμεν -J1, g. 
4 τύπτει -MSS. 3 τύπτειν -Basiliensis. 
5 χύπτεσθαι -Aldine, Basiliensis. 
᾿ παρέσχεν -J, 
? καθ᾽ αὑτὸ -omitted by K, B. 
8 φωνήεντός -J, g. 
® λαβεῖν τινα -X, ε. 
10. ἔν ιν Ξἢ. 


11 κοινὸν ποιεῖν ἐξ αὐτῶν -X. 


----.-.-.οο-.-.-.ς.- 


α The phrase, σῶμα ἢ πρᾶγμα σημαῖνον. occurs in the 
definition of ὄνομα given by Dionysius Thrax, Ars Gram- 


110 





PLATONIC QUESTIONS x, 1009-1010 


these, not that it is blended by means of them, and 
lest then like one who, when the medicine is said 
to be a mixture of wax and galbanum, carps at the 
omission of the fire and the receptacle, without 
which it could not have been mixed, we too similarly 
object that Plato disregarded conjunctions and pre- 
positions and the like, for it is not of these that 
speech is naturally blended but, if at all, by means 
of them and not without them. For it is not the case 
that as one by uttering “strikes ”’ or “ is struck ”’ 
and again ‘“ Socrates’ or “ Pythagoras ’’ has pro- 
vided something to conceive and have in mind some- 
how so, when “ indeed ”’ or “ for ᾿᾿ or “ about’ has 
been pronounced by itself, it is possible to get some 
conception of an act or an object*; but, unless 
these are expressions about those other words and 
in association with them, they resemble senseless 
sounds and noises. The reason is that they naturally 
signify nothing either by themselves or in association 
with one another ; but, however we may combine 
or mix together conjunctions and articles and pre- 
positions in trying to make of them a single thing 
in common, it will seem that we are babbling gib- 


matica § 12 (p. 24, 3-4 [Uhlig]). Since Plutarch has just 
given both verbs and nouns as counter-examples, however, 
πράγματος here is probably meant in the sense of τὰ πράγματα 
in 1009 ἢ supra (page 108, note a); cf. also Dionysius Hal., 
De Comp. Verb. xii, 69-70 (p. 46, 21 f. [Usener-Rader- 
macher]), ᾧ σημαίνει τι σῶμα ἢ πρᾶγμα, where the preceding 
οὔτε ὄνομα οὔτε ῥῆμα (ibid., p. 46, 18) indicates that πρᾶγμα 
means “‘ act’’ and not “ thing.” The use of σῶμα for “ ob- 
ject’ generally reflects the Stoic doctrine that all agents and 
patients—and so all entities—are σώματα (see notes f and g 
on De Comm. Not. 1073 © infra and cf. Apollonius Dyscolus, 
De Constructione i, 16 =p. 18, 5-8 [Uhlig}), 


111 


(010) 


= 


> 
εἰώθαμεν ἐπαινεῖν ἢ ψέγειν οὕτω πως λέγοντες 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


ofan" δόξομεν' ῥήματος δ᾽ ὀνόματι" συμπλεκομέ- 
Oba τὸ γενόμενον εὐθὺς διάλεκτός" ἐστι καὶ λόγος. 
ὅθεν εἰκότως ἔνιοι μόνα ταῦτα μέρη τοῦ λόγου τί- 
θενται: καὶ “Ὅμηρος ἴσως τοῦτο βούλεται δηλοῦν 
ἑκάστοτε λέγων 

μή “ὙΠ ἸῊἤ 2 ἊΨ 3 > / 

ἔπος τ᾽ EpaT ἔκ τ᾽ ὀνόμαζεν' 
" A \ ta “A ” Ὶ [ > ’ 
ἔπος γὰρ τὸ ῥῆμα καλεῖν εἴωθεν, ὥσπερ ἐν τούτοις 


Ἂν ᾽’ J «-- Ψ W wie 
ὦ γύναι, 7 μάλα τοῦτο ἔπος Gupadyes* ἔειπες 
καὶ 

χαῖρε, πάτερ ὦ ξεῖνε, ἔπος δ᾽ εἴπερ ti” λέλεκ- 

ται 

δεινόν, ἄφαρ τὸ φέροιεν ἀναρπάξασαι ἄελλαι. 

” \ , yw 3 3 7 ” 4 8 
οὔτε yap σύνδεσμον οὔτ᾽ ἀρθρον΄ οὔτε πρόθεσιν 
δεινόν ἐστι καὶ θυμαλγὲς εἰπεῖν ἀλλὰ ῥῆμα 
πράξεως eupavtiKov™ αἰσχρᾶς 7 πάθους τινὸς 
ἀνεπιτηδείου. διὸ καὶ ποιητὰς καὶ συγγραφεῖς 


1 διαλογίζεσθαι -J, δ. Ἶ “ὀνόματος -ς 
3 διάλογος -β', n, Voss. 16, Escorial T-11-5, Bonon. 
4 θυγαλγὲς -J?. 
ae ἔπος τ᾽ εἴπερ τε -β. n, Voss. 16, Escorial ‘T-1 1-5, Bonon. 
" βέβακται -Homer. 
ἡ ἄθερον Jt. 
* πρότερον εὖ ἧς 2. 
ῥίζα -J*, g. 
τῇ Ae -€. 
1 ἢ -Meziriac ; ἐκ -Mss. 





α “Blakes ‘Sophist 262 c 4-7 pee η 2-6. 

> Cf. [Apuleius], Περὶ ἑρμηνείας iv (p. 178, 4-7 Biren : 
Apollonius Dyscolus, De Constructione i, (p. 28, 6-9 
[Uhlig] with Priscian, Inst. Grammatica xvii, 22 =i, pp. 121, 
21-122, 1 [Hertz]); and Scholia in Dionysii Thracis ‘Artem 
Grammaticam, pp. 515, 19-517, 32 (Hilgard), where the 


112 








PLATONIC QUESTIONS x, 1010 


berish rather than speaking a language. When a 
verb is combined with a noun, however, the result 
is straightway language and speech. Wherefore it 
is reasonable that some people consider these alone 
to be parts of speech ®; and this perhaps is what 
Homer wants to make clear each time he says 


gave word to the thought and announced it,° 


for it was his custom to call the verb “‘ word,”’ as in 
these lines : 


Verily, woman, a heart-breaking word is this thou hast 
spoken 4 


and 


Joy to thee, reverend guest ; if offensive words have been 
spoken, 

May they be gone forthwith swept up and away by a 
whirlwind.¢ 


For what is offensive and heart-breaking to speak is 
not a conjunction or an article or a preposition but a 
verb expressive of a shameful action or of some im- 
proper experience. This is also why we customarily 
praise or censure writers of poetry and prose in 


doctrine is ascribed to the Peripatetics and some of the 
supporting arguments are answered (cf. Priscian, op. cit., 
ii, 15 and xi, 6-7 =i, p. 54, 5-7 and pp. 551, 17-552, 14 
{Hertz]). An elaborate defence of the doctrine, in many 
particulars like Plutarch’s, is given by Ammonius (De 
Interpretatione, pp. 11, 1-15, 13), who with explicit reference 
to the Cratylus and the Sophist asserts that Plato anticipated 
Aristotle in holding it (De Interpretatione, Ὁ. 40, 26-30 ; 
p. 48, 30-32; τ. 60, 1-3 and 17-23). CF. Aristotle, Rhetoric 
1404 Ὁ 26-27; Theophrastus and Boethus of Sidon in 
Simplicius, Categ., p. 10, 24-27 and p. 11, 23-25; and 
Adrastus in Theon Smyrnaeus, p. 49, 7-9 (Hiller). 

¢ Iliad vi, 253 and 406 ; vii, 108; and passim, 

4 Odyssey xxiii, 183. 

¢ Odyssey viil, 408-409, 


115 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1010) “" ᾿Αττικοῖς ὁ ὀνόμασιν ὁ δεῖνα κέχρηται Kat’ καλοῖς 
ῥήμασιν᾽ ᾿ὴ πάλιν ' “πεζοῖς ᾿᾿ τὸ δέ γε “πεζοῖς ’” 
ἢ “ καλοῖς ᾿ πάλιν “Ὧ καὶ ᾿Αττικοῖς ἄρθροις ’ 
οὐκ ἂν εἴποι τις Edpimidny ἢ Θουκυδίδην διει- 
λέχθαι. 

8. “Τί οὖν; ᾿᾿--φήσαι τις ἄν--' οὐδὲν ταῦτα 
, \ / ᾽) ες A 39 nv 
συμβάλλεται πρὸς λόγον; ᾿ ἔγωγε φήσαιμ᾽ av 
ὥσπερ ἅλας" συμβάλλεσθαι πρὸς ὄψον ὕδωρ δὲ 
πρὸς μᾶζαν. Eunvos* δὲ καὶ TO πῦρ ἔφασκεν 
ἡδυσμάτων εἶναι κράτιστον. ἀλλ᾽ οὔθ᾽ ὕδωρ μάζης 
ἢ ἄρτου μέρος εἶναι λέγομεν" οὔτε πῦρ οὔθ᾽ ἅλας 
ἐψήματος ἢ ἢ βρώματος," ὧν ἀεὶ τυγχάνομεν δεόμε- 
νοι, οὐχ ὥσπερ ὁ λόγος πολλάκις ἐκείνων ἀπροσ- 

D δεής ἐστιν, ὡς δοκεῖ μοι [περὶ Ῥωμαίων] € ἔχειν ὁ 
Ῥωμαίων, ζ(ᾧ νῦν ὁμοῦ τι πάντες ἄνθρωποι 
χρῶνται" προθέσεις τε γὰρ ἀφήρηκε πλὴν ὀλίγων" 

1 καὶ -J1', g 3 omitted by all other mss. 
2 Diibner (τὸ δὲ πεζοῖς -Wyttenbach) ; 6 δέ γε πεζοῖς -J}, 
2; πεζοῖς δὲ Pareto T-11-5;3 ὅδε δὲ πεζοῖς -all other mss. 
* εὔωνος -N, Voss. 16, εἰ (?). 
. κράτιστον. ; + μέρος εἶναι -omitted by J, g, a, A, y, E, 
: κράτιστον . . .- εἶναι λέγομεν -omitted by B (added in 
margin by sb B 
ἀρώματος -\, ε- 
7 Diibner ie ὁ Ῥωμαίων ἔχειν,  -Wyttenbach);: μοι 
περὶ ῥωμαίων λέγειν ὁρῶ μέλλω (μ έλλων τβ, 0, Voss. 16, Bo- | 
non.) νῦν -all mss. except atonal T-11-5 (μοι περὶ ῥω- | 


μαίων λέγειν dpa... vac. 30... ἀλλ᾽ ὥσπερ ὁμοῦ πάντες). 
ὀλίγον -J. 


(6 











* In such expressions ὄνομα (and the same could be said 
of ῥῆμα) is used in a different sense, 7.¢. τὸ κοινῶς ἐπὶ πᾶν μέρος 
λόγου διατεῖνον (cf. Simplicius, Categ., p. 25,'14-17 ; Scholia 
in Dionysii Thracis Artem Grammaticam, p. 522, 21-28 
{ Hilgard]). 

> Evenus, frag. 10 (Bergk, Poetae Lyr. Graec. ii*, p. 271 ; 


114 





PLATONIC QUESTIONS x, 1010 


terms like these, “ the nouns employed by so-and-so 
are “ Attic’ and the verbs are ‘ elegant’ ” or again 
“ pedestrian,’ * whereas it would not be said by 
anyone that in the language of Euripides or Thucy- 
dides ‘‘ pedestrian”’ or again “ elegant and Attic 
articles ’’ are used. 

3. ““ What then? ’’—one might say—* Do these 
words contribute nothing to speech?” I should say 
that they do make a contribution to it Just as salt 
does to a dish of food and water to a barley-cake. 
Evenus even said that fire is the best of sauces.? 
Nevertheless, we do not say either that water is a 
part of barley-cake or wheat-bread or that fire or 
salt is a part of greens or victuals, although we do 
always require fire and salt, whereas speech unlike 
this often has no need of those additional words. 
So it is, it seems to me, with the speech of the 
Romans, which now is used by nearly all men, for it 
has eliminated all prepositions except for a few ¢ 
Edmonds, Elegy and Iambus i, p. 476). The remark is 
ascribed to Evenus in Quomodo Adulator ab Amico Inter- 
noscatur 50 a and in Quaest. Conviv. 697 c-p but to Prodicus 
in De Tuenda Sanitate 126 Ὁ. 

¢ According to Hartman (De Plutarcho, p. 583) this is an 
erroneous generalization from those Latin expressions of 
relations of place in which no preposition is used ; according 
to H. J. Rose (The Roman Questions of Plutarch {Oxford, 
1924], p. 198 ad lIxvii [208 a]) it is rather an exaggeration 
suggested by the contemporary fondness for archaic and 
poetical constructions which omitted the prepositions of 
Ciceronian grammar; and both these observations may be 
partial explanations of Plutarch’s “ odd statement,” but it 
should be remembered also that many Latin ‘‘ prepositions ”’ 
were regarded by the Greeks as not being prepositions at all 
(Priscian, Jnst. Grammatica xiv, 9-10 and 23=ii, pp. 28, 
19-29, 11 and pp. 36, 20-37, 6 [Hertz]). From a different 
point of view Plutarch’s statement without being noticed is 


115 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1010) ἁπάσας, τῶν TE καλουμένων ἄρθρων οὐδὲν προσ- 
δέχεται τὸ παράπαν, ἀλλὰ ὥσπερ ἀκρασπέδοις" 
χρῆται τοῖς ὀνόμασι. καὶ οὐ θαυμαστόν ἐστιν, 
ὅπου καὶ “Ὅμηρος ἐπέων κόσμῳ περιγενόμενος 
ὀλίγοις τῶν ὀνομάτων ἄρθρα ὥσπερ λαβὰς ἐκπώ- 
pact μὴ" δεομένοις 7 λόφους" κράνεσιν ἐπιτίθησι" 
διὸ καὶ" παράσημα τῶν ἐπῶν ἐν οἷς ταῦτα ποιεῖ" 
γέγονεν, ὡς τὸ 


Αἴαντι δὲ μάλιστα cree θυμὸν ὄρινε 
τῷ Ἰελαμωνιάδῃ 
καὶ τὸ 
ποίεεν," ὄφρα τὸ κῆτος ὑπεκπροφυγὼνἾ ἀἁλέοιτο" 
A 4 A ’ [2 A 3 » 
καὶ βραχέα πρὸς τούτοις ἕτερα. τοῖς δ᾽ ἄλλοις 
E μυρίοις οὖσιν ἄρθρου μὴ προσόντος οὐδὲν εἰς 
tA » A / ς 4 Ψ 
σαφήνειαν οὐδὲ κάλλος ἡ φράσις βλάπτεται. 
1 Nleziriac ; κρασπέδοις -MSS. 
2 μὴ -B?, n, Voss. 16, Escorial T-11-5, Bonon.; omitted 
by all other mss. 
λόφοις -1, δ. : καὶ -omitted by ae 
ποιεῖν τε: "pe (1.6. προγέγονεν) -Fscorial 1-11-ὅ. 
ποιεῖν 13 ποίεον -Homer. 7 ὑπερπροφυγὼν -Ἡ. 
ἀλλέοιτο -Eseorial T-11-5 ; ἀλέαιτο -Homer. 
ἄρθρου δὲ μὴ -J, ἕξ. 


orn ὦ ὦ 





supported by R. Poncelet (Cicéron Traducteur de Platon 
{Paris, 1957]), who characterizes the Latin penury of analy- 
tical instruments as “ pas d’articles, peu de prépositions, peu 
de participes ’’ (p. 18) and considers the rudimentary prepo- 
sitional system of Latin along with its lack of an article to be 
one of the principal reasons for Cicero’s difficulties in trans- 
lating the philosophical Greek of Plato (pp. 52-61, pp. 105- 
129, p. 139). 

¢ Cf. Quintilian, Jnstit. Orat. i, 4, 19; Vriscian, Jnst. 
Grammatica ii, 16 and xvii, 27 (i, p. 54, 13-16 and ii, p. 124, 
16-18 [Hertz]). 

ὑ Cf. Democritus, frag. B 21 (D.-K.) and Pausanias, ix, 30, 


116 





PLATONIC QUESTIONS x, 1010 


and of the words called articles admits none at all ¢ 
but employs nouns without tassels, as it were. This 
is not surprising either, since Homer too, who ex- 
celled in marshalling words,’ attaches articles to 
few of his nouns, as it were crests to helmets or 
handles to goblets that do not require them ὁ ; and 
that is the very reason why critical marks ὦ have 
been put at the verses in which he does so, for 
example : 

Wrathful fury he chiefly excited in fiery Ajax, 

The Telamonian one,? 
and 

Built it to let him elude and evade the notorious monster ἢ 


and a few others besides. In the rest, however, 
countless as they are, though an article is not 
present, the expression suffers nothing in clarity or 
beauty. 


4 and 12. The phrase κόσμον ἐπέων occurs in a line of 
Solon’s quoted by Plutarch himself (Solon viii, 2 [82 c]) 3 ef. 
also Parmenides, frag. B 8, 52 (D.-K.) and Philetas of Cos, 
frag. 8 (Diehl, Anth. Lyr. Graec. ii, p. 211)=10 (Powell, 
Collectanea Alexandrina, p. 92). 

¢ There were ἐκπώματα of countless kinds (Clement of 
Alexandria, Paedagogus τις iii, 35, 2), many without handles 
(Athenaeus, xi, 783 a, 478 b, and 481 d). 

a Cf. Aristotle, Soph. Elench. 177 b 6 (κἀκεῖ 42:0 ὁ παράσημα 
ποιοῦνται). 

¢ Iliad xiv, 459-460. Leaf (The Iliad 115, p. 97 ad 458-459) 
calls the use of τῷ in 460 “ hardly Homeric.”’ Cf. in general 
Scholia Graeca in Homeri Iliadem ed. Dindorf i, p. 70, 10-11 
ad B 1 and p. 339, 14-15 ad Καὶ 1 (ἔστι yap ὁ ποιητὴς παρα- 
λειπτικὸς τῶν ἄρθρων). 

f Jliad xx, 147. For the use of the article here cf. Scholia 
Graeca in Homeri Iliadem ed. Dindorf ii, p. 199, 19-20; 
Leaf (The Iliad ii?, p. 359) calls it very rare in Homer and 
says that “‘ instances such as this are confined to late passages 
in the /liad.” 

117 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1010) 4. Kat μὴν οὔτε ζῷον οὔτ᾽ ὄργανον οὔὐθ᾽ ὅπλον 
eee » ~ 3» > \ > ’ / > 
out ἄλλο τῶν ὄντων οὐδὲν οἰκείου μέρους ἀφαι- 
ἢ \ ͵ , , / 1 999 
ρέσει καὶ στερήσει πέφυκε γίγνεσθαι KaAALoV' οὐδ 
3 , Ὁ / / / ? 
ἐνεργέστερον οὐδὲ ἥδιον" λόγος δέ, συνδέσμων ἐξ- 
αἱρεθέντων, πολλάκις ἐμπαθεστέραν καὶ κινητικω- 
τέραν ἔχει δύναμιν: ὡς ὁ τοιοῦτος 
ἄλλον ζωὸν ἔχουσα" νεούτατον, ἄλλον ἄουτον, 
ἄλλον τεθνειῶτα" κατὰ μόθον ἕλκε ποδοῖιν' 


\ \ - , ΝΠ \ ‘ x 
καὶ τὰ τοῦ Δημοσθένους ταυτὶ “᾿ πολλὰ yap ἂν 
, ε 7 ie 2 le \ v9 20> Ὁ 
ποιήσειεν ὁ τύπτων, ὧν' ὁ παθὼν eu’ οὐδ᾽ ἂν 
Ἐ πα εἰλ ὃ v4 θ᾽ e / “ 4 ~ Bx / A 
γγεῖλαι δύναιθ᾽ ἑτέρῳ, TH σχήματι. τῷ βλέμ 
ματι τῇ φωνῇ, ὅταν ὑβρίζων, ὅταν ἐχθρὸς" ὑπ- 
ἄρχων, ὅταν κονδύλοις," ὅταν ἐπὶ κόρρης"" ταῦτα 
κινεῖ," ταῦτ᾽ ἐξίστησιν αὑτῶν ἀνθρώπους" ἀήθεις 
τοῦ" προπηλακίζεσθαι. καὶ πάλιν “ἀλλ᾽ οὐ" 
Μειδίας: ἀλλ᾽ ἀπὸ ταύτης τῆς ἡμέρας" λέγει, λοι- 

- “A A > 
δορεῖται, Bod. χειροτονεῖταί τις ; Μειδίας “Ava- 
1011 γυράσιος" προβέβληται. []λουτάρχου" προξενεῖ, 


1 κάλλιστον -J, g. 2 ἔχουσα -omitted by J’, g. 

3 χεθνηῶτα -Homer (cf. Scholia Graeca in Ifomeri Iliadem 
ed. Dindorf ii, p. 176 ad 537). 
τύπτων, ὦ ἄνδρες ᾿Αθηναῖοι, ὧν -Demosthenes. 
ὅταν ὡς ὑβρίζων, ὅταν ὡς ἐχθρὸς -Demosthenes. 
ὅταν κονδύλοις -omitted by J}, g. 
κόρης -J, £3 κόρης τύπτη -Escorial T-11-5. 
κινῇ -J, g, Escorial T-11-5. 
αὐτῶν ἐξίστησιν ἀνθρώπους -J : αὐτοῦ ἐξίστησιν ἀνθρώπους 
-£3 ἐξίστησιν αὐτοὺς ἀνθρώπους -Escorial T-11-5; ἐξίστησιν 
ἀνθρώπους αὑτῶν -Demosthenes. 

10 ἀήθους τοῦ -€3 ἀήθεις ὄντας τοῦ -Demosthenes. 

11 οὐδὲ -£. . 

12 γῆς ἡμέρας ταύτης -Demosthenes S and Y (but A and 
F agree with Plutarch). 13 [Demosthenes ; τι -Mss. 

14 Escorial T-1 1-5 and Demosthenes 4 ἀναγυρράσιος -all 
other mss. 15 )emosthenes ; πλουτάρχῳ -MSS. 


118 





PLATONIC QUESTIONS x, 1010-1011 


4. Moreover, it is not natural for any living being 
or instrument or weapon or any other existing thing 
to become more beautiful or more effective or more 
pleasant by the removal or loss of a part that belongs 
to it®; but frequently when conjunctions have 
been eliminated speech has a force more emotional 
and more stirring,? as in a case like this : 


One just wounded alive in her clutches, another un- 


wounded, 

Dead already another she dragged by the feet through the 
turmoil ¢ 

and this by Demosthenes: “‘ He who strikes one 


might do many things, some of which his victim 
could not even report to another, by his posture, by 
his look, by his tone of voice, when insultingly, when 
in hostility, when with the fist, when with a slap in 
the face; these are the things that stir up, that 
drive to distraction men unused to contemptuous 
treatment.’* And again: ‘ Not Meidias, how- 
ever; but from this day forth he talks, reviles, 
shouts. Is someone to be elected? Meidias of 
Anagyrus is a candidate. He represents the interests 


α Cf. Scholia in Dionysii Thracis Artem Grammaticam, 
pp. 516, 37-517, 4 (Hilgard). 

> Cf. [Plutarch], De Vita Homeri 40 (vii, pp. 355, 20-356, 
5 [Bernardakis]) ; for Plutarch, Caesar 1, 3-4 (731 F) cf. R. 
Jeuckens, Plutarch von Chaeronea und die Rhetorik (Strass- 
burg, 1908), pp. 162-163. 

¢ Iliad xviii, 536-537 =(Hesiod], Scutum 157-158 (ef. F. 
Solmsen, Hermes, xciii [1965], pp. 1-6). 

4 Demosthenes, Oratio xxi, 72. The passage is quoted and 
analysed by “ Longinus’’ (De Sublimitate xx-xxi) for the 
combination of several figures, asyndeton included ; ef. also 
Tiberius Rhetor, [epi σχημάτων 40 (Rhetores Craeci iii, 
p. 78, 1-4 [Spengel}). 


119 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1011) τἀπόρρητ᾽ οἶδεν, ἡ πόλις αὐτὸν οὐ χωρεῖ. διὸ καὶ 
σφόδρα τὸ ἀσύνδετον σχῆμα παρὰ τοῖς τὰς" 
τέχνας γράφουσιν εὐδοκιμεῖ" τοὺς" δ᾽ ἄγαν νομί- 
μους ἐκείνους καὶ μηδένα σύνδεσμον ἐκ τῆς 
συνηθείας ἀφιέντας ὡς ἀργὴν καὶ ἀπαθῆ καὶ 
κοπώδη τῷ ἀμεταβλήτῳ τὴν φράσιν ποιοῦντας 
αἰτιῶνται. τὸ δὲ τοὺς διαλεκτικοὺς μάλιστα συν- 
δέσμων δεῖσθαι πρὸς τὰς τῶν ἀξιωμάτων συναφὰς 
καὶ συμπλοκὰς καὶ διαζεύξεις ὥσπερ ἡνιόχους 
ζυγῶν καὶ τὸν Cev)* Κύκλωπος ᾿Οδυσσέα λύγων 
πρὸς τὴν τῶν προβάτων σύν(δεσιν ΝΠ 
λόγου τὸν" σύνδεσμον ἀλλ᾽ ὄργανόν. τι, συνδετικὸν" 

Β ἀποφαίνει, καθάπερ ὠνόμασται, καὶ συνεκτικὸν οὐ 

παρ᾽ οἷς -n, Voss. 16. 

τὰς -omitted by a, A, y, E, B, 

τῆς -J15 τοὺς -all bile MSS. 

<év> -added by Emperius (Op. Philol., P- 340). 

Hubert after Bernardakis (λύγων πρὸς τῶν προβάτων τὴν 


σύνδεσιν <Odyssey ix, 425 and 427> οὐ): : λυγῶν πρὸς τὴν 
τῶν προβάτων οὐ -J, £3 tnrcvat “πρὸς τὴν τῶν προβάτων συν 


aor O ND = 


. vac. 83 (first 5 erased) . . οὐ -B (civ... vac. 57... ob 
3 -Bonon.) ; Avy@vra πρὸς τὴν τῶν “προβάτων. 4 Weer tae 
ov -N, Voss. 163; λέγοντα πρὸς τὴν τῶν sipB iT WARE, 


64... 00-Escor 12] -11-ὅ ; ᾽Οδυσσέα. .. ν80. 80 -ἃ : 69 -α: 
100 -Α: 84-y; 87-E; 88 -Β ; 69 -e€... ov. 

8 τὸν omitted by J, 83 τοῦ -α. 

7 χιτῶν 23 omitted by all other mss. 

8 συνδεκτικὸν -J, g. 


¢ Plutarch, the tyrant of Eretria (ef. Plutarch, Phocion 
xii-xiii {747 a-z]; Demosthenes, Oratio v, 5 {with scholion 
ad loc.| and xxi, 110). 

Ὁ Demosthenes, Oratio xxi, 200. Part of this passage is 
quoted for asyndeton by [Aristides], Libri Rhetorici i, 28 
(pp. 13, 23-14, 1 [W. Schmid)}). 

¢ Cf. Demetrius, De Elocutione 193-194 and 268-269 ; 
‘* Longinus,” De Sublimitate xxi; Tiberius Khetor, Περὶ 


120 


PLATONIC QUESTIONS x, 1011 


of Plutarch,¢ knows the secrets of state, is too big 
for the city.” This is just the reason why the 
figure of asyndeton is very highly esteemed by the 
writers of the rhetorical manuals, and those who 
abide too strictly by the rules and leave out no con- 
junction of the ordinary language they censure for 
making their style dull and unemotional and weari- 
some from lack of variety.¢ That the dialecticians 
have special need of conjunctions for the connexions 
and combinations and disjunctions of propositions,@ 
as charioteers have of yokes and as Odysseus <in the 
cave) of Cyclops had of withes for binding the sheep 
together ¢¢. . .), this shows not that the conjunction 
is a part of speech’ but that it is a kind of instru- 
ment for conjoining, just as its name indicates, that 


σχημάτων 40 (Rhetores (rraeci iii, Ὁ. 78, 11-15 [Spengel]) ; 
[Cicero], Ad Herennium iv, 41. lor αἱ τέχναι =“‘ rhetorical 
manuals ’’ ef. Isocrates, Adv. Sophistas 19 (ras καλουμένας 
τέχνας) with the scholion ad loc. 

¢ The dialecticians are the Stoics (see note d on page 107 
supra). ‘The propositions in question are the conditional 
(συνημμένον), the conjunctive (συμπεπλεγμένον), and the dis- 
junctive (διεζευγμένον) ; and the σύνδεσμοι required for these 
are respectively 6 συναπτικός (εἰ), ὁ συμπλεκτικός (καί), and ὁ 
διαζευκτικός (ἤτοι Or ἢ) : ef. Diogenes Laertius, vii, 71-72 
(S.V.F. ii, frag. 207); Galen, lnstitutio Logica iii, 3-4 and 
iv, 4-6 (pp. 8, 13-9, 8 and pp. 10, 13-11, 12 [Kalbfleisch] = 
S.V.F. ii, frags. 208 and 217); and Plutarch, De E 386 r— 
387 a, De Sollertia Animalium 969 a-s, and De An. Proc. 
in Timaeo 1026 B-c. 

e Of. Odyssey ix, 427 and Euripides, Cyclops 225. 

f As the Stoics held it to be: cf. Diogenes Laertius, vii, 
57-58 (S.V.F. ii, frag. 147 and iii, p. 214, 1-2); S.V.F. ii, 
frag. 148; Scholia in Dionysii Thracis Artem Grammaticam, 
p. 356, 13-15 and p. 517, 33-34 with p. 519, 26-32 (Hilgard). 
Posidonius wrote against those who said that conjunctions 
οὐ δηλοῦσι μέν τι αὐτὸ δὲ μόνον τὴν φράσιν συνδέουσι (Apollonius 
Dyscolus, De Conjunctionibus, Ὁ. 214, 4-8 [Schneider]). 


12] 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1011) πάντων ἀλλὰ τῶν οὐχ ἁπλῶς λεγομένων, εἰ μὴ 


3 “-- / \ δι ὦ \ “-- ι ’ \ 
καὶ τοῦ φορτίου Tov ἱμάντα καὶ Tod βιβλίου τὴν 
χὰ 3 Ε ͵ 3 ae Ad ΠῚ ὅ 
κόλλαν ἀξιοῦσι μέρος εἶναι καὶ νὴ Ata’ τὰς δια- 

\ A λ ,ὔ e =r A 10 A 
νομας TOU TOALTEVLATOS, WS EAEVYE ANA Ὡς, KOA- 
dav ὀνομάζων τὰ θεωρικὰ τῆς δημοκρατίας. 
ποῖος δὲ σύνδεσμος οὕτως ἕν ἐκ πολλῶν ἀξίωμα 
ποιεῖ συμπλέκων καὶ συνάπτων ὡς ἡ μάρμαρος" 

\ ’ A \ A \ 7 5ΔᾺ79 
τὸν συλλιπαινόμενον᾽ διὰ τοῦ πυρὸς σίδηρον ; ἀλλ 
οὐκ ἔστιν οὐδὲ λέγεται τοῦ σιδήρου μέρος" καίτοι 
{τὰ τοιαῦτά γε τοῖς κεραννυμένοις ἐνδυόμενα 
καὶ συντηκόμενα ποιεῖ τι [καὶ πάσχει" κοινὸν ἐκ 
πλειόνων. τοὺς δὲ συνδέσμους εἰσὶν οἱ μὴ νό- 

1 γὴ Δία -X, βῆ, n, Voss. 16, Bonon., Escorial T-11-5 ; 
εἶναι νὴ Δία καὶ -ε: νὴ Δία -omitted by all other mss. 

2 θεωρητικὰ -J, g, Voss. 16, Escorial T-11-5. 
μάρμερος -J 9 Escorial T-11-51 3 μάμερ τ 
σὐύλανλιπαινόμενον -J. 

.3 καὶ τοιαῦτα -J, £3 καίτοι ταῦτα -all other mss. 


: [καὶ πάσχει] -deleted by Hartman (De Plutarcho, p. 588). 


’ὔ 
7 πλοιόνων τῷ. 


= (ὦ 


α That is even for the Stoics the conjunction holds together 
only a molecular proposition, this consisting of two or more 
atomic (simple) propositions, each of which itself consists of 
a subject and predicate not connected by any conjunction : 
cf. Sextus, Adv. Math. viii, 93-95 and 108-109 (S.V.F. ii, 
p. 66, 28-37 and pp. 70, 36-71, 2) with Mates, Stoic Logic, 
pp. 95-96; and Diogenes Laertius, vii, 68-69 and 71-72 
(S.V.F. ii, frags. 203 and 207). 

> Cf. [Apuleius], Περὶ ἑρμηνείας iv (p. 178, 7-11 [Thomas]) ; 
Ammonius, De Interpretatione, pp. 12, 25-13, 6 and p. 67, 
15-19 and p. 73, 19-22; Simplicius, Categ., p. 64, 23-25 ; 
Scholia in Dionysti Thracis Artem Grammaticam, Ὁ. 515, 
19-29 (Hilgard). 

ὁ Demades, frag. 13 (Baiter-Sauppe, Oratores Attici ii, 
p. 315 B 38-42) =xxxvi (De Falco, Demade Oratore?, p. 31). 

4 See note d on 1011 a supra. 


122 


PLATONIC QUESTIONS x, 1011 


is for holding together not all statements but those 
that are non-simple,7—unless one also maintains 
that the strap is part of the load and the glue part 
of the book ® and the dole, by heaven, part of the 
government, as Demades said when he called the 
festival-grants the glue of the democracy. What 
kind of conjunction, moreover, by combining and con- 
necting ὦ makes of many a proposition so thoroughly 
one as the marble makes the iron that is smelted with 
it in the fire? The marble, however, is not and is 
not said to be a part of the iron; and yet things of 
this kind make something common out of a multi- 
plicity ὁ by permeating the objects that are being 
blended and by being fused with them.’ As to con- 
junctions, however, there are people who believe 


ε Cf. 1010 a supra: ἕν τι πειρώμενοι κοινὸν ἐξ αὐτῶν ποιεῖν. 

7 The marble is not fused with the iron, as Plutarch 
apparently believed it is, but supplies the limestone which 
unites with the non-ferrous minerals of the ore (the “ gan- 
gue ’’) and with the ash of the fuel to form the “‘ cinder ”’ or 
‘* slag.”’ It may be such a flux to which reference is made by 
[Aristotle], De Mirabilibus Auscultationibus 833 Ὁ 24-28 and 
by Theophrastus, De Lapidibus 9 (cf. H. Bliimner, Techno- 
logie und Terminologie der Gewerbe und Kiinste bei Griechen 
und Rémern iv { Leipzig, 1887], pp. 219-220 ; A. W. Persson, 
Eisen und Eisenbereitung in dltester Zeit [Lund, 1934], pp. 
15-17; Εἰ, R. Caley and J. F. C. Richards, Theophrastus on 
Stones [Columbus, 1956], p. 77); but in no ancient text, so 
far as I know, is an explanation of the process offered, 
although the purpose of the flux used in refining gold is 
mentioned (cf. Agatharchides in Photius, Bibliotheca, cod. 
250, p. 448, 19-30 [Bekker]; Pliny, V.H. xxxiii, 60; H. 
Bliimner, op. cit., pp. 131-135). It is to a different stage in 
the working of the iron that Plutarch refers in Quaest. 
Conviv. 660 c and De Primo Frigido 954 a-B; cf. also 
Η. D. P. Lee on Aristotle, Meteorologica 383 a 32~b 7 (L.C.L., 
pp. 324-399). 


123 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


͵ v4 a 3 > > 
(1011) μίζοντες ἕν τι ποιεῖν ἀλλ᾽ ἐξαρίθμησιν εἶναι τὴν 
,ὔ 7 3 ᾽ 9 lon \ “ 
διάλεκτον, ὥσπερ ἀρχόντων ἐφεξῆς (ἢ) ἡμερῶν 
/ 
καταλεγομένων. 
\ \ ~ ~ ς \ > , 
ὅ. Καὶ μὴν τῶν γε λοιπῶν ἡ μὲν ἀντωνυμία 
~ , 2 9 7 , 9 ’ - ΄ 
περιφανῶς γένος" ὀνόματός ἐστιν, οὐχ ἡ πτώσεων 
μετέχει μόνον ἀλλὰ καὶ τῷ κυριωτάτην ἅμα τῇ 
φάσει" ποιεῖν δεῖξιν ἐνίας ἐπὶ τῶν ὡρισμένων ἐκ- 
φερομένας" καὶ οὐκ olda ὅτι μᾶλλον ὁ “ Σωκρά- 
τὴν ᾿ φθεγξάμενος ἢ ὁ “᾿ τοῦτον ᾿᾿ εἰπὼν ὀνομαστὶ" 
Uy VA 
πρόσωπον δεδήλωκεν. 
ec \ / v4 A wh 
6. Ἢ δὲ καλουμένη μετοχή, μῖγμα ῥήματος 
οὖσα καὶ ὀνόματος, καθ᾽ ἑαυτὴν μὲν οὐκ ἔστιν, 
ω 3 Ν 4 \ ~ \ > ~ Φ 2 
ὥσπερ οὐδὲ τὰ κοινὰ θηλυκῶν καὶ ἀρρενικῶν ὀνό- 
/ we | / 2 / A A 
D ματα, συντάττεται δ᾽ ἐκείνοις, ἐφαπτομένη Tots μὲν 
χρόνοις τῶν ῥημάτων ταῖς δὲ πτώσεσι τῶν ὀνο- 
μάτων. οἱ δὲ διαλεκτικοὶ τὰ τοιαῦτα καλοῦσιν 
1 «ἢΣ -added by Meziriac ; implied by Amyot’s version. 
> γένος περιφανῶς -J, Ε΄. 
3. Wyttenbach ; φύσει -Μ88. 
Σωκράτη -Ν. 5 ὀνόματι -J, £. 
8 καὶ ὀνόματος -omitted by J}, g. 


7 ἑαυτὸ -Χ. 


« Cf. the sceptical argument that a statement or propo- 
sition cannot exist, because the expressions, which must be 
its constituent parts, do not coexist but are at most successive 
(Sextus, Adv. Math. i, 132-138 with Pyrrh. [Typ. ii, 109 and 
Adv. Math. viii, 81-84, 132, and 136). 

> i.e. demonstratives (ef. Apollonius Dyscolus, De Prono- 
mine, pp. 9, 17-10, 7 and p. 10, 18-26 [Schneider]: Scholia 


124 


PLATONIC QUESTIONS x, 1011 


that they do not make anything one but that 
language is an enumeration like that of annual 
magistrates ¢or) of days listed one after another.* 
5. Now, of the rest the pronoun is patently a 
kind of noun, not only as it shares the cases of the 
noun but also by reason of the fact that some pro- 
nouns,” being expressions of definite reference, make 
an indication fully decisive as soon as they are 
spoken ; and I do not know that a speaker uttering 
‘Socrates ’’ has by calling a name more clearly in- 
dicated a person than has one saying “ this man.” ¢ 
6. And as for what is called the participle, since 
it is a mixture of verb and noun,? it does not exist 
of itself,¢ to be sure, as the nouns of common feminine 
and masculine gender do not either’; but it is 
ranked with those parts of speech, since through its 
tenses it borders on the verbs and through its cases 
on the nouns. Terms of this kind, moreover, are 


in Dionysti Thracis Artem Grammaticam, pp. 77, 25-78, 6 
with p. 86, 7-13 and p. 260, 21-24 [Hilgard]). 

¢ Cf. Sextus, Adv. Math. viii, 96-97 (S.V.F. ii, frag. 205 
[pp. 66, 38-67, 9]) : according to the Stoics Σωκράτης κάθηται 
is intermediate between the indefinite ris κάθηται and the 
definite οὗτος κάθηται. 

4 Cf. Dionysius Thrax, Ars Grammatica ὃ 15 (p. 60, 9-4 
[Uhlig]) ; Scholia in Dionysii Thracis Artem Grammaticam, 
pp. 255, 25-256, 7 (Hilgard); Ammonius, De Interpre- 
tatione, p. 15, 2-4. 

« Cf. Priscian, Inst. Grammatica xi, 2 (i, p. 549, 3-6 
{Hertz]: ‘‘ ideo autem participium separatim non tradebant 
[scil. Stoici] partem orationis .. .’’) and ii, 16 (i, p. 54, 9-10 
{Hertz]); Scholia in Dionysit Thracis Artem Grammaticam, 
p. 518, 17-22 (Hilgard). 

7 Cf. Scholia in Dionysii Thracis Artem Grammaticam, 
pp. 218, 18-219, 15 and especially pp. 525, 32-526, 11 (Hil- 
gard); KR. Schneider, Apollonii Dyscoli Quae Supersunt i, 2 
(Commentarium ...in Apollonii Scripta Minora), pp. 24-25. 

125 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1011) ἀντανακλάστους," οἷον ὁ φρονῶν ἀντὶ" τοῦ φρο- 
νίμου καὶ ὁ σωφρονῶν' ἀντὶ" τοῦ σώφρονός ἐστιν, 
ὡς ὀνομάτων καὶ προσηγοριῶν δύναμιν ἔ ἔχοντα. 

ΤΟ δ γε μὴν προθέσεις ἔστιν ἐπικράνοις καὶ 
βάσεσι καὶ ὑποθέμασιν, ὡς οὐ λόγους ἀλλὰ περὶ 
τοὺς λόγους μᾶλλον οὔσας, ὁμοιοῦν. ὅρα δὲ" μὴ 
κὄμμασι καὶ θραύσμασιν ὀνομάτων ἐοίκασιν, ὥσπερ 
γραμμάτων σπαράγμασιν" καὶ κεραίαις ot’ σπεύ- 


δοντες ypagovor: TO yap “ ἐμβῆναι’ ἀν τ “* éx- 


3 
βῆναι" συγκοπῇὴ προφανής" ἐστι τοῦ “ ἐντὸς 
~ \ 
KE βῆναι ᾿᾿ καὶ τοῦ “ ἐκτὸς Prva,’ Kat τὸ ‘‘ mpo- 
A ’ \ A 
γενέσθαι τοῦ ‘‘ πρότερον γενέσθαι," καὶ τὸ 


“ καθίζειν ᾿ τοῦ “κάτω ἵζειν ὥσπερ ἀμέλει 


τὸ “λίθους βάλλειν ᾿᾿ καὶ “ τοίχους ὀρύσσειν ”’ 


1 R. T. Schmidt (Stoicorum Grammatica {Halle, 1839], 
p- 46, Nn. 66) 3 ἀνακλάστους -MSS. 

2 ἀντὶ -G. F. Shoemann (Die Lehre von den Redetheilen 
[Berlin, 1862], p. 39, n. 1); ἀπὸ -Mss. 
“ σώφρων -J, 2 
ἀντὶ -G. F. cae (loc. cit.) ; ἀπὸ -MSS. 
ὅρα δὴ -J', σ᾽ : ὅσα δὲ -ε. 
σπαράγματα - 7 οἷον -J!, g. 
περιφανῶς -J', δ: : προφανῶς -B*, n, Voss. 16, Bonon., 
sia T-11-5. 


+99 


oon & 


i Moe -X; xaraifew -all other mss. 








α Cf. Priscian, Inst. Grammatica xi, | (i, pp. 548, 14-549, 
1 (Hertz]): ‘sic igitur supra dicti philosophi [scil. Stoici] 
etiam participium aiebant appellationem esse reciprocam, id 
est ἀντανάκλαστον προσηγορίαν, hoc modo: legens est lector 
et lector legens, cursor est currens et currens cursor, amator 
est amans et amans amator, vel nomen verbale vel modum 
verbi casualem.” 

> The correction, καὶ mpoonyopidy, is required because the 
Stoics had restricted ὄνομα to proper nouns and had made a 
separate part of speech called προσηγορία to cover common 
nouns and noun adjectives (Diogenes Laertius, vii, 57-58 


126 





PLATONIC QUESTIONS x, 1011 


called reciprocals by the dialecticians ὦ on the ground 
that they have the force of nouns, that is of appel- 
latives,? as for example the reflecting instead of re- 
flective and the abstaining instead of abstinent man.°¢ 

7. The prepositions, for their part, can be likened 
to capitals and pedestals and bases as being not 
speech but rather appurtenances of speech. Consider 
too that they resemble bits and pieces of words 4 
like the fragmentary letters and dashes used by 
those who write in haste. For “ incoming” and 
‘“ outgoing’ are plainly contractions of ‘ coming 
within’ and “ going without,” “foregoing” of 
“ going before,” and “ undersetting ᾿ of “ setting 
underneath,” just as it is, of course, by quickening 
and abridging the expression that for “ pelting with 
[S. V.F. ii, frag. 147 and iii, p. 213, 27-31]), which the gram- 
marians, however, continued to call ὀνόματα or treated as a 
sub-class of ὄνομα (Dionysius Thrax, Ars Grammatica, p. 23, 
2-3 and pp. 33, 6-34, 2 [Uhlig] with Scholia in Dionysii 
Thracis Artem Grammaticam, pp. 214, 17-215, 3 and p. 356, 
7-23 and pp. 517, 33-518, 16 [Hilgard}). 

¢ The Stoics, for whom the sage alone is φρόνιμος and 
σώφρων and alone φρονεῖ and σωφρονεῖ. could hold that ὁ 
φρονῶν must always be ὁ φρόνιμος and ὁ σωφρονῶν ὁ σώφρων and 
even that ὁ φρόνιμος is always 6 φρονῶν, since the sage’s 
exercise of virtue is continual and unremitting (S.V.F. i, 
frags. 216 [p. 52, 25-33] and 569 ; iii, p. 149, 16-18). Never- 
theless, they did distinguish between 6 φρόνιμος and ὁ φρονῶν 
(S.V.F. iii, p. 64, 3-5; cf. iii, frag. 244); and the same 
distinction between the appellative and the participle is 
implied by Chrysippus in S.V.F. iii, frag. 243 (De Stoic. 
Repug. 1046 r—1047 a infra). 

4 ὀνομάτων here must have been meant in this general 
sense, since Plutarch proceeds to represent the prepositions in 
composition as fragments of adverbs and not of what he calls 
nouns. Varro also appears to have taken the prepositions, 
which he called “‘ praeverbia,” to be adverbs (frag. 267, 4-7 
{Funaioli, Grammaticae Romanae Fragmenta i, Ὁ. 286]). 


127 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1011) “ λιθοβολεῖν Ny καὶ “ τοιχωρυχεῖν ’’* ἐπιταχύνοντες 


καὶ σφίγγοντες τὴν φράσιν λέγουσι. 

8. Διὸ χρείαν μέν τινα τῷ λόγῳ παρέχεται 
τούτων ἕκαστον, μέρος δὲ λόγου καὶ στοιχεῖον 
οὐδέν ἐστι, πλὴν ὥσπερ εἴρηται τὸ ῥῆμα καὶ 
τοὔνομα, ποιοῦντα τὴν πρώτην τό τ᾽ ἀληθὲς καὶ 
τὸ ψεῦδος δεχομένην σύνθεσιν, ἣν ot μὲν πρότασιν 

δ᾽ ἀξίωμα [ἰλάτων δὲ λόγον προσηγόρευκεν. 


1 τυχωρυχεῖν -X : τοιχορυχεῖν -ε. 





* Cf. Ammonius, De Interpretatione, p. 12, 27-30 and for 
the στοιχεῖον added by Plutarch in explanation of μέρος ibid., 
p. 64, 26-27 and S.V.F, ii, frag. 148 (p. 45, 9-11) with 
Scholia in Dionysit Thracis Artem Grammaticam, Ὁ. 356, 
1-4 and pp. 514, 35-515, 12 (Hilgard). 

δ See 1009 c supra. Of the six “ parts of speech ”’ besides 
noun and verb which had there been listed as present in 


128 





PLATONIC QUESTIONS x, 1011 
stones” and “breaking into houses” men say 
“ stoning ἡ and “ housebreaking.”’ 

8. Consequently, while each of these renders some 
service to speech, none is a part of speech, that is a 
constituent element of it,? except, as has been said,” 
the verb and the noun, for these produce the first 
combination admitting of truth and falsity, that 
combination which has been styled pronouncement 
by some and proposition by others but by Plato 
speech. 


dliad i, 185 Plutarch has accounted for al] except the adverb 
(ἐπίρρημα). With his neglect of this ef. what is said of the 
Stoics, τὰ ἐπιρρήματα οὔτε λόγου οὔτε ἀριθμοῦ ἠξίωσαν, παρα- 
φυάδι καὶ ἐπιφυλλίδι αὐτὰ παρεικάσαντες (Scholia in Dionysii 
Thracis Artem Grammaticam, p. 356, 15-16 and p. 520, 16-18 
{ Hilgard]), for whose treatment of the adverb cf. M. Pohlenz, 
Kleine Schriften i (Hildesheim, 1965), p. 55. 


129 













τ i ΣῊΝ : 5 ἢ τι 7 
Pata eu Ἱ ᾿ Ted 
7 ἊΨ ἢ Ὁ 
t cat: κα - ᾿ nt Ὶ ᾿ i. 
5 λ ἵ ! 4 } te 
= 1 bas: ἊΝ ys ᾿ ; 
᾿ ; 7 i if ~ ἢ py! i 
- - q ᾿ 
᾿ 


σὴ alte? 


Ἧς 


cuit i 
pad 

ἂν eae 

a 7 


4 sai or an ROU 
τ ΟῚ 3 ἢ ἊΝ Bear) A 


te. pupa rm αὶ nsec: 
“a si aki ald Re te thes acs srtcass 
, ve Phases: stra Ab 


Larter ee aR rm τῷ Ἶ: 
sestiaut ἢ ah ἣν separ δ τς “§ 
RIAD ORS ἃ γα ὥβηδδόλο, lane eane kha 

iwersabeler elt cid fev bi ἈΠΕ: τνχ νον 
τ LOAM, δῇ ΜΝ τ "th ead ag} T ae 
adie. Ὁ vend! we at acs oe On| hag Be. 
; ᾿ ; / 3 ἮΝ Ἢ ἬΝ 


ες ἦ 
, \ 
Ξ . 
Ὁ 
τ 
n\ 
ἢ 
Oe ᾿ 
| 7 i ἐξ if 
χὰ 
ay 
¢ 


= 


ON THE GENERATION OF 
THE SOUL IN THE 
TIMAEUS 


(DE ANIMAE PROCREATIONE 
IN TIMAEO) 





4 
7 Ay ᾿ ne 
i ἃ At 
¥ Re) ᾿ 
“Le ΞΖ 7 if 
4 a4 
LA ὅλη, Oe 
fy Ὁ)... iA & 
* hoe Ὁ" Mi 
a fine t ‘ ὸ ἢ 
“ἢ ᾿ 
F i i 
ὰ ist " Ὁ ᾿ Η U ἣν 
; Π “ — 
A eee ἢ Por 
᾿ ἐᾷν ψ τοῦ 
s μη 
Κι 4 
ὑπ νὼ 
μὴ ᾽ Rae 
‘ie bly es ie ae ay 
7 “ Vs a) 
a ¥ 





“πὸ Yor A παληὸ. am 


me es art ae ie 


* 


( ὴ f ν Φ ne ral ἤν; » 4 ' iy " vr ihe bees 
} Y , om re f } j MG 7 " 







~ ἣϊ : J 
M4 A ~ A i ἔν, ᾿ ‘ Nel 
J dj ee Ve 
é ἐν ᾿ ν 
ἵ ἜΝ 
an Γ 7 7 eT. ve he i 4 ee) 


INTRODUCTION 


Tuis essay, Plutarch says at the very beginning, was 
written because the two sons to whom he addresses 
it thought that he ought to bring together in a 
separate treatise what he had frequently said and 
had here and there written of the way he understood 
Plato’s doctrine of the soul, since this interpretation 
of his was not easy to manage otherwise and was in 
need of vindication. 

The two sons addressed, who were themselves not 
the oldest of Plutarch’s children (cf. Consolatio ad 
Uxorem 608 c and 609 p), could not have been much 
less than twenty years old when they made this 
suggestion, for it is assumed that they are familiar 
both with their father’s earlier writings and also with 
most of the extensive literature about the disputed 
passage of the Timaeus (cf. 1012 Ὁ and 1027 a [chap. 
29 init.| onfra). Plutarch, therefore, could not have 
been much less than forty-five years old and probably 
was a good deal older when he wrote the essay. In 
it he refers (1013 καὶ ifra) to an earlier treatise of his 
on the cosmogony as Plato meant it; and what in 
Plat. Quaest. 1V is together with II the essence of 
the interpretation developed in the present essay he 
there had already called τὸ πολλάκις ὑφ᾽ ἡμῶν λεγόμε- 
νον (1003 a). Aspects of it or parallels to certain aspects 
of it appear in the Quaest. Conviv., the De E, and the 


133 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


De Iside; but there is no conclusive evidence to 
prove that any of these is earlier or later than the 
present essay.” 

The essay is in form ἃ commentary on Timaeus 35 
A 1—36 B 5 and falls into two parts, each of which is 
begun by way of preface with the quotation of that 
section of the Platonic passage with which it deals, 
the first (chaps. 1-28 [1012 B—1027 a]) with the 
quotation of Timaeus 35 a 1-8 4 and the second 
(chaps. 29-33 [1027 a—1030 c])° with that of Timaeus 
35 B 4—36 B 5. 

This second part is expressly divided into three 
sections, in each of which one specific question is 
discussed and answered (1027 c-p): first, what the 
whole numbers are that Plato adopts in, the double 
and triple intervals and that will permit the insertion 
of the means described by him (1027 Ὁ-Ὲ and 1017 
c—1022 c [chaps. 30 and 11-19]); second, whether 
these numbers are to be arranged in a single row or 
in the figure of a lambda (1022 c-E and 1027 r— 
1028 a [chaps. 20 and 30 b]); and, third, what is 
their function or for what effect are they employed 
in the composition of the soul (1028 a—1030 c 


2 In 1029 ἢ here Plutarch asserts what in Quaest. Conviv. 
745 c-F he denies in his own person but then has Ammonius 
assert. It would be equally easy to make out a specious but 
inconclusive case for the priority of either passage to the 
other. 

> The traditional numbers of the chapters and the pagina- 
tion of Stephanus are retained, though they are confusing 
because they antedate the discovery and correction of the 
displacement in the mss. The order in the text as rearranged 
is: chaps. 1-10 (1012 a—1017 c), chaps. 21-30 (1022 r— 
1027 ¥F), chaps. 11-20 (1017 c—1022 &), chaps. 30 b-33 
(1027 r—1030 c). 


134 


GENERATION OF THE SOUL 


[chaps. 31-33]). All this by Plutarch’s own admission 
(1027 a {chap. 29 znit.] and 1022 c [chap. 20 znit.]}) 
contains little that is original; and it is of interest 
chiefly for the information that it provides about 
earlier treatments of Timaeus 35 B 4—36 B 5 and 
about the arithmological, musicological, and astro- 
nomical speculations related to them. With regard 
to the third question Plutarch rejects all the astro- 
nomical interpretations that he reports in chaps. 
31-32 and says that the ratios and numbers in this 
passage of the Zimaeus are meant to signify the 
harmony and concord of the soul itself (chap. 33 
[1029 p-r and 1030 B-c]). As to the second question, 
which receives the briefest treatment, he accepts 
Crantor’s arrangement because he thinks it almost 
explicitly prescribed by the order of the numbers in 
Plato’s text. The treatment of the first question is 
the longest, and in the course of it Plutarch reveals 
some of his characteristic weaknesses. He is aware 
of the correct contention that Plato is concerned not 
with any particular integers but with the ratios that 
alone are specified ; and yet he rejects it, ‘‘even if 
it be true,’ not only because it makes the matter 
harder to understand but also because it would pre- 
vent him from indulging himself in the arithmological 
speculations about the “ remarkable numbers ’’ to 
which he devotes several chapters (1027 v-F and 
1017 c—1019 B [chaps. 30 and 11-14]). Then as the 
base for the intervals into which the means are 
inserted he chooses 192 instead of 384 because “ the 
‘ leimma ’ will have its ratio expressed in the numbers 
that Plato has given, 256 to 243, if 192 is made the 
first number,’ thus arguing with misplaced literalness 
as if it were the very numbers and not just the ratio 


135 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


that Plato intended and at the same time showing 
that he could not have worked out the problem, 
since 192 will not serve the purpose of clearing the 
fractions after the first fourth (1020 c-p [chap. 16 sub 
jinem| and 1022 a [chap. 18 sub finem)). 

The originality of the first part of the essay is 
emphasized by Plutarch himself. At the very begin- 
ning he says that the interpretation here advocated 
requires vindication because it is opposed to that of 
most Platonists (1012 B), and after criticizing the 
interpretations of 72maeus 35 a 1-B 4 by Xenocrates 
and Crantor he repeats in beginning his own that he 
must vindicate what is unusual and paradoxical about 
it (1014). In the first place, he insists that contrary 
to what the Platonists contend Plato must have 
meant the generation of the universe and its soul to 
be understood literally as a beginning, for otherwise 
soul could not be senior to body and so there would 
be nothing to Plato’s argument against the atheists 
in the Laws (chap. 4, cf. chap. 3 zzt.). Plutarch 
holds, therefore, that according to Plato god did 
literally bring into being the soul and the body of 
the universe, though not from nothing, which is 
impossible, but from precosmic principles that had 
always existed, an amorphous and chaotic corpore- 
ality and a self-moved and irrational motivity that 
kept the former in disorderly turmoil (chap. 5). This 
irrational psychic principle Plutarch identifies with 
the “ infinitude ” of the Philebus, the “ congenital 
desire ’’ and “ inbred character ”’ of the Polticus, the 
“necessity” and even (1024 c) the precosmic 
γένεσις Of Timaeus 52 Ὁ and says is openly called in 
the Laws “ disorderly and maleficent soul ”’ (1014 p— 
1015 a [chap. 6]). It is, moreover, this, he maintains, 


136 


GENERATION OF THE SOUL 


that is the principle of evil whereby Plato avoided the 
absurdity into which the Stoics later fell, for the evil 
in the universe must have a cause and this cause 
cannot be god, who is entirely good, or matter, which 
is inert and without quality, but must be soul, which 
is the cause and principle of motion (1015 a-x [chaps. 
6-7}) ; and this irrational soul, “ soul in itself,’”’ it is 
that in the Phaedrus is proved to be indestructible 
because not subject to generation and not subject 
to generation because self-moved, the precosmic 
principle from which god by introducing into it 
intelligence and reason created the soul of the 
universe (chaps. 8-9), as he created its body out of 
precosmic matter by removing from this the cause of 
its turbulence and introducing into it form and 
symmetry (cf. 1015 Ε and 1016 p—1017 a). 

The “ creation’ in the Tzmaeus had already been 
taken literally by Aristotle and others but so far as is 
known not by anyone regarded as a Platonist,* and 
no one at all is known to have anticipated Plutarch 
in interpreting it with a theory of the cosmic soul 
such as his.2 This theory of his, despite all narrow 
literalism © and despite his protest against interpret- 

@ See note a on 1013 © (chap. 4 init.) infra. 

» Plutarch’s claim to the originality of his interpretation 
was accepted by Thévenaz (L’ Ame du Monde, pp. 55-56), 
and Helmer argued that there is no reason to doubt it (De 
An. Proc., pp. 69-70), though Plutarch’s “ general lack of 
originality ’» made Rh. M. Jones doubt that he could have 
been the author of the theory (Platonism of Plutarch, p. 80). 

¢ Such as the assumption that ἰδέα in the Posidonian in- 
terpretation must mean “idea” (see 1023 B-c [chap. 22] 
with note ὁ on 1023 8) and the crucial assumption that 
πρεσβυτέρα used of soul must mean senior in the sense of 
earlier in origin (see 1013 Ἐ-Ρ [chap. 4] and 1016 a-s {chap. 
8}), concerning which ef. Cherniss, Aristotle’s Criticism of 


137 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


ing Plato for the promotion of one’s own doctrines 
(1013 8), was not the consequence of his literal 
interpretation of the Timaeus but was the formulation 
of his own theology and theodicy, which, to be 
plausibly represented as in his words “ something 
that agrees with Plato,” required the “ creation ”’ in 
the Timaeus to be taken literally. This is indicated 
by the very reasons that he here gives for adopting 
this interpretation (1013 E-F and 1015 a-£) 4 and even 
more clearly by his way of manipulating Platonic 
texts to support it. Not only is there nothing in those 
texts to justify him in identifying with soul, as he 
does here, the “ infinitude ” of the Philebus or the 
“ necessity ἡ or γένεσις of the Timaeus, but these 
identifications are incompatible even with what he 
says in other passages himself.2 When he identifies 


Plato ..., pp. 424-426 and note 365 on pp. 429-431 and 
EK. de Strycker in Aristotle and Plato in the Mid-Fourth 
Century, ed. I. Diiring and G. E. L. Owen (Géteborg, 1960), 
pp. 90-91. F. Romano is mistaken, however, in supposing 
that Plutarch’s interpretation was simply the consequence of 
his “‘ cieco 6 pedissequo ossequio al verbo di Platone,”’ which 
made him incapable of distinguishing logos from mythos 
(Sophia, xxxiii [1965], p. 119 sub finem). 

« Cf. Zeller, Phil. Griech. 111, 2, p. 191; Andresen, Logos 
und Nomos, pp. 281, 284, and 290; H. Dérrie, Philomathes : 
Studies . . . in Memory of Philip Merlan (The Hague, 
1971), p. 46; and especially Babut, Plutarque et le Stoicisme, 
p. 287, who considers this essay to be primarily a polemic 
against Stoic monism and a continuation of Plutarch’s anti- 
Stoic works (op. cit., pp. 139-142). 

> For the ἀπειρία of the Philebus see page 185, note d 
(chap. 6); for the γένεσις of Timaeus 52 Ὁ see notes ὁ and d 
on 1024 c (chap. 24) and the comparison with De Facie 
926 F in note a on 1016 F (chap. 9); and for the ἀνάγκη of 
the Timaeus see note ¢ on 1014 £ (chap. 6) with Cherniss, 
Aristotle’s Criticism of Plato ..., pp. 446-450. As to the 


138 


GENERATION OF THE SOUL 


6 


with irrational soul the “ congenital desire” and 
“inbred character” in the myth of the Poltcus, 
adapting for this a quotation of Politicus 273 B 4-6, 
he suppresses Plato’s phrase, τὸ σωματοειδὲς τῆς 
συγκράσεως, Which would have embarrassed his in- 
terpretation 2; when he insists that in the proof of 
Phaedrus 245 c 5—246 a 2 the soul that is not subject 
to generation is meant to be only “ the soul that 
before the generation of the universe keeps all things 
in disorderly motion” (1016 a, 1016 c, 1017 a-B 
(chaps. 8-9]), he ignores both the words ψυχὴ πᾶσα 
with which that proof begins (Phaedrus 245 c 5) and 
of which the conclusion is certainly meant to hold 
and the express statement that it is impossible for 
the self-moving mover that sustains the universe, 2.e. 
the cosmic soul, either to perish or to come to be 


last, were ἀνάγκη. aS Plutarch here maintains, the precosmic 
irrational soul from which by mixture with νοῦς the soul of 
the cosmos was created, his interpretation would be open 
to the objection that he opposes to Crantor’s (1013 B-c, 
1023 a), for what he calls the psychogony would not be dis- 
tinguishable from the cosmogony, since Plato says μεμειγμένη 
yap οὖν ἡ τοῦδε TOU κόσμου γένεσις ἐξ ἀνάγκης TE Kai νοῦ συστά- 
σεως ἐγεννήθη (Timaeus 47 πὶ 5—48 a 2). 

¢ See note f on 1015 a (chap. 6). In this passage he also 
substitutes ἀνάγκη for the εἱμαρμένη of the Politicus (see 
note 6 on 1015 a); cf. his substitution of σφαῖρα for Plato’s 
dopa Or κύκλος (see note f on 1029 c [chap. 32]) and his 
insertion of ὕλη into quasi-quotations of the Timaeus (see the 
end of note c, page 173 [chap. 3]). Sometimes by omitting 
words or curtailing the original he alters the meaning of a 
passage (see note c on Plat. Quaest. 1004 & supra), thereby 
eliminating what would otherwise impugn his interpretation 
(see note d on 1016 F [chap. 9] and notes ἡ, ὁ, and ¢ on 1023 
Ἐ-Ε [chap. 23]); and sometimes he inserts into an apparent 
quotation what is in fact an erroneous inference of his own 
(see note b on Plat. Quaest. 1002 F supra). 


139 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(Phaedrus 245 τὶ 7-E 2); and, when he asserts that 
by all these Plato meant what in the Las he called 
disorderly and maleficent soul and that this is “ soul 
in itself,’ which became the soul of the universe 
(1014 p-E [chap. 6] and 1015 e[chap. 7]), he disregards 
the fact that the evil kind or aspect of soul there 
posited is never said to be precosmic or antecedent 
to beneficent soul or that out of which a single 
cosmic soul was created but to the contrary is repre- 
sented as being coeval with the good souls, the 
movers of the celestial bodies and the uniy verse, and 
distinct from them. 

All this is far from literal interpretation of Plato’s 
words ; and so is the identification of the ‘ divisible 
being ”’ in the psychogony of the T%maeus with the 
irrational and maleficent soul elicited from the Laws 
(1014 p-E [chap. 6] and 1015 & [chap. 7]). Neither in 
the psychogony nor elsewhere in the 7%maeus is 
there any mention of such an irrational soul or of 
any irrational element in the cosmic soul’; and 


: « Cf. Laws 896 pv 10-r 6, 898 « 6-—899 B 9, 904 a 6-c 4 

and πὶ 5-7, 906 a 2-7; see Cherniss, Proceedings of the 
American Philosophical Society, xcviii (1954), p. 26, n. 29. 
In De Iside 370 F Plutarch himself implies that what he takes 
to be the maleficent soul of the Laws is not antecedent to 
the beneficent soul but that the two are coeval and distinct, 
tor he says that according to Plato there (1.6, Laws 896 » 10- 
E 6) the universe is moved by at least two souls, one beneficent 
and the other adverse to this. 

δ Of. Cherniss, Aristotle's Criticism of Plato ..., p. 446 
with notes 386 and 387 and Proceedings of the American 
Philosophical Society, xeviii (1954), Ὁ. 26 with notes 26-28, 
The soul that in Timaeus 44 a4 7-8 1 is said to become ἄνους 
is only the human soul when disturbed in consequence of its 
embodiment (cf. 86 B 2—-87 a 7); even in that soul there 
is no irrationality in the ‘“‘ immortal part’? produced by the 


140 





GENERATION OF THE SOUL 


Plutarch’s assertion that this is what Plato meant by 
οὐσίας... τῆς av περὶ TA σώματα γιγνομένης μεριστῆς 
(Timaeus 35 a 2-3) is made without any supporting 
argument? and apparently in reliance upon the mere 
assumption that in the Laws the proper name is used 
for that to which Plato elsewhere must have been 
referring covertly in enigmatic and metaphorical 
terms,” a principle so pliable that in the very passage 
where it is enunciated this maleficent soul of the 
Laws is identified not, as it is in this essay, with the 
‘divisible being ’’ but with the “ difference,” the 
θάτερον, of the psychogony.° 

Identifying the “ divisible being ” of the psycho- 
gony with precosmic irrational soul from which god 
by introducing into it intelligence and reason created 
the soul of the universe ought to imply moreover 
that the “ indivisible being ” there is νοῦς ; and Plu- 
tarch does explicitly make this identification also,? 


demiurge, the circles of sameness and difference, when not so 
disturbed (44 B 1-7), while the “ mortal and passible part ”’ 
of it (.e. the θυμοειδές and ἐπιθυμία). which Plutarch derives 
froin the ‘ divisible being,’ > is in the Timaeus a confection 
of the “ὁ created gods’ and is unrelated to the ingredients 
or the result of the psychogony (see note ¢ on 1026 pb [chap. 
27 sub finem)). 

« The later attempts to account for the term μεριστή j (1024 4 
[chap. 23] and 1024 c [chap. 24]) are not arguments in sup- 
port of this identification and would not be cogent if they 
were intended to be so. 


ὑ Cf. 1014 ν (. . . ἐν δὲ τοῖς Νόμοις ἄντικρυς oe + εἴρηκε 
.) with De Iside 370 E-F (πολλαχοῦ μὲν ΠΟ ae παρα- 
TNE 4 ἐν ἐν δὲ τοῖς Νόμοις . - - οὐ δι᾽ αἰνιγμῶν οὐδὲ 


συμβολικῶς ἀλλὰ κυρίοις ὀνόμασιν. . . 
¢ De Iside 370 Ἐ-Ὲ ; see page 251, note eon 1025 νυ infra. 
¢ See infra 1014 v-£ (ἐν δὲ Seay τὴν τῇ ἀμερίστῳ συγκε- 
ραννυμένην . . . αὕτη. ++ νοῦ . . . μετέσχεν, ἵνα κόσμου ψυχὴ 


141 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


although in the Zimaeus not only is there no men- 
tion of precosmic νοῦς as an ingredient in the 
constitution of soul but in a passage from which Plu- 
tarch conveniently omits νοῦς 5 the latter is said to 
arise in the soul after its constitution and organiza- 
tion and as a result of its contact with the ideas. 
Plutarch’s one attempt to justify his identification is 
an explication of the sense in which the terms ἀμερὲς 
Kal ἀμέριστον are used; but in this sense even 
according to him they characterize the incorporeal 
and intelligible as such, and so they are in fact more 
appropriately used of the being of the ideas and can 
be supposed to refer to νοῦς only because he takes 
νοῦς to be a νοητόν." Since for him it is god, how- 
ever, the νοητόν par excellence® and the only true 
being,? that is vois,* although in arguing against the 
Posidonians he contends that god’s relation to soul 
is that of artificer to finished product (1023 c infra), 
he nevertheless asserts that the νοῦς introduced by 


 yévnra.), 1016 c with note c, 1024 4 (page 229, note d), 1024 c-p 
(ὁ δὲ νοῦς . . - ἐγγενόμενος δὲ τῇ ψυχῇ - - - ἡ κοινωνία γέγονεν 
αὐτῶν, τῷ ἀμερίστῳ τὸ μεριστὸν ...) with note c there for an 
additional misrepresentation of the Platonic text. 

α Timaeus 37 c 1-3; see infra 1023 ¥F with note c there. 

» See infra page 214, note α and the references there to 
Plat. Quaest, 1002 c-p and 1002 rE. 

¢ See infra 1016 B with note ὦ and the reference there to 
Plat. Quaest. 1002 B; and cf. De Istde 372 a, where Osiris 
is the οὐσία νοητή of which the sun is the visible light. 

4 Cf. De E 392 a (... μόνην μόνῳ προσήκουσαν τὴν τοῦ εἶναι 
προσαγόρευσιν . - -) and 393 a-s. 

e Cf. De Iside 371 a (in the soul of the universe Osiris is 
νοῦς καὶ λόγος). 373 B (Osiris is λόγος αὐτὸς καθ᾽ ἑαυτὸν ἀμιγὴς 
καὶ ἀπαθής). and 376 ὁ (ὁ τοῦ θεοῦ νοῦς καὶ λόγος ἐν τῷ ἀοράτῳ 
καὶ ἀφανεῖ βεβηκὼς εἰς γένεσιν ὑπὸ κινήσεως προῆλθεν). 


142 


GENERATION OF THE SOUL 


god into the irrational soul is itself a part of god? ; 
and so he implicitly makes the “ indivisible being ” 
of the Zimaeus substantially identical with the 
demiurge, which is itself to renounce the literal 
interpretation of Plato’s text. Moreover, in 1024 
c-p (chap. 24), where of the three, ov and ywpa and 
γένεσις, Said in Timaeus 52 Ὁ 2-4 to have been 
before heaven came to be, Plutarch identifies the 
last with the irrational soul, the second with matter, 
and the first with the intelligible, the real existence 
that always remains fixed and of which semblances 
are dispersed in this world, he introduces without 
explanation or reference to the text that he has 
quoted a νοῦς which was “ abiding and immobile all 
by itself ’ before it got into the soul ; and this νοῦς 
he explicitly identifies with the “ indivisible being ” 
of the psychogony. This must be the vods that is 
substantially identical with god, added as a fourth 
to the precosmic three of Timaeus 52 Ὁ 2-4, for it 
cannot be identical with the ὄν, which Plutarch him- 
self here clearly—and correctly (cf. Timaeus 52 a 1-4 
and c ὅ- 1 with 48 κΕ 5-6)—treats as the being of 
the ideas, the stable and real existence with which, 
as he says, the circular motion of the soul made 
rational is most closely in contact; but this is to 
make Plato omit from the three that he lists as pre- 
cosmic the “indivisible being” which he clearly 
treats as such in the psychogony and which must be the 
ὄν among the three that he here lists, not a fourth 
such as that gratuitously introduced by Plutarch. 

* See infra 1016 c with note d and Plat. Quaest. 1001 ς 
referred to there. 


> See 1016 c, Plat. Quaest. 1001 c, and the passages of the 
De Iside, which are cited in the last two preceding notes. 


143 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


That the “ indivisible being ” of the psychogony 
is the being of the ideas and the “ divisible being ” 
the dispersed being of phenomena, not νοῦς and the 
irrational soul, as Plutarch insists, and not ingredients 
of soul but external to soul, which after it has been 
constituted judges them by coming into contact now 
with the one and again with the other, this is clear 
from another passage of the T%tmaeus, which is 
partially paraphrased and partially quoted by 
Plutarch himself but for his own purpose and in a 
mutilated form that obscures its significance. At 
the beginning of this passage which he omits (77- 
maeus 37 a 2-4) it is emphasized that the ingre- 
dients of soul were three. This was twice said in the 
passage of the psychogony (Timaeus 35 a 6-7 and B 1) 
quoted by him at the beginning of his essay (1012 
B-c infra), where it was explained that of these three 
ingredients one is a “ third kind of being ” blended 
by the demiurge between the “ indivisible being ” 
and the “ divisible being ” and the other two are a 
_ sameness and a difference also constructed between 
the indivisible and the divisible sameness and 
difference. This intermediacy of the ingredients 
sameness and difference eluded Plutarch altogether, 


@ Timaeus 37 a 2-—c 5, where in 37 «a 5-8 8 the soul of the 
universe is said now to touch something that has οὐσία 
σκεδαστή, ἐ.6. μεριστή (cf. Plotinus, Hnn. tv, ii, 1, line 12 
and Proclus, In Platonis Timaeum ii, p. 298, 24-25 [Diehl]), 
which is one of τὰ γιγνόμενα, 1.6. the perceptible of 37 5 6, 
and now something that has οὐσία ἀμέριστος. which is one of 
τὰ κατὰ ταὐτὰ ἔχοντα ἀεί, 1.6. the rational of 37 ¢ 1 (cf. 
Proclus, 7bid., p. 300, 5-10 and 17-19 [Dieh!] and Cherniss, 
-tristotle’s Criticism of Plato ..., pp. 407-408); for Plu- 
tarch’s paraphrase of 37 a ὅ- 3 and quotation of 37 B 3- 
c 5 see infra pages 225, note f and 227, notes ὁ and ὡς. 


144 


GENERATION OF THE SOUL 


as it has eluded many modern interpreters ; and 
that of the “ third kind of being ”’ he misinterpreted 
by neglecting the statement that this is only one 
ingredient of soul and by taking it to be the literal 
mixture of “ indivisible ’’ and “ divisible being ’’ 4 
identified with νοῦς and the irrational soul, with the 
result that in fact he made the soul of the universe a 
mixture of these two ingredients alone” or again a 


be The i blending yi (συνεκεράσατο [1 μασι a ἂὶ 9}) οἵ 
the * third kind of being ” like the construction of the inter- 
mediate sameness and difference (κατὰ ταὐτὰ συνέστησεν 
[35 a 5]) is a figurative expression for the construction of a 
mean between two extremes (cf. Porphyry in Proclus, /n 
Platonis Timaeum ii, pp. 162, 31-163, 1 [Diehl] and Proclus, 
ihid,, ii, pp. 149, 14-150, 24 and p. 156, 16-24 [Diehl] ; 
Themistius, De 4nima, p. 11, 1-4; Simplicius, De -fnima, 
p. 259, 11-29; [Philoponus], De .{nima iii [i.e. Stephanus], 
p. 504, 8-12). The figure is used by Plutarch himself when 
he says that means involve τὴν τῶν ἄκρων ..- πρὸς ἄλληλα διὰ 
τοῦ λόγου σύγκρασιν (Plat. Quaest. 1009 a-B); and yet, 
when he uses as a “ likeness of the proportion ’”’ in the 
psychogony the insertion of two means between extremes 
in 7imaeus 31 B 4—32 c 4, he makes of the mathematical 
procedure in that passage a physical “ fusion ” and employs 
in his résumé of it the words ἐκέρασεν and συνέμιξε, which 
Plato there does not use in any form (see infra 1025 a-1 
[chap. 25] with note f there). 

δ See 1014 Ἑ (chap. 6): αὕτη yap ἦν ψυχὴ καθ᾽ ἑαυτήν, vod 
dé... μετέσχεν, ἵνα κόσμου ψυχὴ γένηται ἃπα 1024 4 (chap. 29) : 

. κόσμου ψυχὴν συνίστησιν ἐξ ὑποκειμένων τῆς τε κρείττονος 
οὐσίας καὶ ἀμερίστου καὶ τῆς χείρονος, ἣν περὶ τὰ σώματα μεριστὴν 
κέκληκεν. .-. A striking modern parallel is provided ee ES 
l’riedlander (Plato iii [Princeton University Press, 1969], p. 
366), who without reference to Plutarch and despite his biblio- 
graphy (pp. 543-544) in obvious ignorance of the correct 
construction of 7imaeus 35 a 1- 4 says: “ The ingredients 
... are, first, the being that is indivisible . . . and second, 
the being that is divisible. . . . That would be enough, but 
in order to emphasize the difficulty of the mixture... he 


145 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


blend of four ingredients when to account for the 
obvious presence of sameness and difference in the 
psychogony he took these to be two extremes with 
the “ indivisible being ”’ and the “ divisible ᾿᾿ as two 
intermediates between them.* Plato’s emphatic 
warning that the ingredients of soul are three he 
simply disregarded. 

Similar treatment of Plato’s text and similar 
internal contradictions characterize Plutarch’s literal 
interpretation of the generation of the physical 
universe. A single example will suffice. Timaeus 
begins his account of the creation by saying in a 
passage on which Plutarch lays much stress that god 
took over all that was visible ® but later says that he 
constructed the world visible and tangible.* Instead 
of explaining how these two statements can both be 


adds as a third component the mixture of the previous two— 
or, as it may be put differently (35 a 3-4), the mixture of 
‘the same ’ and ‘ the different.’ ”’ 

4 See 1025 s (chap. 25, where the proportion of four terms 
in Timaeus 32 B 3-7 is expressly cited as parallel to this) 
and note 6 there with references. It is the “‘ divisible being "ἢ 
itself that Plutarch elsewhere calls intermediate, transferring 
to it, which identified with irrational soul or ‘‘ soul in itself ”’ 
he makes an ingredient of *‘ created soul,’”’ the intermediacy 
of the three ingredients in the psychogony (see 1015 5 
[chap. 6] with note c, 1024 B [chap. 23] with note d, and 
1024 c [chap. 24] with note d), two of which, sameness and 
difference, his interpretation fits so ill that in trying to explain 
them he flagrantly contradicts himself (see 1024 p [chap, 24] 
with note f, 1025 a [chap. 24] with note b, and 1027 a 
[chap. 28] with note a). 

> Timaeus 30 a 3-4 (πᾶν ὅσον ἦν ὁρατὸν παραλαβὼν .. «) 3 
see infra 1016 p with note g. 

ὁ Timaeus 32 B 7-8 (. . . συνεστήσατο οὐρανὸν ὁρατὸν καὶ 
ἁπτόν) : cf. 36 πὶ 5-6, 

146 





GENERATION OF THE SOUL 


taken literally? Plutarch simply omits “ visible and 
tangible ᾿᾿ from his quotation of the latter passage,” 
for he maintains that god did not create the tangi- 
bility of the matter out of which he formed the 
physical universe but that this was perceptible and 
corporeal’; and yet elsewhere he insists that 
Platonic “‘ matter ” is entirely without quality and 
becomes tangible and visible by participating in the 
intelligible and simulating it.4 

So Plutarch’s interpretation upon closer inspection 
proves to be far from “ literal.’’ His motive was not 
strict fidelity to Plato’s words but concern to enlist 
Plato’s authority for the proposition that the universe 
was brought into being by god; and, since he says 
himself why he thought it necessary to insist upon 
such a beginning of the universe, the course of his 
reasoning can be plausibly explicated in the following 
manner. Soul as such must have existed without 
beginning, for, as Plato says himself, soul is self- 
moving motion, which itself is not subject to genera- 
tion or destruction. This soul cannot be the soul of 
the universe, however, for, if it were, it would without 
beginning have always been producing in body the 
motions of the corporeal universe just as they are 
now organized by the soul of the universe ¢ ; and this 


α For the bearing of the contradiction on the question 
whether the creation was meant to be taken literally cf. 
L. Taran in Essays in Ancient Greek Philosophy edited by 
J. P. Anton with G. L. Kustas (Albany, State Univ. of New 
York Press, 1971), pp. 382-384 with notes 98-104. 

δ See infra 1016 F with note d. 

¢ See infra pages 183, note d; 185, note c; 229, note 7. 

@ See infra 1014 F with note ὁ and 1013 c with note d. 

¢ See infra 1030 c (chap. 33 sub finem), and Plat. Quaest. 
1003 a-B. 


147 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


corporeal universe, if it had been so organized always 
and without beginning, would be coeval with soul, in 
which case there would be neither cogent evidence 
for the existence of god (see infra 1013 E-F) nor any 
need of his existence.¢ Therefore the existence of 
god requires that the soul of the universe have had 
a beginning antecedent to that of the corporeal uni- 
verse organized by it. This beginning, however, 
could not have been a coming to be from what was 
not soul, since as soul it is without beginning, and so 
could have been only a change in preexisting soul 
such as would account for the regular motions of an 
ordered corporeal universe, 2.6. a change in self- 
motion from the disorderly or demented to the 
orderly and rational, which must have been caused 
by the introduction of νοῦς into the soul already 
existing. Therefore Plato, despite what he seems to 
say in the Zimaeus, must have meant not that the 
demiurge created the substance of soul but that he 
compounded the soul of the universe by blending 
νοῦς with irrational soul, the vestigial irrationality of 
which is the cause of the evil in the universe as the 
rationality imposed upon it by god is the cause of 
the good®; and consequently the essential in- 
gredients in the psychogony must be these two, both 


¢ According to Atticus, who adopted Plutarch’s interpreta- 
tion (see note a on 1013 τ infra), Plato, reasoning that what 
has not come to be needs no creator or guardian for its well- 
being, ἵνα μὴ ἀποστερήσῃ τὸν κόσμον τῆς προνοίας ἀφεῖλε τὸ 
ἀγένητον cone (hatiettes Sisley iv ‘Bande Μι ταν τὴν tre 
Evang. xv, 6, 2 {ii, p. 359, 14-18, Mras]) : and Plutarch is said 
to have called the divine cause πρόνοια (Proclus, In Platonis 
Timaeum i, Ὁ. 415, 18-20 [Diehl]; see Plat. Quaest. 1007 ¢ 
with note ἢ there). 

δ See infra 1026 Ὁ-Ὲ (chap. 27) and 1027 a (chap. 98). 
148 


GENERATION OF THE SOUL 


preexisting and without beginning, νοῦς and the 
self-motion that is soul in itself. 

This interpretation has won for Plutarch the praise 
of some modern scholars for acuteness and ingenuity 
and even for “ fathoming the thought of Plato better 
than did Plato’s immediate disciples.’’? In fact, it 
is instructive chiefly because it shows how Plutarch 
could manipulate for his own purpose philosophical 
texts still available for comparison with his treatment 
of them and what arbitrariness and contradictions are 
involved in an attempt to prove Platonic the dogma 
of “‘ creation ᾿᾿ as an historical beginning. 

A Latin translation of the essay made by Turnebus 
was published in 1552. The first edition of the 
Greek text restored to its original order was pub- 
lished in 1848 by A. D. Maurommates*¢; and in 
1873 B. Miller, who in 1870 had independently 


α So Thévenaz, L’ Ame du Monde, p. 95. Helmer (De An. 
Proc., p. 66) says that Plutarch’s ‘* Scharfsinn ” can seldom 
be refused recognition. R. Del Re tries to defend Plutarch’s 
interpretation even in the crucial and embarrassing matter 
of the ‘‘ divisible being” (Studi Italiani di Filologia 
Classica, N.S. xxiv [1949], pp. 51-64 [”.b. pp. 56-57]) ; and 
J. B. Skemp, while taking the “ἡ analytic’ view of the 
Timaeus ... as at any rate the more probable,” nevertheless 
treats Plutarch’s interpretation very seriously (The Theory 
of Motion in Plato’s Later Dialogues, Enlarged Edition 
[Amsterdam, 1967], pp. x, xiv, 26-27, 59, 76, 111-112, and 
149). 

> Plutarchi Chaeronei De Procreatione Animi in Timaeo 
Platonis Adriano Turnebo interprete. Parisiis, Ex officina 
Adriani Turnebi Typographi Regis. M.D. LII. 

© Τ]λουτάρχου περὶ τῆς ἐν Τιμαίῳ ψυχογονίας, ἐκδόντος καὶ εἰς 
τὴν ἀρχαίαν συνέχειαν ἀποκαταστήσαντος ᾿Ανδρέου A. Μαυρομ- 
μάτου Κορκυραίου, Ἔν ᾿Αθήναις. 1848. The text, based chiefly 
on that of Diibner, is preceded by an essay on the restoration 
of the proper order and followed by ten pages of notes. 


149 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


discovered this order, published another edition of 
it. There are two monographs devoted entirely to 
the essay. One of them by Joseph Helmer is entitled 
Zu Plutarchs ‘* De animae procreatione in Timaeo”’ : 
Ein Beitrag zum Verstdindms des Platon-Deuters 
Plutarch (Wiirzburg, 1937 [Diss. Miinchen]). The 
other by Pierre Thévenaz, L’Ame du Monde, le 
Devenir et la Matiéere chez Plutarque (Paris, 1938), is a 
systematic study preceded by an annotated trans- 
lation into French of the first part of the essay, 2.e. 
chaps. 1-10 (1012 B—1017 c) and 21-28 (1022 E— 
1027 a). There are two earlier monograplis of wider 
range in which the study of this essay is an important 
part, Plutarcht Chaeronensis studia in Platone ex- 
plicando posita by Herbert Holtorf (Stralesundiae, 
1913 [Diss. Greifswald]) and The Platonism of 
Plutarch by Roger M. Jones (Menasha, 1916 [ Diss. 
Chicago]). Unfortunately none of these four authors 
was aware of the correct construction of Tzmaeus 
35 a 1-8 1, first pointed out in modern times ap- 
parently by G. M. A. Grube (Class. Phil., xxvii 
᾿ς [1932], pp. 80-82), the crucial passage with which 
Plutarch begins his exposition. 

The De Animae Procreatione in Timaeo is No. 65 in 
the Catalogue of Lamprias and No. 77 in the Planu- 
dean order. The text of it here printed is based 
upon E Be uf mr? Escor. 72, all of which have been 

α Plutarch iiber die Seelenschépfung im Timaeus, von 
Berthold Miiller, Breslau, 1873 (Gymnasium zu St. Elisabet. 
Bericht iiber das Schuljahr 1872-1873). The text is based 
chiefly on E, and the apparatus reports mainly the readings 
of that μ8.. the Epitome, and the Aldine. 

> y is Leiden B.P.G. 59 and not Voss. 59 as it is called in 


Hubert-Drexler, Moralia vi/1, pp. xv1 and xx; cf. Biblio- 
theca Universitatis Leidensis : Codices Manuscripti—VIII : 


150 





GENERATION OF THE SOUL 


collated from photostats.? In all these mss. there is 
the same displacement of chapters 21-30 (1022 E— 
1027 Fr) from their proper place immediately after 
chapter 10, a displacement discovered first by A. D. 
Maurommates (Π]λουτάρχου περὶ τῆς ἐν Τιμαίῳ 
ψυχογονίας ...[Athens, 1848], pp. ιβ΄-ιε) and later 
independently by B. Miller (Hermes, iv [1870], pp. 
390-403; cf. v [1871], ᾿ 154) and again still later 
by P. Tannery (Rev. Etudes Grecques, vii [1804], 
pp. 209-211). All these mss., therefore, derive from 
one ancestor, but their differences at the junctures 
resulting from the displacement show that they were 
not all copied from a single archetype and suggest 
the division of them into groups that is confirmed by 
their variations throughout the essay. At these 
junctures E and B are alike; e and u are alike and 


Codices Bibliothecae Publicae Graeci descripsit K. A. de 
Meyier adiuvante E. Hulshoff Pol (Lugduni Batavorum, 
1965), p. 82. For confirmation of this fact as well as for 
the correct photostats I am obliged to the generosity of 
Dr. de Meyier. 

4 I report the readings of Escor. 72 because they seem to 
have remained unknown hitherto. From Oxoniensis Coll. 
Corp. Christi 99 (C.C.C. 99) I report only one correct reading, 
for my collation of this ms. has confirmed the statement 
(Hubert-Drexler, Moralia vi/1, Ὁ. xv1) that it is close to f, m, r 
and especially close to r, with which in fact it agrees against. 
all others seventy-six times, though it cannot be their source, 
since it disagrees with all of them at least eighteen times, in 
five of which it lacks words that they preserve. For Marciani 
184, 187, and 523, which I have not collated, cf. B. Miiller 
(1873), pp. 3-4 and Hubert-Drexler, op. cit., pp. xv-xvt. 

> Here (p. 403, n. 1) Miiller reports that the correct order 
had already been indicated in a marginal note made by 
Deodat Grihe ; but, since Gréhe published his doctoral dis- 
sertation in 1867, his note could scarcely have been made 
before Maurommates’ publication. 


151 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


different from E, B; f, m, r are substantially alike 
and different from both E, B and e, u; and Escor. 72 
agrees in part with e, u and in part with f, m, r (see 
the critical apparatus on 1022 καὶ following 1017 Ὁ, 
chapter 21 mit.). The text of the Aldine at one 
juncture is closest to that of e, u and at the other 
two agrees with that of m, r. 

B agrees with E (or with E corrected) against all 
the other mss. more than eighty times, indicating 
lacunae where all the others show none but instead 
have words or letters missing from E and B (ef. 
1015 οἰ rod... θέντος], 1015 ἢ [ws .. . τὴν], 1024 E 
[τῶν . . . ἐπικρατεῖ])), omitting words that all the 
others preserve (cf. 1014 a [περὶ τούτων], 1025 B 
[ἀλλὰ], 1018 B [ὧν]), and preserving words omitted 
by all the others (cf. 1027 c [καὶ τριπλασίοις], 1018 A 
[καὶ ποιοῦσαι .. .|). B alone or in agreement with 
others differs from E in forty-nine places; but the 
negligence of the scribe of B might be held to 
account for many of these differences * and his own 
acumen for others,® although he must have been 
-~more than acute to have added the καὶ that E and 
all the others omit in διὰ τὸ καὶ τὰς apyas. . . (1025 E).° 

α It is difficult to believe that negligence alone can explain 
εὐρύθμως for the εὐσήμως of EK (1019 A) or συνήθειαν (unre- 
corded in Hubert-Drexler, Moralia vi/1, p. 179) for the per- 
fectly clear συνήχησιν of E (1021 B). 

> e.g. for τῇ ὕλῃ καὶ ὑπ᾽ ἐκείνης (1016 Ὁ), where E alone 
omits καὶ (unrecorded in Hubert-Drexler, ibid., p. 153), and 
for “Apeos (1029 B), where E with all others except f, m, r 
has ἀέρος. 

¢ One of the eight cases of difference added by D. A. 
Russell (Class. Rev., N.S. v [1955], p. 161) to the “ crucial 
instance ’’ (p. 170, 9 f. [Hubert-Drexler] =1018 B: ἐν ὅσαις 


ἡμέραις [μοίραις]) adduced in Hubert-Drexler, zbzd., p. xvi as 
proof that B is independent of E. Of Russell’s seven remain- 


152 


GENERATION OF THE SOUL 


This and the ἣν δὴ ὁ θεὸς αὐτὸς of B in 1017 a-s, 
where E has τὴν δὲ αὐτὸς ὁ Geos,” look like genuine 
variants rather than mere “ slips”’ or arbitrary 
emendations ; and so does the καὶ that B alone has 
between τῷ ἐπογδόῳ and τῷ ἐπιτρίτῳ in 1022 c 
(chapter 19 sub finem), for something is certainly 
missing here and the erroneous καὶ may be a mis- 
reading by B of some sign to that effect in his original. 
There are indications, then, that this essay in B 
was not copied directly from E, though it must be 
admitted that none of them is tantamount to 
definitive proof. 

While e and u are frequently in agreement with 
f, m, r against E and B® and more frequently in 
agreement with E, B against f, m, r,° it is still more 


ing cases two (171. 3 and 176. 20, @.e. [ἀφ᾽ [ἐφ᾽ in 1018 B and 
ἀντὶ ὄντι in 1020 a) are merely errors in the critical apparatus 
of Hubert-Drexler, four others (150. 13, 159. 12, 163. 10, 
187. 21 [Hubert-Drexler]) are cases in which the text of B 
might be accounted for by the corrections in EK, and the 
seventh (156. 8 [Hubert-Drexler]=1022 τ: θήγουσα for 
θιγοῦσα) is an error shared by B with τι], a fact not recorded 
by Hubert-Drexler, as four other cases of the agreement of 
u with B in error against all the others have also gone un- 
recorded, though to many these might seem to be more 
significant than the “ crucial instance’ of 1018 B where B 
neglects two letter-spaces left vacant in E between ὅσαις and 
μοίραις. 

ἃ ἣν δὲ αὐτὸς ὁ θεὸς is the reading of e!. Neither this 
nor the reading of B is recorded in Hubert-Drexler (ibid., 
p. 154, 26). 

ὃ Besides such cases as 1025 B and 1027 c already men- 
tioned for the agreement of E and B against all the others 
see especially 1018 B (καὶ τὰ ιβ΄) and 1028 A (μονονουχὶ οὖν). 

¢ There are more than a score of cases, among which see 
τρίτα for ἐπίτριτα and the omission of πρὸς τὰ γ΄ καὶ μ΄ Kai σ΄ 
in 1021 &. 


155 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


common for e and u or for e and u with Escor. 72 to 
be in agreement against all the others. Neverthe- 
less, e and u are clearly independent of each other, 
for they differ from each other in more than sixty 
places, in forty of which u is alone in error but in at 
least one of which it agrees with f, m, r in correctly 
preserving a word that is not in e or in the others 
(1017 F [καὶ τοῦ 1B’|), while in several places e pre- 
serves words that are lacking in u, most notably a 
passage of 21 words that the latter omits (1019 F 
[ἐν δὲ τοῖς τριπλασίοις . . . οὕτω γίγνεται μέσος }). 
While in agreement with e and u against E and B 
at least a dozen times and in five of these with 
words that are not in E or B at all,> f, m, and r are 
clearly independent of e and u, since in about a 
dozen passages all three of them agree in having 
words that are absent from both e and u“; but f, 
m, and r, although they agree against all the others 
in more than sixty places and in more than a score 
of these alone preserve the correct text, are them- 
selves independent of one another, for besides other 
striking differences each of them preserves words 
that the other two do not have.¢ Of the three the 


* Of the two score cases and more see 1015 D (ὡς οὐκ εὖ 
τὴν), 1017 B (see the critical apparatus on μέγα), 1023 E 
(λέγειν), 1027 B-c (καὶ ὑπερεχομένην . . . ὑπερέχουσαν omitted by 
e, u, Escor, 72). 

> See 1014 a, 1018 B (twice), 1025 B, and 1028 a. 

¢ Of these the most significant are 1027 B-c (καὶ ὑπερεχο- 
μένην . - « ὑπερέχουσαν), 1018 a (see the critical apparatus on 
καὶ ποιοῦσαι), 1020 a (καὶ τοῖς τριπλασίοις). and 109] Ἑ (πρὸς 
τὰ γ΄ καὶ μ΄ καὶ σ΄). In all these cases the Aldine also lacks the 
words preserved by f, m, r. 

@ Of the many cases see e.g. 1020 p and 1028 p for words 
in f and m that are not inr; 1025 Fr, 1019 p, and 1021 c for 


154 


GENERATION OF THE SOUL 


text of m is most nearly intact and the best by 
far. 

Escor. 72,5 though it often agrees with f, m, and r 
against e and u and more often with e and u against 
f, m, and r and in both cases frequently agrees with 
E and B, was not copied from any of these mss. 
From E and B it differs more than eighty times and 
in at least seven of these exhibits in agreement with 
e and u or with f, m, and r or with all five of them 
words that are absent from both E and B.° So also, 
while f, m, and r have words that it lacks,° it pre- 
serves words that are missing from them, as it does 
others that are missing from e or from u.¢ Although 
like f, m, and r more recent than the Aldine, like 
them (see page 154, note ὁ supra) it too preserves 
words that are lacking in the Aldine,’ from which it 


words inmandrthatarenotinf; 1024 a, 1025 p,and 1019 £ 
for words in f or r that are not in m. 

* The contents of this ms. (D-I-12) are of different dates, the 
De Animae Procreatione in Timaeo (ff. 75*-87") being of the 
16th century according to P. A. Revilla, Catdlogo de los 
Cédices Griegos de la Biblioteca de El Escorial 1 (Madrid, 
1936), p. 253 and p. 255 (No. 13). 

> See 1012 8B, 1014 4, 1015 v, 1024. 5, 1025 B, 1018 B, 1028 a. 

¢ There are more than a dozen such cases to testify that 
f, m, and r do not derive from Escor. 72; see especially 
ard. (καὶ τοῖς τριπλασίοις) and 1021 E (πρὸς τὰ γ΄ καὶ μ΄ 
καὶ σ΄). 

4 There are half a dozen cases of this, the most striking 
being 1022 5, where a whole clause is missing from f, m, r ; 
in 1025 F it is f alone that omits eleven words, and in 1025 ὁ 
f and r that omit ten. 

¢ See 1027 νυ (περὶ δὲ τῆς τάξεως) and 1029 a (πέντε τετρα- 
χόρδων), and for ualone 1019 F (ἐν δὲ τοῖς τριπλασίοις + « ἃ 

Γ See the critical apparatus on 1016 Ἐ (καὶ τὴν), 1017 B 
(τεκμήριόν ἐστι μέγα), and 1024 α (καὶ τῆς χείρονος). 

155 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


differs in more than thirty passages * and with which 
it is alone in agreement against all the other mss. 
only twice.2 When it agrees with the Aldine against 
other ss., it is usually at the same time in agree- 
ment with e and u or at least with e. 

The Aldine itself cannot have been taken from E 
or B, with both of which it disagrees more than a 
hundred times and with neither of which it ever 
agrees against all the other mss.° In at least a dozen 
places it exhibits words that are in other mss. but 
are missing from E; and Β ὦ ; and at 1027 B-c it agrees 
exactly with e, u, and Escor. 72 in a mutilated text 
entirely different from the text of Τὰ and B, although 
other passages prove that it could not have been 
taken from e or u either.¢ Nor could it have been 


α See 9.5. the critical apparatus on 1016 8B (συνέρξας). 
1024 Ἐ (κρίσις), 1018 a (τὰ μὲν yap), 1022 a (ἀναλόγως ἤδη), 
1030 c (ἐμμέλειαν). 

> See the critical apparatus on 1017 a (ταῦτα δὴ δεῖ) and 
1021 π (κατὰ τὸν βαρύτατον). In 1020 ἢ (υπς") Escor. 42 has 
ὃ superscript over ς΄, a miscorrection that might have come 
from the Aldine (u78’) or from the source of f, m, r (υοδ΄). 
There are more than half a dozen cases in which Escor. 72 
has been corrected to a reading in which the Aldine and 
f, m, r agree. 

¢ The nearest it comes to this is at 1029 p where for the 
first word in chapter 33 (σκοπεῖτε) it agrees with E, B, and 
r against all the others. 

4 See ¢.g. the critical apparatus on 1014 α (περὶ rovTwr), 
1015 ἢ (ὡς οὐκ εὖ τὴν), 1024 (πλανήτων), 1025 B (ἄδεκτον 
οὖσαν ἀλλὰ). 1018 B (ἐπόγδοος ὧν), 1028 a (μονονουχὶ). 

e In half a dozen passages it agrees with u alone against 
all the other mss. (see especially 1024 Ἑ on κρίσις : κίνησις -U, 
Aldine); and yet in 1019 F it preserves twenty-one words 
that are not inu(éy δὲ rots tpimAacios...), While in at Jeast 
two places it agrees with f, m, rin words that are not ine ΟΥ̓ τὶ 
(see 10148 on πρὸ τῆς τοῦ and 1099 c on TH ὑπάτῃ τόνου). 
In more than thirty other passages it disagrees with e and u, 


156 


GENERATION OF THE SOUL 


taken from C.C.C. 99, which in many passages lacks 
words that it preserves.4 


for which e.g. see the critical apparatus on 1023 © (λέγειν), 
1025 F (χωρὶς τούτων), 1018 a (τὰ μὲν yap), 1018 B (διὰ τοῦτο 
καὶ), 1022 a (ἀναλόγως ἤδη). and 1028 B (τὸν ἝἙ μοῦ). 

α To mention none of the other cases, words that the Aldine 
preserves and r omits in the following passages are also 
wanting in C.C.C. 99: 1017 a, 1017 B, 1020 p, 1022 B, 1025 c¢, 
1026 κ, 1028 pb. 


157 


1012 


Β 


ΠΕΡῚ ΤΗΣ 
EN ΤΙΜΑΙΩΙ ΨΥΧΟΓΌΝΙΑΣ 


Ὃ πατὴρ Αὐτοβούλῳ καὶ Πλουτάρχῳ εὖ 


πράττειν 


> \ \ / > / \ : / 

Ἐπεὶ τὰ πολλάκις εἰρημένα καὶ γέγραμμένα 
\ 

σποράδην ev ἑτέροις ἕτερα τὴν IlAatwvos ἐξηγου- 

[ “A - 
μένοις δόξαν ἣν εἶχεν ὑπὲρ ψυχῆς, ὡς ὑπενοοῦμεν 
ἡμεῖς, οἴεσθε δεῖν εἰς ἕν συναχθῆναι καὶ τυχεῖν 
40.) 5 3: \ , re > » ’ 
ἰδίας ἀναγραφῆς τὸν λόγον τοῦτον, οὔτ᾽ ἄλλως εὐ- 
μεταχείριστον ὄντα καὶ διὰ τὸ τοῖς πλείστοις τῶν 
ἀπὸ IlAatwvos ὑπεναντιοῦσθαι δεόμενον παραμυ- 
θίας, προεκθήσομαι τὴν λέξιν ὡς ἐν “Τιμαίῳ γέγρα- 
πται. “τῆς ἀμεροῦς" καὶ ἀεὶ κατὰ" ταὐτὰ ἐχούσης 
οὐσίας καὶ τῆς αὖ περὶ τὰ σώματα γιγνομένης 


1 ἐν τῷ Τιμαίῳ -E, B, e, u, Escor. 72. 
2 ἀμερίστου -Timaeus 35 4 1. 
3 καὶ ἀεὶ καὶ κατὰ -e, U, Escor. 72. 


α Concerning these two sons of Plutarch’s cf. K. Ziegler, 
R.-E. xxi/1 (1951), col. 649, 9-63. 

>» Timaeus 35 a 1-8 4. The passage is here translated in 
such a way as to make it compatible with the construction 
of it implied by Plutarch’s subsequent interpretation. The 
correct construction and interpretation of Plato’s text are 
given by G. M. A. Grube (Class. Phil., xxvii [1932], pp. 80- 
82) and by F. M. Cornford (Plato’s Cosmology, pp. 59-61), 
who might have cited in their own support not only Pro- 
clus, as they do (cf. especially In Platonis Timaeum ii, pp. 


158 


ON THE GENERATION OF 
THE SOUL IN THE TIMAEUS 


To Autobulus and Plutarch α from their Father 
nith his Wishes for ther Welfare 


1. Since you think that there ought to be a unified 
collection of the various statements that 1 have 
frequently made and have set down sporadically in 
various writings explaining what I supposed to be 
the opinion held by Plato concerning the soul and 
that a separate treatise ought to be devoted to this 
account, as it is both difficult to deal with otherwise 
and in need of vindication because of its opposition 
to most of the Platonists, I shall make my preface 
the passage as it is written in the Timaeus.° “ Of 
the indivisible ὁ and ever invariable being and of the 


155, 20-156, 24 and p. 162, 6-14 [Diehl]), but also the clear 
and concise paraphrases of the passage by Hermias (/n 
Platonis Phaedrum, p. 123, 4-12 [Couvreur]) and by Aristi- 
des Quintilianus (De Musica iii, 24 =p. 126, 1-7 [Winnington- 
Ingram]). Proclus (ibid., pp. 162, 25-163, 3) implies that 
Porphyry understood the passage in the same way. 

¢ Plato wrote ἀμερίστου here (Timaeus 35 a 1), and Plu- 
tarch usually employs that word in referring to this passage 
(1012 ©, 1014 p, 1022 © and Fr, 1025 πὶ and £ infra; cf. Plat. 
Quaest. 1001 p supra); but a few lines below (Timaeus 35 
A δ) Plato himself used ἀμεροῦς in the same sense (cf. The- 
aetetus 205 c 2 and p 1-2 with & 2), and in 1022 £ infra 
Plutarch remarks τὸ... μονοειδὲς ἀμερὲς εἴρηται Kai ἀμέριστον. 


150 


(101 


2) 


C 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


“A ’ > 5 “κ᾿ 9 , ,ὔ 
μεριστῆς τρίτον ἐξ ἀμφοῖν ἐν μέσῳ συνεκεράσατο" 
’ > “A ~ 4 a5. a 
οὐσίας εἶδος, τῆς τε ταὐτοῦ φύσεως αὖ πέρι καὶ τῆς 
δὴν 2 ‘ \ pe ae f 9 ! 
τοῦ ETEPOV’ και KATA ταῦτα" συνέστησεν EV μέσῳ 

A ? 3 A ἢ A a x \ 

τοῦ T ἀμεροῦς αὐτὴν καὶ τοῦ κατὰ τὰ σώματα 
~ \ 
μεριστοῦ. καὶ τρία λαβὼν αὐτὰ ὄντα συνεκερά- 
reer , , 107 \ , , , 
Gato εἰς μίαν πάντα ἰδέαν, τὴν θατέρου φύσιν δύσ- 
> γ 
μικτον οὖσαν εἰς ταὐτὸ" συναρμόττων βίᾳ μιγνὺς 
A ~ , ΐ ~ 
δὲ μετὰ τῆς οὐσίας. καὶ EK τριῶν ποιησάμενος ἕν 
πάλιν ὅλον τοῦτο μοίρας εἰς as’ προσῆκε διένειμεν 
ἑκάστην δὲ τούτων" ἔκ τε ταὐτοῦ καὶ θατέρου καὶ 

Cond / a 
τῆς οὐσίας μεμιγμένην: ἤρχετο δὲ διαιρεῖν ὧδε.᾽᾽ 

aA ~ , A 
ταῦτα πρῶτον ὅσας παρέσχηκε Tots ἐξηγουμένοις 

1 συνεκεκράσατο -U. 

2 τοῦ ἑτέρου -E, B (cf. 1012 εκ infra: τοῦ δὲ ταὐτοῦ Kai τοῦ 
ἑτέρου), J'tmaeus 35 a 4-5 (in A, P, W, Y but θατέρου 
in F); τοῦ θατέρου -e, u; θατέρου -f, m, r, Escor. 72. 
ταὐτὰ -r, Timaeus 35 a 5 (in F but ταῦτα in A, P, W, Y). 
αὐτῶν -m, τ, Tumaeus 35 a 6. 
συνεκεκράσατο -U. 
ταὐτὸν -limaeus 35 a 8. 


μοίρας ὅσας -limaeus 35 B 2. 
Omitted in Timaeus 35 B 3 by A, P, W, Y. 


ono oO ἢ. ὦ 





¢ Plato wrote κατὰ ταὐτὰ . .. αὐτῶν ; but instead of the 
former Plutarch probably read κατὰ ταῦτα, and instead of 
the latter he certainly read αὐτὴν and construed τοῦ τ᾽ 
ἀμεροῦς . +. καὶ Too... μεριστοῦ aS a genitive of material 
with συνέστησεν αὐτήν instead of as governed by ἐν μέσῳ. 
for in 1025 B and 1025 r—1026 a infra he says that between 
sameness and difference there was placed as a receptacle 
for them the mixture of the indivisible and the divisible. 
The change of αὐτῶν to αὐτὴν may have been occasioned 
by the same desire for an expressed object of συνέστησεν 
that led Hackforth (Class. Rev., N.S. vii [1957], p. 197), 
while adopting Cornford’s construction of the passage, to 


160 


GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1012 


divisible on the other hand that comes to pass in the 
case of bodies he blended together out of both a 
third kind of being in the middle, and in regard to 
the nature of sameness again and that of difference 
he also in this way compounded it ¢ in the middle of 
the indivisible and what is divisible among bodies. 
And he took them, three as they were, and blended 
them all together into a single entity,® forcibly fit- 
ting into sameness the nature of difference, which 
is refractory to mixture, and mixing them together 
with being. And, when out of three he had made 
one, he again distributed the whole of this into 
fractions ὦ that were appropriate and each of these a 
blend of sameness and difference and being ; and he 
began the division in the following way.” To recount 
at present all the dissensions that these words have 


propose κατὰ ταῦτα «ταὐτὸ» : but κατὰ ταὐτὰ συνέστησεν 
here needs a separately expressed object no more than does 
μιγνύς five lines below (T'imaeus 35 8 1) or περί τε ψυχῆς 
φύσεως διϊδὼν κατὰ ταὐτά in Phaedrus 277 B 8. 

ὃ For Plato’s use of ἰδέα in this sense cf. Theaetetus 18-4 
p 3, 203 £ 4, 204 a 1-2, 205 c 1-2, 205 » 53; Parmenides 
157 vp 7- 2; Politicus 308 c 6-7 (and with this cf. Timaeus 
28 a 8). 

¢ As Proclus saw (Jn Platonis Timaeum ii, p. 159, 5-14 
[Diehl]), Plato meant simply “ and mixing them (i.e. both 
of them) with being ” (cf. Τ᾽ παρ 37 a 2-43; and for this 
use of μετά cf. 83 B 5-6, 85 α 5, and Laws 961 p 9-10); but 
from 1025 B infra it appears that Plutarch took it to mean 
*“and mixing them (i.e. the two of them) together with the 
help of being,’ as do ‘Taylor (Commentary on Plato’s 
Timaeus, p. 109) and Thévenaz (L’ Ame du Monde, pp. 13, 
39, 42). 

¢@ The εἰς ds, which here replaces Plato’s ὅσας (cf. Lairs 
737 τὶ 3-4 and 756 B 8—-c 1), is in accordance with Plutarch’s 
own usage (cf. De Comm. Not. 1081 τῷ infra, De Defectu 
Orac. 422 πὶ, Quaest. Conviv. 719 τ). 


161 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1012) διαφορὰς ἄπλετον ἔ ἔργον ἐστὶ διελθεῖν ἐν τῷ παρ- 
ὄντι, πρὸς δὲ ὑ ὑμᾶς ἐντετυχηκότας' ὁμοῦ (ry? ταῖς 
πλείσταις καὶ περιττόν. ἐπεὶ δὲ τῶν δοκιμωτάτων 
ἀνδρῶν τοὺς μὲν Ξενοκράτης προσηγάγετο, τῆς 
ψυχῆς τὴν οὐσίαν ἀριθμὸν αὐτὸν ὑφ᾽ ἑαυτοῦ κινού- 

3 4 8 ¢€ \ 4 ~ ag 
μενον ἀποφηνάμενος," οἱ δὲ Κράντορι τῷ Σολεῖ 
προσέθεντο, μιγνύντι τὴν ψυχὴν ἔκ τε τῆς νοητῆς 
καὶ τῆς περὶ τὰ αἰσθητὰ δοξαστῆς φύσεως, οἶμαί τι 
τὴν τούτων ἀνακαλυφθέντων σαφήνειαν ὥσπερ ἐν- 
δόσιμον ἡμῖν" παρέξειν. 

2. "Ἔστι δὲ βραχὺς ὑπὲρ ἀμφοῖν o° λόγος. οἱ 
μὲν γὰρ οὐδὲν ἢ γένεσιν ἀριθμοῦ δηλοῦσθαι νομί- 

E ζουσι τῇ μίξει τῆς ἀμερίστου καὶ μεριστῆς οὐσίας: 
ἀμέριστον μὲν γὰρ εἶναι τὸ ἕν μεριστὸν δὲ τὸ πλῆς- 

1 ἐντυχόντας -f, m, 

2 «τῷ -added by Hato (De Plutarcho, p. 589, n. 1); 
ἐμοῦ ταῖς -τ : ὁμοῦ ταῖς -all other mss. 

ἀποφηναμένους -δοογ. 72. 
~ms; σωλεῖ -r; σολιεῖ -E, B, e, u, Escor. 72. 

δ ἢ Βιο: ἡμῖν sus δι πὴ»; Escor. 72. 

6 ὁ -omitted by e, u, Escor. 72. 

α Sextus according to the mss. of Adv. Math. i, 301 asserts 
that πάντες of Πλάτωνος ἐξηγηταί were silent about the 
passage; but cf. W. Theiler’s suggestion (Gnomon, xxviii 
[1956], p. 286). 

Ὁ Xenocrates, frag. 68 (Heinze [p. 187, 6-8]); cf. Plat. 
(uaest. 1007 c supra with note c there and Xenocrates, 
frags. 60-61 with Cherniss, Aristotle's Criticism of Plato 

ὁ oy Pi 968; ἢ. S21. 

° Crantor, frag. 3 (Kayser)=frag. 3 (Mullach, Frag. 
Philos. Graec. iii, p. 140). With the formulation, τῆς νοητῆς 
καὶ τῆς . . . δοξαστῆς φύσεως, cf. Plutarch, ddv. Colotem 
1114 ὁ: Albinus, Epitome ix, 4 (p. 55, 1-3 [Louis]=p. 164, 
1-3 [Hermann]) and Apuleius, De Platone i, 9 (p. 92, 10-15 
[Thomas]) referring to Tinaeus 51 Ὁ-Ὲ: Sextus, Adv. 
Math. vii, 141 referring to Timaeus 27 pv 6—28 a 4; and 


162 





GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1012 


occasioned their interpreters @ is in the first place an 
immense task and to do so to you superfluous as 
well, as you have read pretty nearly the most of 
them. Since, however, of the men most highly 
esteemed some were won over by Xenocrates, who 
declared the soul’s essence to be number itself being 
moved by itself, and others adhered to Crantor of 
Soli, who makes the soul a mixture of the intelligible 
nature and of the opinable nature of perceptible 
things,* I think that the clarification of these two 
when exposed will afford us something like a key- 
note.4 

2. The statement concerning both is concise.¢ 
The former believe 7 that nothing but the generation 
of number is signified by the mixture of the indi- 
visible and divisible being, the one being indivisible 


see Plato, Republic 534 a 6-7. Crantor, the pupil of Xeno- 
crates (Diogenes Laertius, iv, 24), is called by Proclus (Jn 
Platonis Timacum i, p. 76, 1-2 [Diehl]) 6 πρῶτος τοῦ Πλά- 
τῶνος seen τής. 

Cf. De Defectu Orac. 420 Ε and 421 Fr, Quaest. Conviv. 
ἐν E; Athenaeus, xiii, 556 ἃ. 

¢ The expression suggests that what follows was taken 
not directly from Xenocrates and Crantor but from a report 
of their interpretations. 

7 Xenocrates, frag. 68 (Heinze [p. 187, 11-23]). Cf. 
Cherniss, The Riddle, pp. 45-46 and p. 73 and Aristotle's 
Criticism of Plato ..., pp. 396-402 ; and Merlan, Platonism 
to Neoplatonism, pp. 34-35, who on pp. 45-48 argues that 
Xenocrates’ interpretation of Timaeus 35 a 1—B 4 is not “‘ so 
thoroughly mistaken ”’ although on p. 13 he had himself 
accepted as correct the interpretation given by Cornford 
(see note ὁ on 1012 8 supra), whereas it is by neglect of the 
latter and consequent misconstruction of Timaeus 35 a 1- 4 
that Xenocrates’ interpretation is vindicated by H. J. 
Kramer Nort ee p. 328; cf. his Arete, p. 314, 
lines 1-3). 


163 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


ἃ ~ 
(1012) Bos ἐκ δὲ τούτων γίγνεσθαι Tov ἀριθμὸν τοῦ ἑνὸς 
δ, 4 A \ A. bo / / ? 
ὁρίζοντος τὸ πλῆθος Kal TH ἀπειρίᾳ πέρας ἐντιθέν- 
1 ἃ \ δ "ἢ ἣν A 5} \ 7 7 ς 
TOS, ἣν καὶ δυάδα καλοῦσιν ἀόριστον (καὶ Zapatas ὁ 
, / / ~ 
Πυθαγόρου διδάσκαλος ταύτην μὲν ἐκάλει τοῦ apt- 
θμοῦ μητέρα τὸ δὲ ἕν πατέρα" διὸ καὶ βελτίονας 
εἶναι τῶν ἀριθμῶν ὅσοι τῇ μονάδι προσεοίκασι), 
τοῦτον δὲ μήπω ψυχὴν τὸν ἀριθμὸν" εἶναι: τὸ γὰρ 
κινητικὸν καὶ τὸ κινητὸν ἐνδεῖν αὐτῷ. τοῦ δὲ Tad- 
1 mss. (cf. 1014 bv infra [ἀπειρίαν .. ἐν αὑτῇ πέρας οὐδὲν 
. ἔχουσαν] and 1026 a infra with Quaest. Conviv. 719 τ 
[ἀπείρῳ πέρατος ἐγγενομένου] : lamblichus, Theolog. Arith., 
p. 9, 1 [de Falco]) ; ἐπιτιθέντος -Bernardakis. 


2 τὸν ἀριθμὸν -deleted as a gloss by Papabasileios (Athena, 
x [1898], p. 226). 








2 Of. De Defectu Orac. 429 4 (τότε yap ἀριθμὸς γίγνεται 
τῶν πληθῶν ἕκαστον ὑπὸ τοῦ ἑνὸς ὁριζόμενον). 

>’ Of. Proclus, In Platonis Timaeum ii, p. 153, 19-21 and 
23-25 (Diehl) = Numenius, Test. 31 (p. 97 [Leemans]) ; The- 
mistius, De Anima, p. 12, 13-27 (cf. Gnomon, xxxi [1959], 
pp. 42-43); and for number as the product of the one and 
the indefinite dyad see the references in note a on Plat. 
Quaest. 1002 a supra (where the terms used are μονάς and 
ἡ ἄπειρος δυάς). 

ς Plutarch mentions ‘* Zaratas ’’ only here and must have 
been unaware that this is just another form of “ Zoroaster ἡ 
(cf. Bidez-Cumont, Les Mages Hellénisés i, pp. 36-38), to 
whom he refers at 1026 8B infra and for whom he accepted 
the date of 5,000 years before the Trojan War (De Iside 
369 Ὁ-π : cf. Hermodorus in Diogenes Laertius, i, 2 and 
Hermippus in Pliny, Δ᾽. ἢ. xxx, 4). With the first part of 
Plutarch’s parenthesis here cf. Hippolytus in Refutatio vi, 
23, 2 (p. 149, 29-30 [Wendland]|: καὶ Ζαράτας 6 Πυθαγόρου 
διδάσκαλος ἐκάλει τὸ μὲν ἕν πατέρα τὸ δὲ δύο μητέρα), who 
for this cites no authority but who in Refutatio i, 2, 12 
(p. 7, 2-5 [Wendland]) as his source for a highly con- 
taminated account of the doctrine expounded to Pythagoras 
by Zaratas cites Aristoxenus (frag. 13 [Wehrli]; οὐ F. 
Jacoby, F. Gr. Hist. U1 a, pp. 295, 20-298, 14 [ad 273 Fr 94] 


164 


GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1012 


and multiplicity divisible and number being the 
product of these when the one bounds multiplicity 2 
and inserts a limit in infinitude, which they call 
indefinite dyad too ὃ (this Zaratas too, the teacher of 
Pythagoras, called mother of number ; and the one 
he called father,*¢ which is also why he held those 
numbers to be better that resemble the monad 4) ; 
but they believe that this number is not yet soul, 
for it lacks motivity and mobility,’ but that after the 


and W. Spoerri, Rev. Htudes Anciennes, lvii [1955], pp. 267- 
290 [especially pp. 272-273]) and an otherwise unknown 
Diodorus of Eretria. ‘The explanation of this latter name 
attempted by J. Bidez (Hos [Bruxelles, 1945], pp. 16-17) is 
implausible even on chronological grounds ; and it is more 
probable that behind this “ Diodorus ”’ lurks the name of 
Eudorus (cf. J. Roeper, Philologus, vii [1852], pp. 532-535), 
who is cited by Plutarch at 1013 5, 1019 £, and 1020 ς 
infra and who is therefore likely to have been his source 
not only for the parenthetical reference to Zaratas here but 
also for the summary in which it stands (see note e on 1012 Ὁ 
supra and Helmer, De An. Proc., p. 13, n. 18). 

4 3,6, the odd numbers (cf. Nicomachus, Arithmetica 
Introductio τι, xx, 2 [p. 118, 4-6, Hoche] ; Syrianus, Metaph., 
p- 181, 23-25), which are called male (cf. Plutarch, Quaest. 
Romanae 264 a and 288 c-p, De Εἰ 388 κ-8) and “ better ” 
(cf. Quaest. Romanae 264 a init.; Demetrius in Proclus, 
In Platonis Rem Publicam ii, p. 23, 13-22 [Kroll] ; Aristides 
Quintilianus, De Musica iii, 24 [p. 126, 24-27, Winnington- 
Ingram]). Plutarch himself speaks of their derivation from 
the monad as from “ the better principle ” (De Defectu Orac. 
429 5), and Xenocrates seems to have identified with odd- 
ness the monad which as male he gave the rank of father 
(Xenocrates, frag. 15 [Heinze] and Aristotle, Metaphysics 
1084 a 32-37 with 1083 b 28-30; of. A.J.P., Ixviii [1947], 
pp. 245-246 in note 86). 

¢ Cf. infra τοῦ κινεῖσθαι καὶ κινεῖν (“ὁ of being in motion 
and setting in motion ”’) and Aristotle’s objection, De Anima 
409 a 3 (et [ἢ] γάρ ἐστι κινητικὴ καὶ κινητή, διαφέρειν δεῖ) with 
De Generatione 326 Ὁ 3-5. 

165 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1012) τοῦ καὶ τοῦ ἑτέρου συμμιγέντων, ὧν τὸ μέν ἐστι 
κινήσεως ἀρχὴ καὶ μεταβολῆς τὸ δὲ μονῆς, ψυχὴν' 
γεγονέναι, μηδὲν ἧττον τοῦ ἱστάναι καὶ ἵστασθαι 

Ε δύναμιν ἢ τοῦ κινεῖσθαι καὶ κινεῖν οὖσαν. οἱ δὲ 
περὶ τὸν Kpavropa μάλιστα τῆς ψυχῆς ἴδιον ὑπο- 
λαμβάνοντες ἔργον εἶναι τὸ" κρίνειν τά τε νοητὰ καὶ 
τὰ αἰσθητὰ τάς τε τούτων ἐν αὑτοῖς καὶ πρὸς ἀλ- 
ληλα γιγνομένας διαφορὰς καὶ ὁμοιότητας ἐκ πάν- 
των paciv, ¢ ἵνα πάντα γιγνώσκῃ, συγκεκρᾶσθαι τὴν 

1018 foxy ταῦτα δ᾽ εἶναι τέσσαρα, τὴν νοητὴν φύσιν 
1 μονὴν (μόνην -f) ψυχῆς -f, τὰ, r, Escor. 72eorr. (ν and ς 


sipensariis over s and »), Aldine. 
τὸ -f, m, r; τοῦ -E, B, e, u, Escor. 72, Aldine. 











* For difference and sameness as the principles of motion 
and rest respectively cf. Aristotle, Physics 201 b 19-21 
(= Metaphysics 1066 a 11) and Metaphysics 1084 a 34-35 
with Cherniss, Aristotle’s Criticism of Plato . .., note 305 
on p. 385 and pp. 11-12, p. 122, p. 443. Aristotle argues 
that a self-mover must have an internal principle of motion | 
(cf. Cherniss, op. cit., ΡΡ. 389-390) and that soul must be 
στατική as well as κινητική (Topics 127 Ὁ 15-16 ; cf. De Anima | 

406 b 22-24 with 409 b 7-11); and Xenocrates mistakenly 
tried to make soul as self-motion satisfy both these require- 
ments (cf. Cherniss, op. cit., note 366 [especially pp. 4392- 
433]). In ‘‘ Timaeus Locrus ” 95 r—96 a the sameness and 
difference mixed with the blend of indivisible form and 
divisible being are called δύο δυνάμιας ἀρχὰς κινασίων without 
further specification. 

> Crantor, frag. 4 (Kayser)=frag. 4 (Mullach, Frag. 
Philos. Graec. iii, p. 140), with the whole of which ef. 
Albinus, Epitome xiv, 1-2 (p. 79, 3-14 [Louis]=p. 169, 16-26 
{Hermann]). Unlike Xenocrates Crantor did not read into 
the psychogony any principle of motion or any identification 
of soul with number (Taylor, Commentary on Plato’s 
Timaeus, p. 113); and P. Merlan in saying that “ Crantor 

‘ interpreted the ‘ tase irl of the Timaeus as said 
simply ‘ arithmogony ’ * (Armstrong, Later Greek . 


166 





GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1012-1013 


commingling of sameness and difference, the latter of 
which is the principle of motion and change while 
the former is that of rest,* then the product is soul, 
soul being a faculty of bringing to a stop and being 
at rest no less than of being in motion and setting in 
motion. Crantor and his followers, on the other 
hand,° supposing that the soul’s peculiar function is 
above all to form judgments of the intelligible and 
the perceptible objects* and the differences and 
similarities occurring among these objects both 
within their own kind and in relation of either kind 
to the other,? say that the soul, in order that it may 
know all, has been blended together out of all ὁ and 


Philosophy, pp. 17-18) erroneously ascribes to him the very 
interpretation that he in fact rejected. 

ο Cf. Albinus, loc. cit., p. 79, 3 (Louis)=p. 169, 16 (Her- 
mann) and Proclus, /n Platonis Timaeum i, p. 254, 29-31 
with ii, p. 135, 24-25 (Diehl). This use of κρίνειν is frequent 
in Aristotle (e.g. De Anima 427 a 17-21, 428 a 3-5, cf. 432 
a 15-16 and 404 Ὁ 25-27); for Plato cf. Republic 523 B 1-2 
(ὡς ἱκανῶς ὑπὸ τῆς αἰσθήσεως κρινόμενα). 

4 That is the difference and similarity (1) of intelligibles 
to one another or of perceptibles to one another and (2) of 
intelligible and perceptible to each other. Cf. Timaeus 
37 a ὅ-Β 3 and Proclus, In Platonis Timaeum ii, pp. 304, 
22-305, 4 (Diehl). 

¢ Because “ like is known by like ”’ (cf. Albinus, loc. cit.), 
the assumption underlying the psychogony according to 
Aristotle (De Anima 404 b 16-18) and later interpreters 
generally (cf. Sextus, ddv. Math. i, 303 [ο΄ vii, 92-93 and 
116-120]; Chalcidius, Platonis Timaeus, pp. 119, 14-120, 
11 [Wrobel]=p. 100, 8-22 [Waszink]; Proclus, In Platonis 
Timaeum ii, Ὁ. 135, 23-30 and p. 298, 2-31 [Diehl]); but 
see Cherniss, Aristotle's Criticism of Plato ..., pp. 408-411 
(with note 339 sub jinem on Crantor) and G. M. Stratton, 
Theophrastus and the Greek Physiological Psychology before 
Aristotle (London/New York, 1917), pp. 156-157 on De 
Sensibus 1 (Dox. Graeci, p. 499, 3). 


167 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


a Ἁ ψΠ Vy € , Μ \ ἃ ‘ 
(1013) GEL κατὰ ταῦτα καὶ ὡσαύτως ἐχούσαν καὶ THY περι 
τὰ σώματα παθητικὴν' καὶ μεταβλητὴν ἐ ἔτι δὲ τὴν 
ταὐτοῦ καὶ τοῦ ἑτέρου. διὰ τὸ κἀκείνων ἑκατέραν 
μετέχειν ἑτερότητος καὶ ταὐτότητος. 
ς and A / e ’ὔ » 
8. Opards δὲ πάντες οὗτοι χρόνῳ μὲν οἴονται 


τὴν ψυχὴν μὴ γεγονέναι μηδ᾽ εἶναι γενητὴν" πλεί- 


ονας δὲ δυνάμεις ἔχειν, εἰς ἃς ἀναλύοντα θεωρίας“ 
ἕνεκα τὴν οὐσίαν αὐτῆς λόγῳ τὸν Πλάτωνα γιγνο- 
μένην ὑποτίθεσθαι καὶ συγκεραννυμένην. τὰ δ᾽ αὐτὰ 


1 Mss. (cf. 1023 B infra [τῶν νοητῶν τὸ ἀΐδιον Kai τῶν αἱἰ- 
σθητῶν τὸ παθητικόν] and Dox. Graeci, p. 281 a 11 and B 9); 
παθητὴν ~-Bernardakis (cf. De EF 392 8 from Eusebius, Praep. 
Hivang. xi, 11, 4 [τῶν παθητῶν καὶ μεταβλητῶν)). 

2 γεννητὴν 4. m, Aldine. 3 θεωρίαν -rt. 


« Plato emphatically stated that the ingredients of the soul 
are three (Timaeus 35 A 6-7 and 37 a 2-4). 

> Called τῆς περὶ τὰ αἰσθητὰ δοξαοτῆς φύσεως in 1012 ἡ 
supra (see note ce there) and in 1013 8 infra simply τῆς 
αἰσθητῆς οὐσίας. With the expression used here (περὶ τὰ 
σώματα may have been taken directly from Timaeus 35 a 

2-3, but cf. τῷ περὶ τὰ σώματα πλανητῷ καὶ μεταβλητῷ in 
Quaest. Conviv. 718 >) cf. τῶν αἰσθητῶν τὸ παθητικόν in 1023 
B-C infra, (φύσεως) οὔσης ἐν πάθεσι παντοδαποῖς Kat μεταβολαῖς 
ἀτάκτοις in 1015 £ infra, τὴν δὲ σωματικὴν καὶ παθητικὴν 
(φύσιν) in De Defectu Orac. 428 B, and also ddr. Culotem 
1115 Ἑ (τῆς ὕλης... πάθη πολλὰ καὶ μεταβολὰς. . δεχομένης) 
and 1116p (aitras ais ἐν τῷ πάσχειν Kal werd tees τὸ εἶναι). 

¢ Cf. Albinus, loc. cit., Pp. 79, 10- 11 (Louis) =p. 169, 29-J4. 
(Hermann) : ἐνὸν ἐπὶ τῶν νοητῶν ταὐτότητά τε Kal ἑἕτερό- 
τητα καὶ ἐπὶ τῶν μεριστῶν. .. 

ὦ Xenocrates, frag. 68 (Heinze (p. 187, 23-27]) and 
Crantor, frag. 4 (Kayser [p. 19])=frag. 4 (Mullach, Frag. 
Philos. Graec. iii, p. 140). 

e Cf. 1017 8 infra (οὐ θεωρίας ἕνεκα) and οὐ τοῦ θεωρῆσαι 
ἕνεκεν (Aristotle, Metaphysics 1091 a 28-29; contrast 
Speusippus, frag. 46, 17-20 {Lang]), S Saancalin χάριν ὡς 
μᾶλλον γνωριζόντων (Aristotle, De Caelo 280 a 1, with Taurus 
in Philoponus, De Aeternitate Mundi, p. 187, 1 and p. 224, 


168 





GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1013 


that these are four, the intelligible nature, which is 
ever invariable and identical, and the passive and 
mutable nature of bodies” and furthermore that of 
sameness and of difference because each of the 
former two also partakes of diversity and identity.°¢ 
3. All these interpreters are alike in thinking ὦ 
that the soul did not come to be in time and is not 
subject to generation but that it has a multiplicity of 
faculties and that Plato in analysing its essence into 
these for the sake of examination’ represents it 
verbally as coming to bef and being blended to- 


1 [Rabe]; Alexander, ibid., p. 217, 23-24; Simplicius, 
De Caelo, p. 304, 4-6; [Alexander], Metaph., p. 819, 38 
and p. 820, δ), σαφηνείας χάριν (Theophrastus, Phys. Opin., 
frag. 11 [Dow. Graeci, pp. 485, 18-486, 2], with ‘Taurus in 
Philoponus, De Aeternitate Mundi, p. 187, 5 [Rabe] and 
Alexander, ibid., p. 216, 13), ἐπὶ τοῦ σαφοῦς χρείᾳ (Atticus 
in Eusebius, Praep. Evang. xv, 6, 4=ii, p. 360, 7 [Mras)}), 
and various combinations of these expressions in Plotinus 
(Enn., tv, ili, 9, lines 14-15), Proclus (dn Platonis Timaeum 
i, p. 290, 9-10 [Diehl]), and Philoponus (De Aeternitate 
Mundi, p. 186, 14-16 and p. 189, 10-13 [Rabe]). With 
εἰς ἃς ἀναλύοντα . . . τὴν οὐσίαν αὐτῆς cf. especially Proclus, 
In Platonis Timaeum ii, pp. 123, 27-124, 10 (Diehl) and 
Chalcidius, Platonis Timaeus, Ὁ. 97, 5-7 (Wrobel)=pp. 81, 
26-82, 1 (Waszink), on which cf. J. H. Waszink, Studien 
zum Timaioskommentar des Calcidius i (Leiden, 1964), p. 7, 
n. 3. Tor similar language used of the cosmogony ¢f. 
Taurus, Porphyry, and Alexander in Philoponus, De 
-leternitate Mundi, p. 146, 13-20, pp. 148, 9-23 with 153, 
23-154, 5, and pp. 217, 25-218, 10 (Rabe); Plotinus, ἴηι. 
tv, iii, 9, lines 15-20; and Simplicius, De Caelo, p. 304, 7-13. 

f Cf.*‘ Timaeus Locrus”’ 94c(cap. ii init. [7] ed. W. Marg): 
πρὶν ὦν wpavov λόγῳ γενέσθαι . . . with Proclus, In Platonis 
Denon ii, p. 101, 1-14 (Diehl); cf. also Plotinus, Hunn. 
vI, vii, 35, lines 28-29 (ὁ δὲ λόγος διδάσκων γινόμενα ποιεῖ) 
with ELnn. tv, iii, 9, lines 13-15 and viii, 4, lines 40-42 and 
in general Hnn. m1, v, 9, lines 24-29 (. . . καὶ of λόγοι Kal 
γενέσεις τῶν ἀγεννήτων ποιοῦσι . . .). 


169 


ep MORALIA 


(1013) καὶ περὶ τοῦ κόσμου διανοούμενον ἐπίστασθαι μὲν 
ἀίδιον ὅ ὄντα καὶ ἀγένητον' τὸ δὲ ᾧ τρόπῳ συντέ- 
Β τακται καὶ διοικεῖται καταμαθεῖν οὐ ῥᾷδιον ὁ ὁρῶντα 
aA 7 fo A A 
TOUS μήτε γένεσιν αὐτοῦ μήτε" τῶν γενητικῶν" σύν- 
οὗον ἐξ ἀρχῆς προῦποθεμένοις" ταύτην τὴν ὁδὸν 
τραπέσθαι. τοιούτων δὲ τῶν καθόλου λεγομένων, 
ὁ μὲν Εὔδωρος οὐδετέρους ἀμοιρεῖν οἴεται τοῦ εἰ- 
/ 5 3 A A ~ ~ / 3 ’ 
κότος": ἐμοὶ δὲ δοκοῦσι τῆς Πλάτωνος ἀμφότεροι 
1 ἀγέννητον -f, m, r, Aldine. 
2 μήτε -f, m,r; μηδὲ -E, B, e, u, Escor. 72, Aldine. 
3 γεννητικῶν -f, m, r, Aldine. 
4 προυποθεμένην -Ὑ. 5 εἰκότως -U. 


α Xenocrates, frag. 54 (Heinze [p. 180, 21-26]) and 
Crantor, frag. 4 (Kayser [p. 19])=frag. 4 (Mullach, Frag. 
Philos. Graec. iii, p. 140); cf. in Xenocrates, frag. 54 
(Heinze) and Speusippus, frag. 54 a-b (Lang) Aristotle, 
De Caelo 279 a 32—280 a 8 with Simplicius, De Caelo, 
pp. 303, 33-304, 15 (ef. [Alexander], Metaph., p. 819, 37-38) 
and Scholia in Aristotelem 489 a 4- 12 (Brandis). For 
Crantor’s further explanation of γενητόν as meaning not 
that the universe had a beginning but that it is dependent 
upon an extrinsic cause (frag. 2 [Kayser= Mullach, Frag. 
Philos. Graec. iii, p. 139]=Proclus, In Platonis Timaeum 

i, p. 277, 8-10 [Diehl]) cf. later Albinus, Epitome xiv, 3 
(p. 81, 1-4 [Louis]=p. 169, 26-30 [Hermann]) with Proclus, 
In Platonis Timaeum i, p. 219, 2-11 (Diehl); Taurus in 
Philoponus, De Aeternitate Mundi, p. 147, 5-9 (Rabe) ; 
Plotinus, Hn. 11, ix, 3, lines 12-14 and En. 111, ii, 1, lines 
922-96 and vii, 6, lines 52-54; Chalcidius, Platonis Timaeus, 
p. 89, 20-21 (Wrobel)=p. 74, 18-19 (Waszink) ; Simplicius, 
Phys., p. 1154, 9-113; and Proclus, In Platonis Timaeum i, 
p. 277, 10-17 (Diehl). 

᾿ CH. Taurus in Philoponus, De Aeternitate Mundi, p. 187, 
15-16 (Rabe) with Alexander, ibid., p. 216, 13-15; Chal- 
cidius, Platonis Timaeus, pp. 91, 29-92, 3 (Wrobel) =p. hs 
8-13 (Waszink) ; Simplicius, De Caelo, p. 304, 6-10. 

¢ That is neither Xenocrates in his arithmological explica- 
tion of the psychogony nor Crantor in his epistemological 
explication of it, the two explications that Plutarch proceeds 


170 





GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1013 


gether ; and they think? that with the same thing 
in mind concerning the universe too, while he knows 
it to be everlasting and ungenerated, yet seeing the 
way of its organization and management not to be 
easy for those to discern who have not presupposed 
its generation and a conjunction of the generative 
factors at the beginning,’ this course is the one that 
he took. Such being on the whole what they say, 
Eudorus thinks that neither party is without all 
title to likelihood ὁ ; but to me they both seem to 


to say are both wrong. The passage has been misinterpreted 
to mean that Eudorus reconciled the interpretation of the 
cosmogony by Xenocrates with the “ literal’ interpreta- 
tion of it by Crantor (H. Dérrie, Hermes, Ixxix [1944], 
pp. 27-28 in his article on Eudorus, ibid., pp. 25-39), 
although Plutarch has just asserted that Crantor and 
Xenocrates and all their followers alike rejected the “‘ literal ”’ 
interpretation of both the psychogony and the cosmogony. 
He has also ascribed to all of them alike the same explana- 
tion of both, θεωρίας ἕνεκα, and has not mentioned Crantor‘s 
additional interpretation of γενητόν (see note a on ἢ. 170 
supra); and so C. Moreschini must be mistaken in suppos- 
ing him to refer to these as the two different explications to 
both of which Eudorus gave some title to likelihood (Annali 
della Scuola Norm. Sup. di Pisa {Lettere .. .], 2 Ser. xxxiii 
[1964], pp. 31-32). For Plutarch’s use of Eudorus in this 
essay see note c on 1012 © supra; and for Eudorus himself 
besides Dorrie’s article cf. E. Martini, R.-H. vi (1909), cols. 
915, 41-916, 66 and G. Luck, Der Akademiker Antiochos 
(Bern/Stuttgart, 1953), pp. 27-28. Pap. Oxyrh. 1609 (xiii, 
pp. 94-96; cf. Diels-Kranz, Frag. Vorsok.® i, Ὁ. 352, 1-6), 
in which the author refers to his own commentary on the 
Timaeus, has for this reason been ascribed to Eudorus, who 
has recently been proposed as the source of an ever-increasing 
number of later texts (cf. P. Boyancé, Rev. Etudes Grecques, 
Ixxili [1959], pp. 378-380 and Ixxvi [1963], pp. 85-89, 95, 
and 98; M. Giusta, I Dossografi di Etica i [Torino, 1964}, 
pp. 151 ff.; W. Theiler, Parusia : Festgabe fiir Johannes 
Hirschberger [Frankfurt am Main, 1965], pp. 204 ff.). 


171 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1013) διαμαρτάνειν δόξης, εἰ κανόνι τῷ πιθανῷ xpy- 
στέον οὐκ ἴδια δόγματα περαίνοντας ἀλλ᾽ ἐκείνῳ τι 
βουλομένους λέγειν ὁμολογούμενον. ἡ μὲν Cyapy® 
ἐκ τῆς νοητῆς" καὶ τῆς αἰσθητῆς" οὐσίας λεγομένη 

Ἅ ~ 
μίξις" οὐ διασαφεῖται πῇ ποτε ψυχῆς μᾶλλον 7) τῶν 
ἄλλων, ὅ τι ἄν τις εἴπῃ," γένεσίς ἐστιν. αὐτός τε 

C γὰρ ὁ κόσμος οὗτος καὶ τῶν μερῶν ἕκαστον συν- 

ἕστηκεν ἔκ τε σωματικῆς οὐσίας καὶ νοητῆς, ὧν ἡ 
μὲν ὕλην καὶ ὑποκείμενον 7 δὲ" μορφὴν καὶ εἶδος 
τῷ γενομένῳ" παρέσχε᾽ καὶ τῆς μὲν ὕλης τὸ per 
οχῇ Kal εἰκασίᾳ τοῦ" νοητοῦ μορφωθὲν εὐθὺς ἁπτὸν 

1 τῷ -omitted by f, m, r, ul. : 

‘ «γὰρ > added by Maurommates (“‘ nam” -Turnebus : 
“can * ᾿ Αἰ ή ot 

ὃ Marcianus 187°! ; γρῃτικῆς -all other mss. 


4 Marcianus 187 ; αἰσθητικῆς -all other mss. 

5 μίξης -u. 8 εἴποι -B, r. 

7 f, m, r, Escor. 72°F: ; οὕτως -all other Mss. 

8 of δὲ -Β. 9 τῶν γενομένων -F. 10 +06 -omitted by u. 


@ See 1014 a infra (πιστούμενος τῷ εἰκότι) : and σ΄. De 
Defectu Orac. 430 B (. . . πρὸς τὴν ἐκείνου διάνοιαν ἐπάγειν τὸ 
εἰκός . καὶ, μάδδῇ,: ἘΠ: 728 τὶ (. .. τοῦ δὲ πιθανοῦ καὶ 
εἰκότος. - +) with 700 B and contrast " 19 F (. . δόξας ws 
ἰθαγενεῖς καὶ ἰδίας. . ἐπήνεσα καὶ τὸ εἰκὸς ἔφην ἔχειν ΕΣ ΜΟῚ 
ὃ For τῆς αἰσθητῆς οὐσίας. an abbreviation of the formula- 
tions given in 1012 Ὁ and 1013 a supra (see note ὁ there), 
cf. Proclus, In Platonis Timaeum ii, p. 154, 1-3 (Diehl) with 
Plotinus, Enn. rv, viii, 7 and Simplicius, De Anima, p. 28, 1-2. | 
¢ Crantor may not have meant to make the μεριστὴ οὐσία 
of Timaeus 35 a 2-3 a constituent part of the soul and 
probably did not identify it with corporeal being or matter 
(cf. Helmer, De An. Proc., p. 11; Thévenaz, L’ Ame du 
Monde, p. 61); but the present refutation assumes that he 
did, and the assumption may have been the easier for 
Plutarch to make because such an interpretation had 
already been adopted by others: it is attributed to Eratos- 
thenes by Proclus (Jn Platonis Timaeum ii, Ὁ. 152, 24-27 ; 


172 








GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1013 


be utterly mistaken about Plato’s opinion if as a 
standard plausibility is to be used, not in promotion 
of one’s own doctrines but with the desire to say 
something that agrees with Plato. (For), as to what 
the one party calls the mixture of the intelligible 
and the perceptible being,® it is not made clear how 
in the world this is generation of soul rather than of 
anything else one may mention, for this universe 
itself and each of its parts consist of corporeal and 
intelligible being, of which the former provided 
matter or substrate and the latter shape or form for 
what has come to be,’ and any matter that by 
participating in the intelligible and simulating it has 
got shape is straightway tangible <and) visible,¢ 


cf. F. Solmsen, 7.A4.P.A., xxiii [1942], pp. 198 and 202) 
and is recorded by Chalcidius (Platonis Timaeus, p. 94, 4-10 
{ Wrobel] =p. 79, 9-14 [Waszink]), whose ultimate source for 
it is probably pre-Plutarchean (cf. “ Timaeus Locrus ”’ 
94 a-B). Later (1023 a infra), when against those who 
interpret the psychogony as a commingling of corporeal 
matter with indivisible being the present refutation of 
Crantor is repeated, it is preceded by the argument that 
Plato in that passage uses none of the expressions by which 
he was accustomed to designate corporeal matter. In fact, 
like Aristotle (Physics 209 b 11-13) Plutarch identified with 
ὕλη the χώρα or receptacle of the Timaeus (1024 c infra; 
ef. 1015 p infra and Quaest. Conviv. 636 Ὁ), confusing this 
further with “ precosmic ”’ corporeal chaos (cf. 1014 B-c and 
1016 p—1017 a infra; Jones, Platonism of Plutarch, p. 81, 
n. 34; Thévenaz, L’Ame du Monde, pp. 110-113); and, 
though he apparently knew that Plato had not used ὕλη in 
this sense (De Defectu Orac. 414 τ; cf. Chalcidius, Platonis 
Timaeus, pp. 304, 4-7 and 336, 8-12 [Wrobel]=pp. 277, 18- 
278, 2 and 309, 3-6 [Waszink]), he even went so far as to 
insert the term into quasi-quotations of the Timaeus (cf. 
1016 v infra and De Defectu Orac. 430 c-p). 

4 Cf. Plat. Quaest. 1001 Ὁ-Ὲ supra; and for ἁπτὸν «καὶ» 
ὁρατόν cf. Plato, Timaeus 28 5 7-8, 31 B 4, and 32 B 7-8. 


173 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1013) (καὶ) ὁρατόν ἐστιν, ἡ ψυχὴ δὲ πᾶσαν αἴσθησιν 
ἐκπέφευγεν. ἀριθμόν γε μὴν ὁ Πλάτων οὐδέποτε 
τὴν ψυχὴν προσεῖπεν ἀλλὰ κίνησιν αὐτοκίνητον ἀεὶ 
καὶ κινήσεως πηγὴν καὶ ἀρχήν' ἀριθμῷ δὲ καὶ 
λόγῳ καὶ ἁρμονίᾳ διακεκόσμηκε τὴν οὐσίαν᾽" αὐτῆς 
ὑποκειμένην καὶ δεχομένην τὸ κάλλιστον εἶδος ὑπὸ 
τούτων ἐγγιγνόμενον. οἶμαι δὲ μὴ ταὐτὸν εἶναι τῷ 

D κατ᾽ ἀριθμὸν συνεστάναι τὴν. ψυχὴν τὸ τὴν οὐσίαν 
αὐτῆς ἀριθμὸν ὑπάρχειν, ἐπεὶ (καὶ καθ᾽ ἁρμο- 
νίαν συνέστηκεν ἁρμονία δ᾽ οὐκ ἔστιν, ὡς αὐτὸς ἐν 
τῷ περὶ Ψυχῆς ἀπέδειξεν. ἐκφανῶς δὲ τούτοις 
ἠγνόηται τὸ περὶ τοῦ ταὐτοῦ καὶ τοῦ ἑτέρου: λέ- 
γουσι γὰρ ὡς τὸ μὲν στάσεως τὸ δὲ κινήσεως συμ- 
βάλλεται δύναμιν εἰς τὴν τῆς ψυχῆς γένεσιν, αὐτοῦ 
Πλάτωνος ἐν τῷ Σοφιστῇ τὸ ὃν καὶ τὸ ταὐτὸν καὶ 
τὸ ἕτερον πρὸς δὲ τούτοις στάσιν καὶ κίνησιν ὡς 


1 «καὶ -added by Xylander, implied by versions of 
Turnebus and Amyot. 
2 διακόσμηκεν οὐσίαν -Ὑ. 3 «καὶ» -added by Hubert. 


9 Plato, Laws 898 Ε 1-2 (see Plat. Quaest. 1002 c supra 
with note g there) and Timaeus 36 © 5-6 and 46 p 6-7; cf. 
Albinus, Epitome xiii, 1 (p. 73, 4-7 [Louis]=p. 168, 6-9 
{Hermann)). 

> Phaedrus 245 c 9 (πηγὴ καὶ ἀρχὴ κινήσεως). The pre- 
ceding κίνησιν αὐτοκίνητον ἀεί is not a quotation but a 
formulaic summary of Phaedrus 245 c 7-8 and 245 τ 2-4 
influenced by the phraseology of Laws 894 B 9—c 1, 895 B 1-6, 
and 895 © 10—896 a 5 (cf. infra 1014 D [αὐτοκίνητον. δὲ καὶ 
κινητικὴν ἀρχήν], 1016 a [τῷ δ᾽ αὐτοκινήτῳ πιστουμένη τὸ 
ἀγένητον αὐτῆς, 1017 a [δύναμιν αὐτοκίνητον καὶ ἀεικίνητον], 
1023 c [ἡ μὲν γὰρ ἀεικίνητος), and it does not indicate that 
Plutarch knew αὐτοκίνητον as a variant of ή ἀεικίνητον in 
Phaedrus 245 c 5 (cf. Lustrum, iv [1959], Ῥ. 137, + 692 and 
+ 693). Others also, who certainly read ἀεικίνητον there, say 
that in this passage of the Phaedrus soul is defined as τὸ 
αὐτοκίνητον (6.5. Hermias, In Platonis Phaedrum, Ὁ. 108, 


174 








GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1013 


whereas soul is beyond the range of all sense-per- 
ception.? Then as for number, that Plato never 
called the soul; but he called it motion perpetually 
self-moved and motion’s source and principle.’ By 
means of number and ratio and concord he did 
arrange its substance © underlying and receiving the 
fairest form, which by their agency arises in it ; but 
it is not the same, I think, to say that the soul is put 
together on a numerical pattern and to say that its 
essence is number, since <in fact) it is put together 
on the pattern of a concord but is not a concord, as 
he himself proved in the work on the Soul.? It is 
manifest too that these interpreters ¢ have failed to 
understand the part about sameness and difference, 
for they say that to the generation of the soul the 
former contributes the faculty of rest and the latter 
that of motion,’ whereas by Plato himself in the 
Sophist 9 existence and sameness and difference and 
besides these rest and motion are distinguished and 
6-17 and p. 118, 14-16 [Couvreur]; Philoponus, De A eterni- 
tate Mundi, p. 271, 18-23 and pp. 246, 27-247, 2 [Rabe]) ; 
ef. Fernanda Decleva Caizzi, Acme, xxiii (1970), pp. 91-97. 

¢ See 1023 pv infra (. . . τὴν οὐσίαν . .. τῆς ψυχῆς .. . 
ταττομένην ὑπ᾽ ἀριθμοῦ). That is the procedure of Timaeus 
35 B 4—36 ἡ 7, after which the soul is described as λογισμοῦ 
μετέχουσα καὶ ἁρμονίας. .. Kal ava ed ed μερισθεῖσα καὶ 
συνδεθεῖσα (36 πὶ 6—37 a 4). With Plutarch’s expression here 
cf. infra 1015 E(. . . ἁρμονίᾳ καὶ ἀναλογίᾳ καὶ ἀριθμῷ χρώμενος 
ὀργάνοις), 1017 B (διαρμοσάμενος τοῖς προσήκουσιν ἀριθμοῖς καὶ 
λόγοις), 1027 a, 1029 Ὁ-Ὲ, and 1080 c. 

4 Phaedo 92 a 6—95 a 3. For ἁρμονία, translated as 
‘* concord,”’ see note-a on Plat. Quaest. II, 1001 c supra. 

¢ XNenocrates and his followers. 

7 See 1012 © supra with note a on page 166. 

9 Sophist 254 p 4—259 B 7 (especially 255 5 ὅ--Ὲ 2 and 


256 c 5—p 4), to which Plutarch refers in De FE 391 8 and 
De Defectu Orac. 428 c also. 


175 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


¢ ς ’; r t / 4 ‘ 
(1013) ἕκαστον ἑκάστου διαφέρον καὶ πέντε ὄντα χωρὶς 
/ \ / 
ἀλλήλων τιθεμένου Kat διορίζοντος. 

τ 1 Ἁ e f an \ [4 aA - 
4, “Ot γε μὴν οὗτοί τε κοινῇ καὶ ot πλεῖστοι τῶν 

,ὔ / , ἷ \ , 
E χρωμένων [Ϊλάτωνι φοβούμενοι καὶ παραλυπού- 
μενοι πάντα μηχανῶνται καὶ παραβιάζονται καὶ 
στρέφουσιν, ὥς τι δεινὸν καὶ ἄρρητον οἰόμενοι δεῖν 
περικαλύπτειν καὶ ἀρνεῖσθαι, τήν τε τοῦ κόσμου 
τήν τε τῆς ψυχῆς αὐτοῦ γένεσιν καὶ σύστασιν, οὐκ 
ἐξ ἀιδίου συνεστώτων" οὐδὲ τὸν ἄπειρον. χρόνον 
οὕτως ἐχόντων, ἰδίᾳ τε “λόγου τέτευχε καὶ νῦν ἀρκέ- 


“ἜΝ 


σει ῥηθὲν ὅτι τὸν περὶ θεῶν ἀγῶνα καὶ λόγον, ᾧ 


t 


Πλάτων ὁμολογεῖ φιλοτιμότατα Kat παρὰ ἡλικίαν 
πρὸς τοὺς ἀθέους κεχρῆσθαι, συγχέουσι μᾶλλον δὲ 
ὅλως ἀναιροῦσιν εἰ γὰρ ἀγένητος" ὁ κόσμος 


1 3 


οὗ -Υ΄. 2 παραμυθούμενοι -Turnebus. συνεστότων -T. 
4 φιλοτιμώτατα -Ὑ. 5 avepotow -α. 6. ἀγέννητος -f, m, ΤΥ. 
4 According to Proclus (dn Platonis Timaeum i, pp. 276, 
31-277, 1 [Diehl]) Plutarch, Atticus, and “ many other 
Platonists *? took the cosmogony of the Timaeus literally ; 
_ but Plutarch is the earliest of these named either by him 
(cf. op. cit., i, pp. 381, 26-382, 12 and for the psychogony 
ii, pp. 153, 25-154, 1 [Diehl]) or by Philoponus (De Aeter- 
nitate Mundi, p. 211, 10-20 and p. 519, 22-25 [Rabe]), and 
his ‘‘ many others’’ are probably later Platonists like 
Harpocration (Scholia Cod. Vat. f. 347 in Proclus, Jn 
Platonis Rem Publicam ii, p. 377, 15-23 [Kroll]), who was 
a pupil of Atticus (cf. Proclus, /n Platonis Timaeum i, Ὁ. 305, 
6-7 [Diehl]), the anonymous source of Diogenes Laertius, 
iii, 71-72 and 77 (cf. C. Andresen, Logos und Nomos | Berlin, 
1955], p. 283), and possibly even Severus with his “* cyclical ” 
interpretation (Proclus, In Platonis Timaeum i, Ὁ. 289, 7-13 
and ii, pp. 95, 29-96, I; cf. iii, p. 212, 7-9 [Diehl]) and the 
‘‘ eclectic’? Galen (Compendium Timaei Platonis, Ὁ. 39, 
11-13 [Kraus-Walzer]). Before Plutarch, however, the 
literal interpretation of the Timaeus, on which Aristotle had 
insisted (De Caelo 280 a 28-32 and 300 b 16-18, Physics 


176 











GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1018 


set apart from one another as being five things 
different each from each. 

4. In any case, what frightens and embarrasses 
these men in common with most of those who study 
Plato® so that they manipulate and force and twist 
everything in the belief that they must conceal and 
deny it as something dreadful and unspeakable is the 
generation and composition ὃ of the universe and of 
its soul which have not been compounded from ever- 
lasting or in their present state for infinite time. To 
this a treatise by itself has been devoted ὁ ; and now 
it will suffice to state that these people confuse or 
rather utterly ruin the reasoning of Plato’s case for 
the gods,4 which he admits he made against the 
atheists with a zeal extreme and unsuited to his 
years. For, if the universe is ungenerated, there is 
251 b 17-19, Metaphysics 1071 b 37—1072 a 3) but about 
which Theophrastus was uncertain (Phys. Opin., frag. 11 
[Dox. Graeci, pp. 485, 17-486, 2]), seems to have been 
adopted not only by the Peripatetics generally (cf. Philo- 
ponus, De Aeternitate Mundi, p. 135, 9-14 and his quota- 
tions from Alexander, ibid., pp. 213, 17-222, 17 [Rabe}) 
and the Epicureans (cf. Cicero, De Nat. Deorum i, 18-21 
[Usener, E'picurea, pp. 245-246]) but also by Cicero (Timaeus 
5, p. 159, 2-3 [Plasberg]; cf. Tusc. Disp. i, 63 and 70 and 
Acad. Prior. ii, 118) and by Philo Judaeus (De Aeternitate 
Mundi 13-16=vi, pp. 76, 16-77, 20 [Cohn-Reiter]), who 
like Philoponus later appeals to Aristotle as the decisive 
authority for this interpretation. 

Ὁ For σύστασιν here cf. Plato, Timaeus 32 c 5-6 and 36 
Ὁ 8-9. 

¢ Presumably the lost work, No. 66 in the Catalogue of 
Lamprias, Wepi τοῦ γεγονέναι κατὰ Πλάτωνα τὸν κόσμον (Vii, p. 
474 and frag. xxviii on p. 140 [Bernardakis]). 

4 Laws 891 © 4—899 ἢ 4. 

¢ A somewhat inexact reminiscence of Laws 907 5 10-Ὁ 5, 
on which see E. B. England, The Laws of Plato (Man- 
chester, 1921), ii, p. 503. 


177 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1013) ἐ ἐστίν, οἴχεται τῷ Πλάτωνι τὸ πρεσβυτέραν' τοῦ 
F σώματος τὴν ψυχὴν οὖσαν ἐξάρχειν μεταβολῆς καὶ 
κινήσεως πάσης, ἡγεμόνα καὶ πρωτουργόν, ὡς 
αὐτὸς cloner, ἐγκαθεστῶσαν. τίς δ᾽ οὖσα καὶ 
τίνος ὄντος ἡ ψυχὴ τοῦ σώματος προτέρα καὶ πρε- 
σβυτέρα λέγεται γεγονέναι, προϊὼν ὁ λόγος ἐνδεί- 
ξεται: τοῦτο γὰρ ἠγνοημένον ἔοικε τὴν πλείστην 
ge καὶ ἀπιστίαν “παρέχειν τῆς ἀληθοῦς δόξης. 
1014 Πρῶτον οὖν ἣν ἔχω περὶ τούτων" διάνοιαν ἐκ- 
ΤΟΣ πιστούμενος τῷ εἰκότι καὶ παραμυθού- 
μενος, ὡς ἔνεστι, τὸ ἄηθες" τοῦ λόγου καὶ παρά- 
dofov- ἔπειτα ταῖς" λέξεσιν ἐπάξω συνοικειῶν ἅμα 

τὴν ἐξήγησιν καὶ τὴν ἀπόδειξιν. ἔχει γὰρ οὕτως 
κατά γε τὴν ἐμὴν τὰ πράγματα δόξαν. “Ὧ κόσμον 
rovoe’’ φησὶν ᾿Ηράκλειτος “(οὔτε τις θεῶν ot?’ 


1 Hubert (cf. 1013 F infra and 1002 F supra; Timaeus 
34 c 4-5; Laws 892 c 6 and 896 c 6); πρεσβύτερον -Μ85. 
(of E'pinomis 980 Ὁ 6 and Ε 8). 
t τούτων -omitted by Εἰ, B. 
: Wet tenbach (after the versions of Turnebus and Amyot); 
᾿ ἀληθὲς -Mss. 4 ἔπειτ᾽ αὐταῖς -Bernardakis. 


ἅ Laws 896 A 5-c 8 (n.b. 896 B 1: μεταβολῆς τε Kai 
κινήσεως ἁπάσης αἰτία ἅπασιν) With 892 a 2—C 6 (cf. in [Plato], 
Epinomis 980 ἢ 6-- 8 the reference to “‘ the main point ’’) ; 
and see Plat. Quaest. 1002 E-F supra with page 48, note a. 

> Cf. infra 1016 sh μΝΝΝ ἡγεμόνα τοῦ παντὸς ἐγκατέστησαν) 
and 1017 B(... cen πυ ΜᾺ ἡγεμόνα τοῦ κόσμου . . .). in 
both places used of the created soul, 1.6. the soul after it had 
been made rational by god. The title is not quoted from 
Plato, but cf. Timaeus 41 c 7 (θεῖον λεγόμενον “ἡγεμονοῦν τε) 
with Phaedo 80 a 3-9 and 94 c 10-Ὁ 2 and ὡς δεσπότιν in 
Timaeus 34 c 5 (quoted in 1016 8 infra). 

¢ This is not an exact quotation either but a reminiscence 
of Laws 897 a 4, where the soul’s motions are called zpw- 
TOUPYOL κινήσεις. 


178 





GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1013-1014 


an end of Plato’s contention that the soul, being 
senior to the body, initiates all change and motion 4 
installed in her position of chief ® and, as he has said 
himself, of primary agent. What is meant by soul 
and what by body when she is said to have been 
prior and senior to it,@ this will be made plain by our 
account as it proceeds, for it is the failure to under- 
stand this that seems to occasion most of the per- 
plexity and incredulity about the true doctrine. 

5. First, therefore, I shall set down what I think 
about these matters, confirming and vindicating as 
far as may be by probability ὁ what is unusual and 
paradoxical about my account £ ; and then I shall ap- 
ply the interpretation and the demonstration to the 
texts, at the same time bringing them into accord 
with one another.’ For in my opinion this is the 
way matters stand. “ This universe was not made 
by anyone either god or man,’ says Heraclitus ἢ 

¢ Cf. Timaeus 84 ¢ 4-5 (... καὶ γενέσει καὶ ἀρετῇ προτέραν 
Kal πρεσβυτέραν ψυχὴν σώματος .. . συνεστήσατο). 

6 See 1013 Β swpra and page 172, note a. 

f See 1012 B supra (διὰ τὸ τοῖς πλείστοις . . . ὑπεναντιοῦσθαι 
δεόμενον παραμυθίας), and cf. Atticus, frag. vi ἐπέ. (Baudry) 
= Eusebius, Praep. Hvang. xv, 6, 3 (ii, pp. 359, 18-360, 4 
{Mras}). 

9 The object of συνοικειῶν is the texts, ras λέξεις “* under- 
stood ” from ταῖς λέξεσιν (cf. Kiithner-Gerth, ii, pp. 575-576), 
and not, as Thévenaz has it, the interpretation and the demon- 
stration; the reconciliation of apparently incompatible 
passages (1016 a and & infra) is itself taken to be an ἀπόδειξις 
of Plutarch’s interpretation (1015 F infra [chap. 8 init.]), a 
point overlooked by C. Theander in his treatment of this pas- 
sage (Plutarch und die Geschichte [Lund, 1951], pp. 42-43). 

» Heraclitus, frag. B 30 (D.-K. and Walzer)=frag. 20 
(Bywater), quoted more fully by Clement of Alexandria, 
Stromata v, xiv, 104, 2; ef. M. Marcovich, R&.-H. Supple- 
ment x (1965), cols. 261, 23-37 and 293, 51-66. 


179 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1014) ἀνθρώπων ἐποίησεν," ὥσπερ' φοβηθεὶς μὴ θεοῦ" 
ἀπογνόντες ἄνθρωπόν τινα γεγονέναι τοῦ κόσμου 
\ 
δημιουργὸν ὑπονοήσωμεν. βέλτιον οὖν Πλάτωνι 
πειθομένους τὸν μὲν κόσμον ὑπὸ θεοῦ γεγονέναι 
λέγειν καὶ ἄδειν “ὃ μὲν γὰρ κάλλιστος τῶν γεγο- 
Β νότων ὁ δ᾽ ἄριστος τῶν aitiwy’’* τὴν δ᾽ οὐσίαν καὶ 
ὕλην, ἐξ ἧς γέγονεν, οὐ γενομένην ἀλλὰ ὕποκει- 
μένην ἀεὶ τῷ δημιουργῷ εἰς διάθεσιν καὶ τάξιν 
αὑτὴν" καὶ πρὸς αὐτὸν ἐξομοίωσιν ὡς δυνατὸν ἣν 
ἐμπαρασχεῖν." οὐ γὰρ ἐκ τοῦ μὴ ὄντος ἡ γένεσις 
ἀλλ᾽’ ἐκ τοῦ μὴ καλῶς μηδὲ ἱκανῶς ἔχοντος, ὡς 
οἰκίας καὶ ἱματίου καὶ ἀνδριάντος. ἀκοσμία γὰρ 
ἦν τὰ πρὸ τῆς τοῦ κόσμου γενέσεως, ἀκοσμία δ᾽ 
9 3 7 9.9 3. ὡνῇ 509 » 3 > 
οὐκ ἀσώματος οὐδ᾽ ἀκίνητος οὐδ᾽ ἄψυχος ἀλλ 
1 ὡς =I. 
2 θεὸν -Benseler (De Hiatu, Ὁ. 528). 
3 ὑπονοήσομεν -U. 
4 Dibner (from Timaeus 29 4 6) ; αἰτιῶν -MSS. 
5 Wyttenbach (after Xylander’s version) ; αὐτῆς -Mss. 
of, ΤῸ παρασχεῖν -f, m, r, Escor. 72. 
7 τοῦ -omitted by e, u, Escor. 72. 

@ Timaeus 29 a 5-6; cf. Plutarch, Quaest. Conviv. 720 B 

(ὁ δὲ θεὸς τῶν αἰτίων ἀριστον). 

» The identification, οὐσία καὶ ὕλη, is Stoic according to 
Plutarch himself (see De Comm. Not. 1085 r-r infra with 
note a on F, and cf. De Amicorum Multitudine 97 a-s) ; 
but he so far adopts this terminology as even to use οὐσία 
alone for what he considers to be Platonic ὕλη (e.g. De 
Defectu Orae. 430 £ [οὐ yap ὁ θεὸς διέστησεν . . . τὴν οὐσίαν 
ἀλλὰ . .. αὐτὴν .. . ἔταξε)), for which cf. Diogenes Laertius, 
iii, 70 (p. 149, 16-17 [Long]) and Dow. Graeci, p. 447 a 27 
(Areius Didymus) in contrast to p. 447 B 22 (Albinus). 

¢ See Plat. Quaest. 1001 B supra with note e there. 

4 The Platonic source of this is Timaeus 29 © 3—30 a 3 
(cf. 1015 5 infra [. . . πάντα βουλόμενος αὑτῷ κατὰ δύναμιν 


180 





GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1014 


as if afraid lest by absolving god we get the notion 
that some human being had been the artificer of the 
universe. It is better, then, to be persuaded by 
Plato and, chanting “ for it is the fairest of things 
that have come to be and he the best of causes,’’% to 
assert that the universe has been brought into being 
by god whereas the substance or matter? out of 
which it has come into being did not come to be but 
was always available to the artificer to whom it 
submitted itself for disposing and ordering ὁ and 
being made as like to him as was possible,? for the 
source of generation is not what is non-existent ¢ but, 
as in the case of a house and a garment and a statue, 
what is not in good and sufficient condition. In fact, 
what preceded the generation of the universe was 
disorder, disorder not incorporeal or immobile or 


ἐξομοιῶσαι]). For the tendency to take that passage as 
identifying the demiurge with the model of the sensible 
universe see Plat. Quaest. 1007 c-p supra (εἰκόνες . . . τοῦ 
θεοῦ, τῆς μὲν οὐσίας ὁ κόσμος . . .) With page 89, note ὃ: ef. 
H. Dorrie, Museum Helveticum, xxvi (1969), pp. 222-223 
and Philomathes: Studies ...in Memory of Philip Merlan 
(The Hague, 1971), pp. 41-42. 

¢ Cf. Plutarch, Quaest. Conviv. 731 Ὁ (τὴν ἐκ μὴ ὄντος 
παρανόμως ἐπεισάγουσα γένεσιν τοῖς πράγμασιν) and ddr. 
Colotem 1111 a, 1112 a, and 1113 c; for the general 
acceptance of the principle cf. Aristotle, Physics 187 a 27-29 
and 34-35 and 191 b 13-14 and Chalcidius, Platonis Timaeus, 
p. 323, 1-2 (Wrobel)=p. 296, 5-6 (Waszink). 

f Cf. Dion x, 2 (962 B[... ᾧ τὸ πᾶν ἡγουμένῳ πειθόμενον 
ἐξ ἀκοσμίας κόσμος ἐστί]), Quaest. Conviv. 615 F (τὸν μέγαν 
θεὸν ὑμεῖς πού φατε τὴν ἀκοσμίαν εὐταξίᾳ μεταβαλεῖν εἰς κόσμον 
. ..), and with the rest of this paragraph Plat. Quaest. 
1003 a-B supra and Chalcidius, Platonis Timaeus, pp. 95, 
18-96, 4 (Wrobel) = pp, 80, 20-81, 7 (Waszink) with J..C. M. 
van Winden, Calcidius on Matter? (Leiden, 1965), pp. 
256-258. 


181 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


ΝΜ \ \ > , \ \ » 
(1014) ἄμορφον μὲν καὶ ἀσύστατον τὸ σωματικὸν ἐμ- 

\ \ A 
πληκτον δὲ καὶ ἄλογον TO κινητικὸν ἔχουσα" τοῦτο 

3 “ ) / A b ? / / ¢ \ 
δ᾽ ἦν ἀναρμοστία ψυχῆς οὐκ ἐχούσης λόγον. ὁ yap 

θ \ # A 4 3 ᾽ὔ » A ee 

εὸς οὔτε σῶμα TO ἀσώματον οὔτε ψυχὴν TO ἀψυ- 
C χον ἐποίησεν. ἀλλὰ ὥσπερ ἁρμονικὸν ἄνδρα καὶ 
ῥυθμικὸν' οὐ φωνὴν ποιεῖν οὐδὲ κίνησιν ἐμμελῆ δὲ 
φωνὴν καὶ κίνησιν εὔρυθμον ἀξιοῦμεν οὕτως ὁ θεὸς 
οὔτε τοῦ σώματος τὸ ἁπτὸν καὶ ἀντίτυπον οὔτε τῆς 
ψυχῆς τὸ φανταστικὸν καὶ κινητικὸν αὐτὸς ἐποίη- 

> , \ \ > \ er \ \ 
σεν ἀμφοτέρας δὲ Tas ἀρχὰς παραλαβών, τὴν μὲν 
ἀμυδρὰν καὶ σκοτεινὴν τὴν δὲ ταραχώδη καὶ ἀνόη- 
τον ἀτελεῖς δὲ" τοῦ προσήκοντος ἀμφοτέρας καὶ 


1 ἄνδρα, ῥυθμητικὸν (with n changed to i) -r. 
2 δὲ -omitted by r. 





«ἴῃ Timaeus 50 Ὁ 7 and 51 a 7 ἄμορφος is used of the 
‘* receptacle,’’ whereas dovorarov (used by Plato only in a 
different and irrelevant context [Timaeus 61 a 1]) shows 
that Plutarch is here referring to the “* precosmic ”’ chaos of 
Timaeus 53 a 8—B 4 (see 1016 E-F infra). 

> For the expression cf. De Iside 371 B (τῆς ψυχῆς τὸ... 
ἄλογον καὶ ἔμπληκτον) ; the motivity is τὴν κινητικὴν τῆς ὕλης 
Kat... ἄτακτον καὶ ἄλογον οὐκ ἄψυχον δὲ κίνησιν (1015 Ἑ 
infra). 

4.6. ψυχὴν τὴν πρὸ τῆς κόσμου γενέσεως πλημμελῶς πάντα 
καὶ ἀτάκτως κινοῦσαν (1016 c infra). ἀναρμοστία ψυχῆς is 
interpretation of τὸ τῆς παλαιᾶς ἀναρμοστίας πάθος (Plato, 
Politicus 273 c 7—p 1), quoted by Plutarch at 1015 p infra; 
see also 1017 ὁ (ἐκ τῆς προτέρας ἕξεως ἀναρμόστου καὶ ἀλόγου) 
and 1029 & infra (... ἀταξίαν καὶ πλημμέλειαν ἐν ταῖς κινήσεσι 
τῆς ἀναρμόστου καὶ ἀνοήτου ψυχῆς .. .ὕ). 

4 See 1017 a infra (. .. οὐχὶ σώματος ἁπλῶς οὐδ᾽ ὄγκου καὶ 
ὕλης) and De Εἰ 390 ν (σῶμα . .. ἁπτὸν ὄγκον καὶ ἀντίτυπον) 
with the definition, σῶμα . . . ὄγκος ἀντίτυπος in [Plutarch], 
De Placitis 882 τ'ὶ (Dow. Graeci, p. 310 a 10-11) and Sextus, 


182 








GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1014 


inanimate but of corporeality amorphous and in- 
coherent ¢ and of motivity demented and irrational,? 
and this was the discord of soul that has not reason.° 
For god made neither the incorporeal into body nor 
the inanimate into soul ; but just as a man skilled in 
attunement and rhythm is expected not to create 
sound or movement either but to make sound tune- 
ful and movement rhythmical so god did not himself 
create either the tangibility and resistance of body 4 
or the imagination and motivity of soul,’ but he took 
over’ both the principles, the former vague and ob- 
scure 2 and the latter confused and stupid ἢ and both 
of them indefinite and without their appropriate 


Adv. Math. i, 21 (p. 603, 12 [Bekker]). From Timaeus 
31 B 4-6 taken with 62 c 1-2 it could be inferred that cor- 
poreality entails tangibility and tangibility resistance (c/. 
Proclus, In Platonis Timaeum ii, p. 12, 20-23, p. 13, 2-12, 
and p. 17, 13-17 [Diehl]); but the explicit assertion that 
ἀντιτυπία is the distinctive property of corporeality as differ- 
entiated from the geometrical solid is Epicurean and Stoic 
(see page 824, note a on De Comm. Not. 1080 c infra [es- 
pecially Sextus, Adv. Math. i, 21 and x, 221-222; S.V.F. ii, 
p. 127, 5-11 and p. 162, 29-31]). 

¢ See infra 1017 a (. .. τινα φανταστικῆς . . . φορᾶς .. 
δύναμιν αὐτοκίνητον Kal ἀεικίνητον) and 1024 a (. .. 7... 
φανταστικὴν ...Kiwnow...). Cf. De Sollertia Animalium 
960 ἢ (πᾶν τὸ ἔμψυχον αἰσθητικὸν εὐθὺς εἶναι καὶ φανταστικὸν 
πέφυκεν) ; and for Pintarch's conception of τὸ φανταστικόν cf. 
Quomodo Quis... Sentiat Profectus 83 a-c, De Defectu Orac. 
437 ©, and Coriolanus xxxviii, 4 (232 c). 

7 παραλαβών is from Timaeus 30 a 3-5 (cf. 68 & 1-3), 
cited by Plutarch at 1016 pb infra (see also 1029 Ἑ infra and 
De Defectu Orac. 430 πὶ [. . . παραλαβὼν ἔταξε . . .]). 

9 Cf. Plotinus, Enn. τι, iv, 10, line 30 (τοῦτο νοεῖ ἀμυδρῶς 
ἀμυδρὸν καὶ σκοτεινῶς σκοτεινὸν ...-); in Timaeus 49 a 3-4 
χαλεπὸν καὶ ἀμυδρὸν εἶδος refers to the receptacle, χώρα. 

λ΄ See infra 1015 Ἐπ (ὑπὸ τῆς ἀνοήτου ταραττομένην αἰτίας) 
and 1026 c (ἐμφαίνεται . .. αὐτῆς τῷ μὲν ἀλόγῳ τὸ ταραχῶδες). 


183 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1014) ἀορίστους, ἔταξε καὶ διεκόσμησε καὶ συνήρμοσε, 
τὸ κάλλιστον ἀπεργασάμενος καὶ τελειότατον ἐξ 
αὐτῶν ζῷ ζῷον. ἡ μὲν οὖν σώματος οὐσία τῆς λεγο- 
μένης ὑπ᾽ αὐτοῦ" πανδεχοῦς φύσεως ἕδρας τε καὶ 

Ὁ τιθήνης τῶν γενητῶν" οὐχ ἑτέρα τίς ἐστιν Ὁ 
6. Τὴν δὲ τῆς ψυχῆς ἐν Φιλήβῳ μὲν ἀπειρίαν 
κέκληκεν, ἀριθμοῦ καὶ λόγου στέρησιν οὖσαν ἐλλεί- 
1K, B; az’ αὐτοῦν- ον u, f, m, r, Escor. 72. 


2 γεννητῶν -f, m, τ, Escor. 72. 
3 Aldine; ἐστι -Μ58. 








α This idiomatic use of ἀτελές with the genitive is so 
frequent in Plutarch that its occurrence here is not likely : 
to be a reminiscence of the pun in Phaedrus 248 B 4 (ἀτελεῖς 
τῆς τοῦ ὄντος θέας) or to have any of the profound signifi- 
cance seen in it by Thévenaz (L’ Ame du Monde, p. 18, n. 47). 

> Cf. Timaeus, 30 8 4-c 1, 830 Ὁ 13141, 32D 1f, 685 
1-6, 69 w 8-c 3, 92 c 5-9; with Plutarch’s συνήρμοσε Cf. 
Timaeus 36 ἘΠ ΠΝ ΕΞΈΨΕΤΗ sabia lose 

¢ Timaeus 51 a 7 (πανδεχές [cf. 50 5 6: τῆς τὰ πάντα 
δεχομένης σώματα φύσεως), 52 Β1 (ἕδραν δὲ παρέχον ὅσα ἔχει 

| γένεσιν πᾶσιν). 49 a 5-6 (πάσης εἶναι γενέσεως ὑποδοχὴν αὐτὴν 
οἷον τιθήνην). It is to describe the τόϊβ of χώρα, itself incor- 
poreal and imperceptible to sense (Timaeus 51 a 4-8 2 and 
52 a 8-B 2), that Plato uses these terms; but to Plutarch 
they are indifferently designations of ὕλη (see infra 1015 pv, 
1023 a, 1024 c; cf. Quaest. Conviv. 636 pv and De Iside 
372 «-¥) and, as in this chapter, of corporeality, with which 
ὕλη is thus identified (see 1023 a infra: δεξαμενὴν > Je 
ἐκείνην [seil. σωματικὴν ὕλην] .. . μᾶλλον δὲ σῶμα . . .) and 
which is taken to have existed in precosmic disorder (see 
1017 a infra [οὐχὶ σώματος ἁπλῶς . .. ἦν ὁ θεὸς .. . 
δημιουργός] : : of. Plat. Quaest. 1003 a supra [... τὸ ἄμορφον 
σῶμα. .. 8ἃΠα ἐκ σώματος ἀτάκτου ...], and see page 173, 
note ὃ supra). This precosmic matter Plutarch even calls 
perceptible (1024 B infra [τὸ αἰσθητὸν . . . ἦν ἄμορφον Kal 
dépiorov}), although he had already insisted that Platonic 
matter is entirely devoid of quality (1014 r-——1015 ἢ infra) 
and had asserted that ὕλη becomes tangible and visible, 1.6. 


184 








GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1014 


perfection,* and he ordered and arrayed and fitted 
them together, producing from them the living being 
supremely fair and perfect.” So the substance of 
body is none other than what is called by Plato the 
omnirecipient nature, abode and nurse of the things 
that are subject to generation.° 

6. As for the substance of soul, in the Philebus he 
has called it infinitude? as being privation of number 


perceptible body, only when shaped by participation in the 
intelligible (see 1013 c supra with Plat. Quaest. 1001 pD-r). 
When in [Plutarch], De Placitis 882 c (Dow. Graeci, p. 308 
A 49 and B 5-9; cf. Theodoret, Graec. Affect. Curatio 
iv, 13) the Platonic “ receptacle’ is called ὕλη and char- 
acterized as at once corporeal and without quality, it may 
be an example of the identification of Platonic “‘ primary 
matter’ with the Stoic ἄποιον σῶμα (cf. Simplicius, Phys., 
p. 227, 23-26=S.V.F. ii, frag. 326). Others, however, who 
identified the receptacle with ὕλη, asserted that, being 
without quality, it is neither corporeal nor incorporeal but 
potentially corporeal (Albinus, Epitome viii, 3 [Louis]= 
p. 163, 3-7 [Hermann]; Apuleius, De Platone i, 5=p. 87, 
10-20 [Thomas]; Hippolytus, Refutatio i, 19, 3=pp. 19, 
13-20, 1 [Wendland]; Chalcidius, Platonis Timaeus, 
pp. 342, 16-344, 20 [Wrobel]=pp. 314, 17-316, 13 [Wa- 
szink]), an expedient obviously borrowed from Aristotle (De 
Generatione 329 a 33; cf. Areius Didymus, E'pitomes Frag. 
Phys. 2 [Dox. Graeci, p. 448, 3-12] and “ὁ Ocellus Lucanus ”’ 
ii, 6 [24]=p. 16, 22-24 [Harder]). 

4 This assertion (see 1014 © infra: ἐν δὲ core ie 
ἀπειρίαν... TH ψυχῇ) is justified by nothing in the Philebus, 
not even by Phitebus 26 B 6-10 (the limitless appetites of 
wantonness and vice) or 27 © 1—28 a 4 and 52 c (pleasures 
and pains in the class of τὸ ἄπειρον), for the nature of soul 
is not in question there and such “ psychic infinitude ’’ is 
expressly just one example among many of the ἀπειρία in the 
world (cf. Philebus 16 c 9-10, 24 a—25 a, 25c 5-p 1). In 
De E 391 b-c the ἄπειρον of the Philebus, though taken to 
correspond to the κίνησις of the Sophist, is said by its com- 
bination with the πέρας to constitute πᾶσαν γένεσιν. 


185 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1014) pecis’ τε καὶ ὑπερβολῆς καὶ διαφορᾶς καὶ ἀνομοιό- 
THTOS ἐν αὑτῇ πέρας, οὐδὲν οὐδὲ μέτρον ἔχουσαν" 
ἐν δὲ Τιμαίῳ τὴν τῇ ἀμερίστῳ συγκεραννυμένην 
φύσει καὶ περὶ τὰ σώματα γίγνεσθαι λεγομένην 
μεριστὴν οὔτε πλῆθος ἐν μονάσι καὶ στιγμαῖς οὔτε 
μήκη καὶ πλάτη λέγεσθαι νομιστέον, ἃ σώμασι 
προσήκει καὶ σωμάτων μᾶλλον ἢ τῆς ψυχῆς ἐ ἐστιν, 
ἀλλὰ τὴν ἄτακτον καὶ ἀόριστον αὐτοκίνητον δὲ καὶ 
κινητικὴν ἀρχὴν ἐκείνην, ἣν πολλαχοῦ μὲν ἀνάγ- 

E xynv ἐν δὲ τοῖς Νόμοις ἀντικρυς ψυχὴν ἄτακτον 
εἴρηκε καὶ κακοποιόν" αὕτη γὰρ ἣν ψυχὴ καθ᾽ ἑαυ- 
τήν, νοῦ δὲ καὶ λογισμοῦ καὶ ἁρμονίας ἔμφρονος 
μετέσχεν, ἵνα κόσμου ψυχὴ γένηται. καὶ γὰρ τὸ 


1 ἐλλήψεως τὙὉ. 

4 Timaeus 35 A 1-3. 

” See μεριστὸν δὲ τὸ πλῆθος in the Xenocratean interpreta- 
tion (1012 © supra) and in 1023 Ὁ infra ἐκ μονάδων cor- 
responding to the preceding μήτε τοῖς ἀριθμοῖς as οὐδὲ 
γραμμῶν οὐδ᾽ ἐπιφανειῶν corresponds to the preceding μήτε 
τοῖς πέρασι. For καὶ orvypais in a reference to the Xenocratean 
interpretation cf. Aristotle, De Anima 409 a 3-7 with 
Cherniss, Aristotle’s Criticism of Plato..., p. 396 and n. 322 
and W. Theiler, Aristoteles tiber die Seele (Berlin, 1959), : 
p. 101 ad 18, 1. | 

¢ As in the Posidonian interpretation of chap. 22 infra | 
(see in 1023 B δεξάμενοι τὴν τῶν περάτων οὐσίαν περὶ τὰ σώματα 
λέγεσθαι μεριστήν and i in 1023 ἢ οὐδὲ γραμμῶν οὐδ᾽ ἐπιφανειῶν 
corresponding to μήτε τοῖς πέρασι [see the last note supra}). 
For the distinction between the arithmetical and the geo- 
metrical interpretations ¢f. Iamblichus in Stobaeus, Eel. i, 
49, 32 (pp. 363, 26-364, 12 [Wachsmuth]) and Proclus, Jn 
Platonis Timaeum ii, p. 153, 18-25 (Diehl). 

aes 2 pi tiiine: In Platonis Timaeum ii, ΡΡ. 153, 2ὅ-1δ4., 1 
(Diehl) : . μεριστὴν μὲν οὐσίαν λέγουσι τὴν ἄλογον προοῦσαν 
τῆς δονερε . ., Καθάπερ Πλούταρχος καὶ ᾿Αττικός, Distt 

ὁ See 1014 εκ infra (τὴν ἐν Τιμαίῳ λεγομένην ἀνάγκην) and 


186 





GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1014 


and ratio and having in itself no limit or measure of 
deficiency and excess and difference and dissimilitude; 
and in the Z2maeus that which is blended together 
with the indivisible nature and is said to become 
divisible in the case of bodies* must be held to mean 
neither multiplicity in the form of units and points ” 
nor lengths and breadths,° which are appropriate to 
bodies and belong to bodies rather than to soul, but 
that disorderly and indeterminate but self-moved 
and motive principle which in many places he has 
called necessity ὁ but in the Laws has openly called 
disorderly and maleficent soul.f This, in fact, was 
soul in 1156} ; but it partook of intelligence and rea- 
son and rational concord * that it might become the 
soul of the universe. For the aforesaid omnireci- 


1015 a infra (ὥσπερ ἐν ἸΤολιτικῷ λέγεται... ἀνάγκη . - .) 
with the notes there. 

In 1015 £ infra Plato is said to have called it ψυχὴν 
ἐναντίαν Kal ἀντίπαλον τῇ ἀγαθουργῷ (cf. De Iside 370 F), 
which is closer to the terminology of Laws 896 p 5—898 c 8 
(especially 896 © 5-6, 897 B 3-4, 897 Ὁ 1, and 898 c 4-5), 
the passage that Plutarch has in mind. For his interpreta- 
tion of it, which Atticus adopted, cf. Proclus, In Platonis 
Timaeum i, p. 382, 2-12 and p. 391, 8-12 (Diehl); cf. also 
that of Numenius (p. 94, 6-11 [Leemans]) in Chalcidius, 
Platonis Timaeus, p. 326, 12-17 (Wrobel)=p. 299, 14-18 
(Waszink). In fact, the passages of the Laws envisage no 
such evil ‘* world-soul”’ as Plutarch reads into them and 
lend no support to the identification of evil soul or of soul at 
all with the “ necessity ’’ or with the “ divisible being ”’ of 
the Timaeus (cf. Cherniss, Proceedings of the American 
Philosophical Society, xeviii [1954], p. 26, n. 29; H. Herter, 
Rhein. Mus., c [1957], pp. 334-335; H. Gérgemanns, Bei- 
trdge zur Interpretation von Platons Nomoi [Miinchen, 
1960], p. 200, n. 1). 

σ See 1024 a infra: viv οὐχ ἁπλῶς ψυχὴ 

Cf. Timaeus 36 © 6—37 a 13 see 1016 3 B ‘infra and Plat. 
Quaest. 1001 c with note a and 1003 a supra. 

187 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


A ,ὔ Ρ 

(1014) πανδεχὲς καὶ ὑλικὸν ἐκεῖνο μέγεθος μὲν ἐκέκτητο 
\ , A / 4 \ \ A 
καὶ διάστημα καὶ χώραν, κάλλους δὲ Kal μορφῆς 
A / > »“". a A 
καὶ σχημάτων μετριότητος ἐνδεῶς εἶχεν: ἔλαχε δὲ 
τούτων, ἵνα γῆς καὶ θαλάττης καὶ οὐρανοῦ καὶ 
ἀστέρων φυτῶν τε καὶ ζῴων παντοδαπὰ σώματα 

\ » , 1 / ΕΝ ὦ ΟΣ ΧΗ 
καὶ ὄργανα γίγνηται κοσμηθέν. ot δὲ τὴν ἐν Tt- 
’ 4 > / > \ / \ \ 
μαίῳ λεγομένην ἀνάγκην ev δὲ Φιλήβῳ περὶ τὸ 
μᾶλλον καὶ ἧττον ἐλλείψεως" καὶ ὑπερβολῆς ἀμε- 
/ Ne tg) ΄ a & , 28 \ \ 
Tpiav Kal ἀπειρίαν TH ὕλῃ προστιθέντες ἀλλὰ μὴ 

~ fond a3 , A A 4 4... ἃ A + 
Ε τῇ ψυχῇ, ποῦ" θήσονται τὸ τὴν ὕλην ἀεὶ μὲν ἄμορ- 
φον καὶ ἀσχημάτιστον ὑπ᾽ αὐτοῦ λέγεσθαι καὶ πά- 
7” ποιότητος Kal δυνάμεως οἰκείας ἔρημον εἰκά- 


1 γένηται -Bernardakis. 
2 ἐλλήψεως -r; [ἐλλείψεως καὶ ὑπερβολῆς] -deleted by 


a 


Thévenaz (L’ Ame du Monde, p. 19, n. 62). 


3 Turnebus ; bexa γε ov -MSS. ἐγ ὰ . vac: 16%-f) wae: 
17 -m; vac. 10 -r... ye ov). 


* See 1014 c supra with page 185, note c. 

ὃ For χώρα in this sense of “room” in which to hold 
something cf. De (Comm. Not. 1077 © infra (τοῦ διάστασιν 
οὐκ ἔχοντος οὐδὲ χώραν ἐν αὑτῷ) and Quaest. Conviv. ΤΟΥ B 
(χώραν πλακοῦντι καταλιπεῖν). 

¢ Timaeus 47 πὶ 4—48 a 7, 56 c 3-7, and 68 © I1—69 a 5. 
For the attribution to which Plutarch here objects cf. 
*Timaeus Locrus’”’ 93 a; Diogenes Laertius, iii, 75-76 
(p. 151, 17-24 [Long]); Aétius i, 26, 3 (Dow. Gracci, p. 3214 
18-19 and 8 19-20); Numenius (p. 97, 1-5 [Leemans]) in 
Chalcidius, Platonis Timaeus, p. 328, 8-11 (Wrobel)=p. 301, 
18-20 (Waszink) and zbid., pp. 299, 14-301, 22 (Wrobel) = 
pp. 273, 15-275, 17 (Waszink); Plotinus, Enn. 1, viii, 7, 
lines 4-7; Proclus, Jn Platonis Cratylum, Ὁ. 112, 25-28 
(Pasquali). Even Lamprias in De Defectu Orac. 435 r— 
436 a is made to interpret Plato as οὐκ ἀποστερῶν τὴν ὕλην 


188 








GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1014 


pient and material principle* too already possessed 
magnitude and dimension and spaciousness ὃ ; but it 
was in want of beauty and shape and regularity of 
figures, and these were allotted to it that it might be 
reduced to order and then become all the various 
bodies and organs of plants and animals and of earth 
and sea and sky and stars. Those, however, who 
attribute to matter and not to the soul what in the 
Timaeus is called necessity ® and in the Philebus 
measurelessness and infinitude in the varying degrees 
of deficiency and excess,? what will they make of 
the fact that by Plato matter is said always to be 
amorphous and shapeless and devoid of all quality 
and potency of its own ὁ and is likened to odourless 


τῶν ἀναγκαίων πρὸς τὸ γιγνόμενον αἰτιῶν, and in Quaest. 
Conviv. 720 s-c Plutarch in his own person interpreting the 
Timaeus speaks of the universe as perpetually involved in 
generation and change διὰ τὴν σύμφυτον ἀνάγκην τοῦ σώματος. 

ἃ Philebus 24 a—25 a and 25 c ὅ-Ὁ 1 (see page 185, note 
d supra). For the attribution to which Plutarch here ob- 
jects cf. Hermodorus according to Dercyllides as reported 
from Porphyry by Simplicius, Phys., p. 247, 34-35 ; Proclus, 
In Platonis Timaeum i, p. 263, 10-14 and p. 384, 29-30 
(Diehl) and De Malorum Subsistentia, col. 236, 21-24 
(Cousin) =§ 35, 19-21 (Boese); Aristides Quintilianus, De 
Musica iii, 11 (p. 110, 2-9 [Winnington-Ingram]). 

ὁ Timaeus 50 8 6—c 2, 50 p 7- 1, 50 © 4-5, and 51 a 4-7, 
where as in the following simile (Timaeuws 50 Ἑ 5-8) the 
subject is the receptacle, 1.6. χώρα, and not ὕλη (see τὸ 
mavdexes καὶ ὑλικόν [1014 Ἑ supra] and page 185, note ὁ 
supra). With Plutarch’s statement here cf. Albinus, Hpitome 
viii, 2 (p. 49, 6-11 [Louis]=p. 162, 30-36 [Hermann]) ; Doz. 
Graeci, Ὁ. 308 a 4-9 and B 5-9; and Chalcidius, Platonis 
Timaeus, p. 356, 8-12 (Wrobel)=p. 326, 3-6 (Waszink). 
With his δυνάμεως οἰκείας ἔρημον cf. ἀργὸν ἐξ αὑτοῦ (1015 a 
infra); Proclus, Elements of Theology 80 (p. 76, 5-6 [Dodds)) : 
Simplicius, Categ., p. 249, 26-27 ; Olympiodorus, Jn Platonis 
Phaedonem, p, 40, 19-21 (Norvin), 


189 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1014) ζεσθαι δ᾽ awdeow ἐλαίοις ἃ πρὸς τὰς βαφὰς οἱ 
1015 μυρεψοὶ λαμβάνουσιν; οὐ γὰρ οἷόν τε τὸ ἄποιον 
καὶ ἀργὸν ἐξ αὑτοῦ καὶ ἀρρεπὲς" αἰτίαν κακοῦ καὶ 

> Woe Date θ θ A Il 4 4 “- 9 
ἀρχὴν" ὑποτίθεσθαι τὸν [lAatwva καὶ καλεῖν ἀπει- 
ρίαν αἰσχρὰν καὶ κακοποιὸν αὖθις δ᾽ ἀνάγκην πολλὰ 
τῷ θεῷ δυσμαχοῦσαν καὶ ἀφηνιάζουσαν. ἡ γὰρ 
4 “ 
ἀναστρέφουσα τὸν οὐρανόν, ὥσπερ ἐν [[ολιτικῷ 
λέγεται, καὶ ἀνελίττουσα πρὸς τοὐναντίον ἀνάγκη 
ire) ΤῊΝ 4? 6 fy ‘ong Thi ee ἐλ \ 
καὶ “᾿ σύμφυτος" ἐπιθυμία ᾽᾿ καὶ “' τὸ τῆς πάλαι ποτὲ 
φύσεως σύντροφον πολλῆς μετέχον ἀταξίας πρὶν 
εἰς τὸν νῦν κόσμον ἀφικέσθαι, πόθεν éyyéeyove’ 
τοῖς πράγμασιν εἰ τὸ μὲν ὑποκείμενον ἄποιος" ἦν 
ὕλη καὶ ἄμοιρον" αἰτίας ἁπάσης ὁ δὲ δημιουργὸς 
Β ἀγαθὸς καὶ πάντα βουλόμενος αὑτῷ κατὰ δύναμιν 
ἐξομοιῶσαι τρίτον δὲ παρὰ ταῦτα μηδέν; at γὰρ 

i OS ne ἀρεπὲς “€, Us a m, r, Escor. 72. 
- καὶ ἀρχὴν καὶ ἀρχὴν -f. 
5 ἀφανίζουσαν -r. 
4 συμφύτοις -€, ἃ (corrected in margin). 
5 the B, U5 ἐγέγονε “6.4 ἐγεγόνει -f, Ὡς Ir, Escor. 72. 
V 


ς 
ἄποιος -Β ; ἄποιον -Εἰ ; ἄποιον -all other Mss. 
7 ἄμοιρος -Wyttenbach. 


6 


¢ This substitution for τὰ δεξόμενα ὑγρὰ τὰς ὀσμάς of 
Timaeus 50 © 7-8 is made by Albinus too in Epitome viii, 2 
(p. 49, 12-13 [Louis]=p. 162, 37 f. [Hermann]). For oil as 
the base of perfumes cf. with Plutarch, De Iside 374 © and 
Quaest. Conviv. 661 c especially Theophrastus, De Odoribus 
§§ 14-20 and Pliny, ΛΔ΄. ἢ]. xiii, 7 

> The terminology is Stoic. See infra De Stoic. Repug. | 
1054 a and De Comm. Not. 1076 c-p with note c there; and | 
cf. De Iside 514 E, where ὕλη, which in 372 τ was char- 
acterized as ῥέπουσα dei πρὸς τὸ βέλτιον ἐξ ἑαυτῆς. is ex- 
pressly used not in the Stoic sense of ἄψυχόν τι σῶμα Kal 
ἄποιον ἀργόν τε καὶ ἄπρακτον ἐξ ἑαυτοῦ. 

ς This expression, not used by Plato, combines Plutarch’s 


190 





GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1014-1015 


oils¢ which makers of perfume take for their in- 
fusions? For what is without quality and of itself 
inert and without propensity ὃ Plato cannot suppose 
to be cause and principle of evil and call ugly and 
maleficent infinitude ὁ and again necessity which is 
largely refractory and recalcitrant to god.¢ In fact, 
the necessity and “‘ congenital desire ’’ whereby the 
heaven is reversed, as is said in the Politicus,¢ and 
rolled back in the opposite direction and “ its 
ancient nature’s inbred character which had a large 
share of disorder before reaching the state of the 
present universe,’ whence did these come to be in 
things if the substrate was unqualified matter and 
so void of all causality and the artificer good and so 
desirous of making all things resemble himself as far 
as possible’ and third besides these there was 
nothing? For we are involved in the difficulties of 


interpretations of the Philebus and the Luws in 1014 Ὁ-Ὲ 
supra (see pages 185, note d and 187, note 7). In contrast 
to Plutarch cf. Proclus, In Platonis Timaeum i, p. 175, 8-10 
(Diehl) with Plotinus, Enn. 11, iv, 16, lines 19-24 and Olym- 
piodorus, In Platonis Phaedonem, p. 40, 19-20 (Norvin). 

4 Cf. De Iside 371 s-B (. . . πρὸς τὴν βελτίονα ἀεὶ δυσμα- 
χοῦσαν . .. and .. . ἀφηνιασμοὶ Τυφῶνος) : De Virtute 
Morali 442 a-s and 451 Ὁ. 

¢ Politicus 272 © 5-6 (ἀνελίττουσα from ἀνείλιξις in 270 
p 3 and 286 8 9), for the εἱμαρμένη of which Plutarch here 
substitutes ἀνάγκη, a substitution which he may have thought 
justified by Politicus 269 pv 2-3 (. .. αὐτῷ τὸ ἀνάπαλιν ἰέναι 
... ἐξ ἀνάγκης ἔμφυτον γέγονε) or on the ground alleged in 
1026 B infra (. .. ἀνάγκην, ἣν εἱμαρμένην οἱ πολλοὶ καλοῦσιν). 

7 Politicus 273 καὶ 4-6 with slight adaptation but with the 
significant omission of the immediately preceding τὸ cwpa- 
τοειδὲς τῆς συγκράσεως (contrast Quaest. Conviv. 720 B-c,. ." 
διὰ τὴν σύμφυτον ἀνάγκην τοῦ σώματος .. ., Cited in note ¢ on 
1014 Ἐ supra). 

9 Timaeus 29 © 1—30 a 3 (see note d on 1014 8 supra). 


19] 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


\ ~ 

(1015) Στωικαὶ καταλαμβάνουσιν ἡμᾶς ἀπορίαι, τὸ κακὸν 
9 “- \ δ᾿ 
ἐκ τοῦ μὴ ὄντος ἀναιτίως καὶ ἀγενήτως" ἐπεισ- 
/ χὰ 3 x 
ἄγοντας, ἐπεὶ τῶν γ᾽ ὄντων οὔτε τἀγαθὸν οὔτε TO 
” > 4 ? ? / ~ 
ἄποιον εἰκὸς ἐστιν οὐσίαν κακοῦ καὶ γένεσιν παρα- 
σχεῖν. ἀλλὰ ταὐτὸ Πλάτων οὐκ ἔπαθε τοῖς ὕστε- 
ρον, οὐδὲ παριδὼν ὡς ἐκεῖνοι τὴν μεταξὺ τῆς ὕλης 
καὶ τοῦ θεοῦ τρίτην ἀρχὴν καὶ δύναμιν ὑπέμεινε 
τῶν λόγων tov? ἀτοπώτατον, ἐπεισόδιον οὐκ οἷδα 
ὅπως ποιοῦντα τὴν τῶν κακῶν φύσιν am αὐτο- 

4 \ , > 4 \ ‘ 0.3 
μάτου κατὰ συμβεβηκός. ᾿Ἐπικούρῳ μὲν γὰρ οὐδ 

C ἀκαρὲς ἐγκλῖναι τὴν ἄτομον συγχωροῦσιν, ὡς ἀν- 
αἴτιον ἐπεισάγοντιλ κίνησιν ἐκ τοῦ μὴ ὄντος" αὐτοὶ 
δὲ κακίαν καὶ κακοδαιμονίαν τοσαύτην ἑτέρας τε 
περὶ σῶμα μυρίας ἀτοπίας καὶ δυσχερείας, αἰτίαν 
ἐν ταῖς ἀρχαῖς οὐκ ἐχούσας, Kat ἐπακολούθησιν 
γεγονέναι λέγουσιν. 

7. Ὁ δὲ Πλάτων οὐχ οὕτως, ἀλλὰ τήν ye? ὕλην 

1 ἀγεννήτως -f, m, r. 2 πλάττων ~Escor. 72. 
3 +o -f, m, r. 4 ἐπειάγοντες -Y. 
5. ἀλλά ye καὶ -f, m, r. 

* See De Comm. Not. 1076 c-v infra; cf. De Iside 369 p 
(εἰ yap οὐδὲν ἀναιτίως πέφυκε γενέσθαι αἰτίαν δὲ κακοῦ τἀγαθὸν 
οὐκ ἂν παράσχοι, δεῖ γένεσιν ἰδίαν καὶ ἀρχὴν ὥσπερ ἀγαθοῦ καὶ 
κακοῦ τὴν φύσιν ἔχειν) and Numenius (p. 93, 13-16 [Lee- 
mans]) in Chalcidius, Platonis Timaeus, pp. 325, 22-326, 
3 (Wrobel) =p. 299, 5-7 (Waszink). 

ὃ For οὐδέ in this sense cf. W. J. Verdenius, Alnemosyne, 
4 Ser. vi (1953), p. 109; vii (1954), p. 68; and ix (1956), 
p. 249. 

¢ This “third principle” is ψυχὴ καθ᾽ ἑαυτήν (1014 τ 
supra), whereas the τρίτην τινὰ μεταξὺ φύσιν... of De Iside 
370 r—371 a is Platonic ‘* matter,’’ there said to be οὐκ 
ἄψυχον . . . οὐδ᾽ ἀκίνητον ἐξ αὑτῆς. 

4 i.e, the Stoics, who themselves ὅμοιόν τε εἶναί φασιν καὶ 


192 








GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1015 


the Stoics by bringing in evil without cause and 
process of generation out of what is non-existent,? 
since of things that do exist neither what is good nor 
what is without quality is likely to have occasioned 
evil’s being or coming to be. The same thing did not 
happen to Plato, however, as did to those who came 
later, for ὃ he did not as they did by overlooking the 
third principle and potency, which is intermediate 
between matter and god,° acquiesce in the most 
absurd of doctrines that makes the nature of evils 
supervenient I know not how in a spontaneously 
accidental fashion. The fact is that they,? while 
conceding to Epicurus not even the slightest swerve 
of the atom, on the ground that he thus brings in 
uncaused motion from what is non-existent,’ do 
themselves assert that vice and so much unhappiness 
as there is and countless other monstrous and dis- 
agreeable features of body are without any cause 
among the principles but have arisen by way of 
incidental consequence.f 

7. This is not Plato’s way, however ; but, exempt- 


ὁμοίως ἀδύνατον τὸ ἀναιτίως τῷ γίνεσθαί τι ἐκ μὴ ὄντος (Alex- 
ander, De Fato, p. 192, 14-15 [Bruns]=S.V.F. ii, p. 278, 
14-15). See also next note infra. 

6 Usener, Epicurea, p. 201, 21-23 (in frag. 281). Cf. the 
passages cited in note a on De Stoic. Repug. 1045 s-c and 
in note c on 1050 c infra, among them especially De Sollertia 
Animalium 964 c; Cicero, De Fato 18, 20, and 22-23; 
Galen, De Placitis Hippoc. et Plat. iv, 4 (p. 361, 14-16 
{ Miiller]). 

t Cf. S.V.I’. i, p. vi, lines 7-10 and ii, frag. 1170 (Aulus 
Gellius, vir, i, 7-13); Marcus Aurelius, vi, 36; [Plutarch], 
Consolatio ad Apollonium 117 D-E (. . . οὔτε τῶν κατὰ 
προηγούμενον λόγον συμβαινόντων οὔτε τῶν κατ᾽ ἐπακολούθησιν) 3 
Philo Jud. in Eusebius, Praep. Evang. viii, 14, 45-59 (espe- 
cially i, p. 474, 20-22 and p. 476, 7-8 [Mras}). 


193 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


“- ¢ ,ὔ 3 if a A 
(1015) διαφορᾶς ἁπάσης ἀπαλλάττων Kai τοῦ θεοῦ τὴν 
A aA ἥν ἢ ,ὔ a 
TOV κακῶν αἰτίαν ἀπωτάτω τιθέμενος ταῦτα περὶ 
A 4 , 9 σ΄ an 
τοῦ κόσμου γέγραφεν ev τῷ ΙΠολιτικῷ. “παρὰ 
‘ 2 A ,ὔ , \ 2 
μὲν yap τοῦ ξυνθέντος᾽ πάντα τὰ καλὰ" κέκτηται" 
\ \ ~ 3 Ὁ ¢ \ \ 
παρὰ δὲ τῆς ἔμπροσθεν ἕξεως ὅσα χαλεπὰ Kal 
ἄδικα ἐν οὐρανῷ γίγνεται, ταῦτ᾽ ἐξ ἐκείνης αὐτός 
D τε ἔχει καὶ τοῖς ζῴοις ἐναπεργάζεται."" καὶ μι- 
\ » \ {{ oof 4) ct ~ / 
Kpov ἔτι προελθὼν “ προϊόντος b€”’ φησι “ τοῦ χρό- 
3 A '¢ b) / > ᾽ - A 
νου καὶ λήθης ἐγγιγνομένης ev αὐτῷ μᾶλλον δυνα- 
στεύει' τὸ τῆς παλαιᾶς ἀναρμοστίας πάθος ᾿᾿ καὶ 
κινδυνεύει “ διαλυθεὶς εἰς τὸν τῆς ἀνομοιότητος 
ἄπειρον ὄντα τόπον ᾽᾽ δῦναι πάλιν. ἀνομοιότης δὲ 
A A Ὁ 3 \ 3 ’ὔ > 3 
περὶ τὴν ὕλην, ἄποιον καὶ ἀδιάφορον οὖσαν, οὐκ 
ἔστιν. ἀλλὰ μετὰ πολλῶν ἄλλων καὶ Ἐύδημος 
ἀγνοήσας κατειρωνεύεται τοῦ ΙΙλάτωνος ὡς οὐκ 
κ᾿ ᾽ν. / e » 55S ae , \ , 
εὖ τὴν πολλάκις ὑπ᾽ αὐτοῦ μητέρα Kat τιθήνην 
προσαγορευομένην αἰτίαν κακῶν καὶ ἀρχὴν" ἀποφαί- 
" Auer -r; ξελθέντος -e, ὦ, f, τη, Escor. 72, Aldine; 
roo... vac. 1O-E; vac. 6-B... θέντος -E, B. 
2 πάντα τὰ καλὰ -MSS. (SO Cod. B, Vat. 295, and Ven. 185 
of Plato; and Clement, Stromata 11, iii, 19, 5) 3 : mavra καλὰ 
-all other mss. of Plato (so Theodoret, Proclus, Philoponus, 
Simplicius). 
3 δὲ τοῦ χρόνου φησὶ -Β. 
* μᾶλλον καὶ δυναστεύει -P lato, Politicus Se 7; 
ws οὐκ εὖ ey) εἴ [ks ὡς οὐκ αὐτὴν -f, m, τ, Escor. 72, 
Aldine ; ws... vac. 7-8... τὴν -E, B. 


στ Ν B: κακῶν ιζ ἀρχὴν δέ: u, Escor. 72 (pilav in margin) ; 
κακῶν ῥίζαν ἀρχὴν -f, m, τ, Aldine. 


ΡΟ να συ Σου a ne Ca Se ΝΞ ee - ᾿ς 


α Politicus 273 5 6—c 2. 
> Politicus 273 c 6—-p 1. 


194 





GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1015 


ing matter from all differentiation and putting the 
cause of evils at the farthest remove from god, he 
has. written about the universe as follows in the 
Politicus?: “ For it has got from him who constructed 
it all it has that is fair but from its previous state 
whatever troubles and iniquities occur in the universe 
—from that source it has these itself and produces 
them in its living beings.’’ And a little further on 
still he says : “‘ But with the passage of time and the 
setting in of forgetfulness the effect of the ancient 
discord becomes more potent,’ ® and it is in danger 
of sinking again “ dissolved into the boundless region 
of dissimilitude.”’* Dissimilitude, however, is not 
connected with matter, since matter is without 
quality or differentiation.¢ Yet from misapprehen- 
sion shared with many others even Eudemus rallies 
Plato for not doing right in declaring her to be the 
cause and principle of evils whom he frequently calls 
by the name of mother and nurse.¢ In fact, while 


¢ Politicus 273 Ὁ 6-Ὲ 1. In Plato’s sentence πάλιν goes 
with the words that follow (πάλιν 9 ore Pt . γιγνόμενος) 
and not with the preceding δύῃ as in Plutarch’s ‘paraphrase, 
κινδυνεύει . » - δῦναι πάλιν. On the other hand, all the mss. 
of Plato like all those of Plutarch have τόπον (cf. also 
Plotinus, Hnn. 1, viii, 13, lines 16-17; Eusebius, Praep. 
Evang. xi, 34, 4) and not the πόντον adopted by Burnet, 
Taylor, and Diés on the authority of Proclus and Simplicius 
(cf. the articles listed in Lustrum, iv [1959], p. 148 [+ 746] 
and v [1960], p. 602 [# 1987]). 

@ See 1014 F supra with note 6 there. 

¢ Kudemus, frag. 49 (Wehrli) ; cf. U. Schiébe, Quaestiones 
Eudemeae (Diss. Halle, 1931), pp. 43-45 and Cherniss, 
Aristotle’s Criticism of Plato . . ., note 62 (pp. 95-97, 
especially p. 97). Eudemus is called by Simplicius (Phys., 
p. 411, 15-16; cf. Pe 133, 21-22) the most genuine disciple 
of Aristotle. 


195 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1015) vovros. ὃ γὰρ Πλάτων μητέρα μὲν καὶ ἱ τιθήνην καλεῖ 
E τὴν ὕλην αἰτίαν δὲ κακοῦ τὴν κινητικὴν τῆς ὕλης 
καὶ περὶ τὰ σώματα γιγνομένην μεριστὴν a ἄτακτον 
καὶ ἄλογον οὐκ ἄψυχον δὲ κίνησιν, ἣν ἐν Νόμοις 
ὥσπερ εἴρηται ψυχὴν ἐναντίαν καὶ ἀντίπαλον τῇ 
ἀγαθουργῷ προσεῖπε. ψυχὴ γὰρ αἰτία κινήσεως καὶ 
ἀρχή, νοῦς δὲ τάξεως καὶ συμφωνίας περὶ κίνησιν. 
ὁ γὰρ θεὸς οὐκ ἀνέστησε τὴν ὕλην a ἀργοῦσαν ἀλλ᾽ 
ἔστησεν ὑπὸ τῆς ἀνοήτου ταραττομένην' αἰτίας" οὐδ᾽ 
ἀρχὰς τῇ φύσει μεταβολῆς καὶ παθῶν παρέσχεν, 
ἀλλ᾽ οὔσης ἐν πάθεσι παντοδαποῖς καὶ μεταβολαῖς 
3 ’ 3 a \ \ > / \ / 
ἀτάκτοις ἐξεῖλε τὴν πολλὴν ἀοριστίαν καὶ πλημμέ- 
λειαν ἁρμονίᾳ καὶ ἀναλογίᾳ καὶ ἀριθμῷ χρώμενος 
ὀργάνοις, ὧν ἔργον ἐστὶν οὐ μεταβολῇ καὶ κινήσει 
F ἑτερότητος πάθη καὶ διαφορᾶς" παρέχειν τοῖς 
 πραττομένην -f. 
2 ἔργον μεταβολὴν καὶ κίνησιν -Τὶ (μεταβολὴν καὶ κίνησιν -f} 
{in margin], m?! {in margin]). 
3 διαφορᾶς -H. Οὐ. (“ diversitatis et differentiae ” -Turne- 
_ bus): διαφορὰς -Mss. 


@ For “ mother” cf. Timaeus 50 Ὁ 2-4 and 51 a 4-5 and 
for “ nurse”’ J'imaeus 49 a 5-6, 52 190 4-π 1, and 88 ἢ 6. 
With Plutarch’s statement cf. “ Timaeus Locrus ” 94 a (τὰν 
δ᾽ ὕλαν ἐκμαγεῖον καὶ ματέρα τιθάναν te. . .)3 Albinus, 
Epitome viii, 2 (p. 49, 1-2 [Louis] =p. 162, 25-27 [Hermann]) ; 
Chalcidius, Platonis Timaeus, Ὁ. 304, 4-7 and Ὁ. 336, 18-19 
(Wrobel)=pp. 277, 18-278, 2 and p. 309, 11-12 (Waszink); 
and see page 185, note ὁ supra. 

ὃ Timaeus 35 a 2-3 as interpreted in 1014 ἢ supra (See 
page 187, notes a and d). 

¢ See 1014 p-r supra with note / there. 

4 Cf, Plato, Phaedrus 245 c 5—246 a 2 and Laws 896 a 5- 
B 5 (see supra 1013 c with note ὃ and 1013 F with note a) ; 
and for the argument that follows here cf. Galen, Com- 
pendium Timaei Platonis iv b (pp. 43, T-44, 13 [Kranus- 


196 














GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1015 


Plato calls matter mother and nurse,* what he calls 
the cause of evil is the motion that moves matter and 
becomes divisible in the case of bodies,’ the dis- 
orderly and irrational but not inanimate motion, 
which in the Laws, as has been said,¢ he called soul 
contrary and adverse to the one that is beneficent. 
For soul is cause and principle of motion,? but 
intelligence of order and consonance in motion ὁ ; and 
the fact is that god did not arouse matter from torpor / 
but put a stop to its being disturbed by the mindless 
cause 5 and did not impart to nature the origins of 
change and of modifications but from her, who was 
involved in modifications of every kind and in dis- 
orderly changes,” removed the vast indefinitude and 
jangle, using as tools concord and proportion and 
number,’ the function of which is not by change and 
motion to impart to things the modifications of 


Walzer]|) and Proclus, In Platonis Timaeum i, Ὁ. 382, 2-12 
(Diehl). 
¢ For the relation of τάξις in motion to νοῦς and the lack 
of it to ἄνοια cf. Plato, Laws 898 a 8-8 8. The distinction 
between ἁπλῶς κίνησις and κίνησις ἐν τάξει is drawn in Plat. 
Quaest. 1007 D supra. 
f Cf. 1015 a supra (ἀργόν) with note ὁ there; and for what 
follows see 1014 n-c supra and Plat. Quaest. 1003 a with notes. 
9 See 1014 ὁ supra (τὴν δὲ ταραχώδη καὶ ἀνόητον) and 1016 ς 
in fra (ψυχὴν τὴν - - . πλημμελῶς πάντα καὶ ἀτάκτως κινοῦσαν). 
"Οὐ. Plato, Timaeus 52 Ὁ 4x 1 (τὴν δὲ δὴ γενέσεως τιθήνην 
. ὅσα ἄλλα . .. πάθη . . . πάσχουσαν παντοδαπὴν μὲν ἰδεῖν 
φαίνεσθαι. τὰ ΠΗ 1024 c infra (γένεσιν . .. τὴν ἐν μετα- 
βολαῖς καὶ κινήσεσιν οὐσίαν) : Quaest. Conviv. 720 c (ἐν γενέσει 
καὶ μετατροπῇ καὶ πάθεσι παντοδαποῖς . 
3 Cf. ΠΣ Conviv. 720 B (ἐβούλετ᾽ οὖν μηδὲν... ; ὑπολιπεῖν 
. ἀόριστον ἀλλὰ κοσμῆσαι λόγῳ καὶ μέτρῳ καὶ dobad τὴν φύσιν 
᾿ ai) ; and see 1013 c supra with the passages referred to in 
page 175, note c, especially 1029 n-E and 1030 c in chap. 33 
infra. 


197 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1015) πράγμασιν ἀλλὰ μᾶλλον ἀπλανῆ καὶ στάσιμα καὶ 
τοῖς κατὰ ταὐτὰ" ὡσαύτως ἔχουσιν ὅμοια ποιεῖν. ἡ 
μὲν οὖν διάνοια τοιαύτη κατά γε τὴν ἐμὴν δόξαν 

aA / 

τοῦ Ἰ]λάτωνος. 
8. ᾿Απόδειξις δὲ πρώτη μὲν ἢ THS λεγομένης καὶ 
δοκούσης αὐτοῦ πρὸς ἑαυτὸν ἀσυμφωνίας καὶ δια- 
1016 φορᾶς λύσις. οὐδὲ γὰρ σοφιστῇ κραιπαλῶντι, πό- 
θεν γε δὴ Πλάτωνι, τοιαύτην ἄν τις ἀναθείη περὶ 
οὗς ἐσπουδάκει μάλιστα τῶν λόγων ταραχὴν καὶ 
ἀνωμαλίαν ὥστε τὴν αὐτὴν φύσιν ὁμοῦ καὶ ἀγένη- 
Tov" ἀποφαίνειν" καὶ “γενομένην, ἀγένητον" μὲν ἐν 
Φαίδρῳ τὴν ψυχὴν ἐν δὲ Τιμαίῳ γενομένην." ἡ 
μὲν οὖν ἐν Φαίδρῳ διάλεκτος ὀλίγου δεῖν ἅπασι 
διὰ στόματός ἐστι, τῷ ἀγενήτῳ" τὸ ἀνώλεθρον τῷ 
δ᾽ αὐτοκινήτῳ πιστουμένη τὸ ἀγένητον" αὐτῆς" ἐν 
δὲ Τιμαίῳ “τὴν δὲ ψυχήν ᾽" φησιν ' “οὐχ ὡς νῦν 
ὑστέραν ἐπιχειροῦμεν λέγειν οὕτως ἐμηχανήσατο 
καὶ ὁ θεὸς νεωτέραν---οὐ yap ἂν ἄρχεσθαι πρεσβύ- 
εν , , 10 » 3 ; 11 

Β τερον ὑπὸ νεωτέρου συνέρξας" εἴασεν---ἀλλά πως 

κατὰ τὸ αὐτὸ -F. 2 ἀγέννητον -f, m, r 

ἀποφαίνει -Υ. 

ἀγέννητον -f, m, r. 

Wyttenbach ; γινομένην -Mss. (γιγνομένην -T). 

ἀγεννήτῳ -f, m, Τ. 

TO -U. 

ἀγέννητον -f, m, r. 

δὲ -omitted by B; δὲ δὴ -Plato (Zimaeus 34 Bb 10). 

10 Stephanus from Timaeus 34 c 2; ayysnees =f, te 
συνεὶρξεν -€ (sic); συνεῖρξεν -U ; auveips . . vac. 3 -F, vac. 


2-Bs; cuvap... vac. 3 -Escor. 72 ; : Sse ks Aldine. 
1 ἀλλὰ πῶς Ἔ, B, e, u, Escor. 72. 


* For this collocation see supra Plat. Quaest. 1002 pb, 
note ὁ. | 
> See supra 1014 a, note g. 
¢ Cf. Proclus, In Platonis Timaeum ii, p. 119, 29-30 


198 


GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1015-1016 


diversity and difference? but rather to make them 
inerrant and stable and similar to the entities that 
are invariably identical. Such, then, in my opinion 
is Plato’s meaning. 

8. A first proof of it is that it resolves what is 
called and seems to be his inconsistency and self- 
contradiction.’ For one would not attribute even to 
a drunken sophist and it is nonsense then to attribute 
to Plato in regard to the doctrines about which he 
had been most seriously concerned such confusion 
and capriciousness as to declare of the same entity 
both that it is unsubject to generation and that it 
did come to be, in the Phaedrus that the soul is 
unsubject to generation and in the Timaeus that it 
came to be.© Now, almost everyone has at the tip of 
his tongue the discourse in the Phaedrus ἃ confirming 
the soul’s indestructibility by the fact that it is not 
subject to generation and its not being subject to 
generation by the fact that it is self-moved ; but in 
the Timaeus® he says: “The soul, however, now 
later in the account that we are attempting, was not 
thus junior also in god’s devising—for he would not 
have permitted the senior of those that he had 
coupled to be ruled by the junior—, but we, as we 


(Diehl); Chaleidius, Platonis Timaeus, pp. 91, 9-12 and 
92, 3-11 (Wrobel) = pp. 76, 10-12 and 77, 13-20 (Waszink). 

4 Phaedrus 245 c 5—246 a 2. With Plutarch’s summary 
of the argument here cf. Albinus, Epitome xxy, 4 (p. 121, 
3-6 [Louis] =p. 178, 12-15 [Hermann]); Hermias, /n Platonis 
Phaedrum, Ὁ. 115, 1-3 (Couvreur); and Macrobius, Jn 
Somnium Scipionis τι, xiii, 12. 

¢ Timaeus 34 B 10—35 a 1. See 1013 F supra and the 
notes there; and observe that Plutarch in his quotation 
here stops short of ἐκ τῶνδε . . ., which modifies συνεστήσατο 
in Timaeus 35a 1. ᾿ῃ 


199 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1016) ἡμεῖς πολὺ μετέχοντες" τοῦ προστυχόντος τε καὶ 
εἰκῇ ταύτῃ πῃ καὶ λέγομεν, ὁ δὲ καὶ γενέσει καὶ 
ἀρετῇ προτέραν" (καὶ πρεσβυτέραν)" τὴν ψυχὴν 
σώματος ὡς δεσπότιν καὶ ἄρξουσαν ἀρξομένου 
συνεστήσατο. καὶ πάλιν, εἰπὼν ὡς “ ᾿αὐτὴ ἐν 
ἑαυτῇ στρεφομένη θείαν ἀρχὴν ἤρξατο ἀπαύστου 
καὶ ἔμφρονος Piov,” “τὸ μὲν δὴ σῶμά᾽ ᾿ φησιν 
“ὁρατὸν οὐρανοῦ" “γέγονεν, αὐτὴ" δ᾽ ἀόρατος μὲν" 
λογισμοῦ δὲ μετέχουσα καὶ ἁρμονίας ψυχὴ τῶν 
νοητῶν ἀεί T ὄντων ὑπὸ τοῦ ἀρίστου ἀρίστη γενο- 
μένη τῶν γεννηθέντων." ᾧ ἐνταῦθα γὰρ τὸν μὲν 
θεὸν ἄριστον εἰπὼν τῶν ἀεὶ ὄντων τὴν δὲ ψυχὴν 

Ο ἀρίστην τῶν γεννηθέντων," σαφεστάτῃ ταύτῃ τῇ 
διαφορᾷ καί ἀντιθέσει τὸ ἀΐδιον αὐτῆς καὶ τὸ 
ἀγένητον" ἀφήρηται. 

9. Τίς οὖν τούτων ἐπανόρθωσις ἑτέρα πλὴν ἧς 
αὐτὸς δίδωσι τοῖς δέχεσθαι βουλομένοις; ἀγένη- 
Tov” μὲν γὰρ ἀποφαίνει ψυχὴν τὴν πρὸ τῆς κόσμου 
γεμέσείθα πλημμελῶς πάντα καὶ ἀτάκτως κινοῦσαν 


᾿ μετέχοντες πολὺ -Ἰ. 2 τε -omitted by r. 
ΤΡ ΠΡΌΤΕΡΟΝ -r. 
<...) added by Turnebus from Trmaeus 34 c 4-5 (ef. 
ius F supra). 
᾿ ἘΝ -ποῖ in Timaeus 34. ¢ 5. 
ὁρατὸν τοῦ οὐρανοῦ -f, m, ΤΥ. 
7 αὐτὴ -Β. Miiller from Timaeus 36 Ὁ 63; αὕτη -Μ58. 
(αὔτη τι). 
8 αὕτη μὲν ἀόρατος -ἔ, τη. 13 αὕτη μὲν ἀόρατος μὲν ~Escor. 72. 
9. γενηθέντων -Ἐς, B, u, Escor. 72. 
10 fy m3 γεννηθέν -r (at end of line); γενηθέντων -E, B, e, u, 
Escor. 72. 
11 ἀγέννητον -f, τη, Fr. 12 ἀγέννητον -f, Τὴ, r 








4 Timaeus 36 x 3-4. Plutarch stops short of πρὸς τὸν 
σύμπαντα χρόνον Which in the Timaeus follows ἔμφρονος βίου. 
Ὁ Timaeus 36 © 5—37 a 2. 


200 


GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1016 


partake largely of the casual and random, express 
ourselves in this way too, whereas he constructed the 
soul prior ¢and senior) to body in generation and 
excellence to be mistress and ruler of it as her 
subject.” And again, after having said @ that “ her- 
self revolving within herself she made a divine 
beginning of ceaseless and rational life,” he says?: 
“So the body of heaven has come to be visible ; but 
soul herself, invisible but participant in reason and 
concord,° is become best of the things generated by 
the best of intelligible and everlasting beings.” 4 
lor here he has called god best of everlasting beings 
but the soul best of the things generated, and by 
this most manifest distinction and opposition he has 
removed from her the character of being everlasting 
and ungenerated. 

9. What way of adjusting these statements ὁ is 
there, then, other than what he provides himself for 
those who will accept it? Tor unsubject to genera- 
tion is said of the soul that before the generation of 
the universe keeps all things in disorderly and 
jangling motion,‘ but come to be and so subject to 

¢ See supra 1014 £ and note h there. 

¢ What follows shows that Plutarch construed the passage 
in this way, the second of the three ways considered by 
Proclus (Jn Platonis Timaeum ii, p. 294, 1-18 [Diehl]); see 
also Plat. Quaest. 1002 B (ὁ yap θεὸς ἐν τοῖς νοητοῖς) with 
note d on page 42. 

¢ Secel014 a, note g supra on συνοικειῶν. 

7 Cf. κινούμενον πλημμελῶς καὶ ἀτάκτως in Timaeus 30 a 
3-5 (paraphrased in 1016 pv infra), the cause of which motion 
according to Plutarch must have been precosmic soul (see 
1015 © supra with notes ὦ and g there; cf. Proclus, Jn 
Platonis Timaeum i, p. 382, 3-4 and p. 391, 8-12 [Diehl] 
and Chalcidius, Platonis Timaeus, pp. 326, 15-17 and 328, 
16-20 [Wrobel] =pp. 299, 16-18 and 302, 3-6 [Waszink]). 

201 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1016) γενομένην᾽ δὲ καὶ γενητὴν᾽ πάλιν ἣν ὁ θεὸς ἔκ τε 
ταύτης καὶ τῆς μονίμου τε καὶ ἀρίστης οὐσίας ἐκεί- 
νης ἔμφρονα" καὶ τεταγμένην ἀπεργασάμενος καὶ" 
καθάπερ εἶδος καὶ τῷ αἰσθητικῷ τὸ νοερὸν καὶ τῷ 
κινητικῷ τὸ τεταγμένον ἀφ᾽ αὑτοῦ" παρασχὼν ἡγε- 

D μόνα τοῦ παντὸς ἐγκατέστησεν. οὕτως γὰρ καὶ τὸ 
σῶμα τοῦ κόσμου πῇ μὲν ἀγένητον ἀποφαίνει πῇ 
δὲ γενητόν": ὅταν μὲν γὰρ εἴπῃ πᾶν ὅσον ἣν ὁρατὸν 
οὐχ ἡσυχίαν ἄγον ἀλλὰ κινούμενον ἀτάκτως τὸν 
θεὸν παραλαβόντα διακοσμεῖν καὶ πάλιν τὰ τέσ- 
capa γένη, πῦρ καὶ ὕδωρ καὶ γῆν καὶ ἀέρα, πρὶν ἢ" 

τὸ πᾶν ἀπ᾽ αὐτῶν" διακοσμηθὲν γενέσθαι, σεισμὸν 
ἐμποιεῖν" τῇ ὕλῃ καὶ" ὑπ᾽ ἐκείνης τινάσσεσθαι διὰ 
τὴν ἀνωμαλίαν, ὄντα που ποιεῖ καὶ ὑποκείμενα τὰ 


1 γιγνομένην τ-ὉΥ. 2 γεννητὴν -f, m, Pr. 

3 ἔμφρονον -Ὑ. 

4 καὶ -omitted by B and deleted by Diibner. 

5 B. Miiller (“‘ de suo’ -Turnebus ; “ ex se”’ -Diibner) ; 
am’ αὐτοῦ -MSS. 

° ἀγέννητον one γεννητόν ταν ἜΣ 

7 πρὶν καὶ -Z'imaeus 53 A 7. 

8 an’ αὐτῶν -H. C. (cf. De Defectu Orac. 430 v [ἐπ᾽ αὐτῶν 
-mss.] and Babbitt ad loc, [L.C.L. v, Ὁ. 458, n. 5]) 3 ὑπ᾽ 
αὐτῶν -MSS.; ἐξ αὐτῶν -Timaeus 53 a 7. 

® Stephanus ; ἐμποιοῦν -Mss. 

10 καὶ -omitted by E. 


® Cf. γενομένη τῶν γεννηθέντων (Timaeus 37 a 1-2) quoted 
in 1016 B supra; but καὶ γενητήν is Plutarch’s own expli- 
cation, probably suggested by Timaeus 28 c 1-2 cited in 
1016 © infra (γιγνόμενα Kal γενητα). 

δ See 1013 F, note ὃ supra. 

¢ i.e. the indivisible being of Timaeus 35 a 1-2; see 
1024 a infra: τῆς τε κρείττονος οὐσίας Kal ἀμερίστου... περὶ 
τὴν ἀεὶ μένουσαν... οὐσίαν. . . . For the connotation of ἔκ τε 


202 


GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1016 


generation ® is said on the other hand of soul that 
god installed as chief of the sum of things ® when out 
of this soul here and that abiding and most excellent 
being yonder ¢ he had produced a rational and orderly 
one and from himself¢ had provided intellectuality 
and orderliness as form? for her perceptivity and 
motivity. For thus it is that the body of the universe 
too is said in one context to be ungenerated and in 
another to be subject to generation’: when Plato 
says that 5 everything visible, being not at rest but 
in disorderly motion, was taken over by god who 
arranges it and says again that” the four kinds, fire 
and water and earth and air, before the sum of 
things has come to be arranged from them cause 
matter? to be agitated and are shaken by it because 
of the irregularity, he posits bodies as existing, no 


ταύτης καὶ . - - ἐκείνης See infra 1023 F (.. . δοξαστικὴν ταύτην 
εν νοητικῆς ἐκείνης) and 1024 ὁ (διαδιδοῦσαν ἐνταῦθα τὰς ἐκεῖθεν 
εἰκόνας) ; and for μόνιμος cf. 1094. c-p infra and Adv. Colotem 
1116 8 with Plato, Timaeus 29 B 5-7 and 49 εὶ 3-4. 

d See Plat. Quaest. 1001 c (... καὶ ἀπ᾽ αὐτοῦ καὶ ἐξ αὐτοῦ 
γέγονεν) with note 6 there. 

¢ See 1013 c supra (. . . τὴν οὐσίαν αὐτῆς ὑποκειμένην καὶ 
δεχομένην τὸ κάλλιστον εἶδος .. .) and Proclus, In Platonis 
Timaeum ii, pp. 153, 28-154, 1 (Diehl); cf. also Plotinus. 
Ἐπ. τι, iv, 3, lines 4-6 and 111, ix, 5, line 3. 

7 Cf. Apuleius, De Platone i, 8 (p. 91, 12-13 [Thomas]) ; 
Numenius (p. 91, 9-17 [Leemans]) in Chalcidius, Platonis 
Timaeus, p. 324, 4-11 (Wrobel)=p. 297, 10-16 (Waszink) ; 
Hippolytus, Refutatio i, 19, 4 (p. 20, 2-6 [Wendland]}). 

9 Timaeus 30 a 3-5. For the stress laid on this passage by 
Plutarch and Atticus ef. Proclus, In Platonis Timaeum i, 
Ῥ. 381, 26-28 (Diehl). 

» Timaeus 52 © 3-5 and 53 a 2-7; cf. Plutarch, De Defectu 
Orac. 430 c-D (τὰ στοιχεῖα σείοντα τὴν ὕλην .. .). 

* For the insertion of this term see supra 1013 c, note c 
on page 173. 


203 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


/ A A A , 7 ω 
(1010) σώματα πρὸ τῆς τοῦ κόσμου γενέσεως" ὅταν δὲ 
/ ’ “ A 7 / \ ~ 
πάλιν λέγῃ τῆς ψυχῆς νεώτερον γεγονέναι τὸ σῶμα 
A A ’ 
καὶ τὸν κόσμον εἶναι γενητὸν ὅτι ὁρατὸς καὶ 
ε \ \ A , a 
E ἁπτὸς καὶ σῶμα ἔχων ἐστὶ τὰ δὲ τοιαῦτα γιγνό- 
\ ~ 
μενα καὶ γενητὰ" ἐφάνη, παντὶ δῆλον ws γένεσιν 
τῇ φύσει τοῦ σώματος ἀποδίδωσιν. ἀλλὰ πολλοῦ 
π > , , \ / ι οὐ ΑΝ 
δεῖ τἀναντία λέγειν καὶ διαφέρεσθαι πρὸς αὑτὸν 
3 a A 
οὕτως ἐκφανῶς" ἐν Tots μεγίστοις. ov yap ὡσαύ- 
“Ὁ 3 ~ / / 4 e \ lo 
τως οὐδὲ ταὐτὸ σῶμα γίγνεσθαί τέ φησιν ὑπὸ τοῦ 
a \ 4 \ la 4 
θεοῦ καὶ εἶναι πρὶν ἢ" γενέσθαι: ταῦτα yap ἄντικρυς 
a ΠΝ 9 \ , δα a6 \ \ 7 
φαρμακῶντός ἐστιν. ἀλλὰ τί δεῖ νοεῖν" καὶ τὴν 
/ > ἢ , res. \ \ 8 \ 7 
γένεσιν αὐτὸς διδάσκει. “(τὸ μὲν yap’ πρὸ τού- 
tov’ φησὶ “᾿ ταῦτα πάντα" εἶχεν ἀλόγως καὶ ἀμέ- 
Tpws: ὅτε δ᾽ ἐπεχειρεῖτο κοσμεῖσθαι τὸ πᾶν, πῦρ 
πρῶτον καὶ ὕδωρ καὶ γῆν καὶ ἀέρα, ἴχνη μὲν 
” 11 ¥ £2 wind D , \ 13 ὃ ’ 
ἔχοντα" atta αὑτῶν," παντάπασι μὴν᾽" διακείμενα 


γεννητὸν -f, m, r. 
γεννητὰ -f, τὰ, r (A}, Εἰ P in Timaeus 28 c 2). 
m, Aldine; αὐτὸν -all other ss. (αὐτὸν αὐτὸν -U). 
ἀφανῶς -M, ΤΥ. 
ἢ -omitted by f, m, r, Escor. 72. 
νοεῖν -omitted by f, m, r (added in margin of f and m). 
καὶ τὴν -omitted by Aldine, Basiliensis; καὶ ταύτην 
τὴν OF καὶ τὸ γινόμενον καὶ τὴν -B. Miiller; καὶ τίνα (2) 
-Bernardakis. 

8 +6 μὲν δὴ -Timueus 53 a 8. 

® τούτου -Bernardakis from Timaeus 53 a 8; τοῦ -MSS. 

10 πάντα ταῦτ᾽ -Timaeus 53 A 8. 

11 uy, f,r; ἔχον τὰ -E, B, e, m, Escor. 72. 

12 ἅττα αὑτῶν -Diibner (implied by Xylander’s version) 
from Timaeus 53 B 2 (ἔχοντα αὑτῶν ἄττα [αὐτὰ -A, F, Y; 
Simplicius, Phys., p. 228, 6]); αὐτὰ αὐτῶ -Μ88. 


204: 


sy ὦ ὦ fF ὦ W fF 


GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1016 


doubt, and ready to hand“ before the generation of 
the universe ; but, when again he says that? body 
has come to be junior to soul and that ¢ the universe 
is subject to generation because it is visible and 
tangible and has body and such things had been 
shown to be in process of becoming and subject to 
generation, it is clear to everyone that he attributes 
a genesis to the nature of body.4 Nevertheless, he 
is far from contradicting himself and being so 
manifestly at odds with himself in matters of the 
greatest moment, for it is not in the same way and 
not the same body that he says is brought into being 
by god and exists before it came to be; it takes a 
downright sot ¢ for that, whereas he himself explains 
the sense in which the genesis too must be under- 
stood. ‘‘ For before this,’ he says,f “‘ all these were 
without ratio or measure ; and, when it was under- 
taken to reduce the sum of things to order, fire first 
and water and earth and air, while having some 
traces of themselves, were nevertheless in the very 
condition that is likely to be the state of everything 


4 See 1014 8 supra: οὐ γενομένην ἀλλὰ ὑποκειμένην ἀεὶ τῷ 
δημιουργῷ. . .. 

δ Timaeus 34 B 10—35 a 13 see supra 1016 a-B with 
note 6 on page 199. 

¢ Timaeus 28 8 T-c 2. 

@ See against this conclusion Proclus, Jn Platonis Ti- 
maeum i, pp. 283, 27-285, 6 and ii, pp. 117, 3-119, 10 (Diehl) 
on Timaeus 28 B 7-ο 2 and 34 c 4—35 a 1 respectively. 

¢ Cf. σοφιστῇ κραιπαλῶντι (1016 a supra) and εἰ yap οὐ 
κραιπαλῶντες οὐδὲ φαρμακῶντες .. . (Adv. Colotem 1123 τ). 

7 Timaeus 53 a 8-3 5. 


13 Diibner (implied by Xylander’s version) from Timaeus 
53 8 3 (μὴν -F, Y3 ye μὴν -Α ; μὲν -Simplicius, Phys., 
p. 228, 7); παντάπασιν ἦν -Mss. 


205 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 
(1016) . 


yt ὥσπερ εἰκὸς ἔχειν ἅπαν ὅταν ἀπῇ τινος θεός, οὕτω 
δὴ τότε πεφυκότα ταῦτα πρῶτον διεσχηματίσατο 
” 1 9 ayy Τὼ \ ἢ Δεν ¢ 
εἴδεσι Kat’ ἀριθμοῖς." ἔτι δὲ πρότερον, εἰπὼν ws 
“"- “ / A 
od μιᾶς ἔργον" ἣν ἀναλογίας ἀλλὰ δυεῖν τὸ συν- 
δῆσαι στερεὸν ὄντα καὶ βάθος ἔχοντα τὸν τοῦ 
Ἁ » ᾿ \ ” \ \ ~ e 
παντὸς ὄγκον Kat διελθὼν ὅτι πυρὸς καὶ γῆς ὕδωρ 
ἍΝ ¢e A ? 7, \ . 4 \ / 
ἀέρα τε ὁ θεὸς ἐν μέσῳ θεὶς ere: καὶ συνεστή- 
\ ? / 6c \ , 3 (( 
σατο Tov οὐρανόν, ‘ex Te δὴ τούτων ᾿᾿ φησὶ" “τοι- 
1017 ovTwv καὶ τὸν ἀριθμὸν τεττάρων τὸ τοῦ κόσμου 
σῶμα ἐγεννήθη" δι᾽ ἀναλογίας ὁμολογῆσαν, φιλίαν 
T ἔσχεν ἐκ τούτων, ὥστ᾽ εἰς ταὐτὸν αὑτῷ συνελ- 
θὸν ἄλυτον ὑπὸ τῶν ἄλλων" πλὴν ὑπὸ τοῦ συνδή- β 
f ᾽) / / ἢ δι. 
σαντος γενέσθαι,᾽᾽ σαφέστατα διδάσκων ὡς οὐχὶ 
7 e ~ 70.» y+ \ “ > \ 
σώματος ἁπλῶς οὐδ᾽ ὄγκου Kat ὕλης ἀλλὰ συμ- 
’ A a 6 \ ἐχλ .2 € , 
μετρίας περὶ σῶμα" καὶ κάλλους Kai’ ὁμοιότητος 
ἦν ὁ θεὸς πατὴρ καὶ δημιουργός. ταῦτα" δὴ δεῖ" 
εἴδεσί τε καὶ -A in Timaeus 53  ὅ. 
ἔργου -e, αἱ (corrected by τι5). 
᾿δή φησι τούτων τ-Υ. 
ἐγενήθη -E, B, u? (corrected by αὖ). 
ὑπό του ἄλλου -ΑΛ and P in Timaeus 32 ς 3. 
περὶ σῶμα -omitted by a 
καὶ -omitted by B, αἱ (added superscript by u’). 
8 ταὐτὰ -Hubert (dub., cf. ‘‘ quod idem .. .”’ ~Turnebus). 


9 δὴ -omitted by ἢ, m, r; δεῖ μέρος μῆς, ‘by Eiscor. 72, 
Aldine, Basiliensis. 


ἋὯ ὦ ὧι &©® WD WN fH 


« Cf. Plutarch, De Facie 926 Fr (L.C.L. xii, p. 84, note ὁ): 
but there the absence of god is said to mean absence of 


206 





GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1016-1017 


whenever god is absent from it,? and so, this being 
then their natural state, god first gave them definite 
shape with figures and numbers.” Still earlier, after 
saying that ® it took not one proportion but two to 
bind together the mass of the sum of things since it 
is a solid and has depth and after explaining that ° 
god put water and air between fire and earth and so 
bound together and constructed the heaven,? he 
says¢: “from these, being such in kind and four in 
number, was the body of the universe engendered 
consentient through proportion, and from these it 
acquired amity so that banded in union with itself it 
came to be indissoluble by others than by him who 
had bound it together.” So he most manifestly 
teaches that god was father and artificer not of body 
in the absolute sense,f that is to say not of mass and 
matter, but of symmetry in body and of beauty and 
similarity.? This, then, is what one must suppose in 


νοῦς καὶ ψυχή, whereas here it is assumed to be absence of 
νοῦς Only with ψυχὴ καθ᾽ ἑαυτήν (see 1014 Ἐ, note g supra), 
i.e. irrational soul, present and moving the precosmic chaos 
(see supra 1016 c with note f there and Plat. Quaest. 1003 
A, note h). 

ὃ Timaeus 32 a 7-B 8. 

¢ Timaeus 32 B 3-7. 

4 In fact Plato says συνεστήσατο οὐρανὸν ὁρατὸν Kal ἁπτόν 
(Timaeus 32 B 7-8; cf. 31 B 4-8 ae 36 © 5-6 [quoted in 
1016 8 supra)), although in Timaeus 30 a 3-5 (see 1016 νυ 
supra) the supposed precosmic chaos had been called ὁρατόν 
and Plutarch asserts that the tangibility of body was not 
created by the demiurge (1014 c supra with note d there). 

ε Timaeus 32 B 8--Ὁ 4. 

f See supra pages 183, note d and 185, note c; and with 
σώματος ἁπλῶς cf. ἁπλῶς ψυχήν in 1024 a infra. 

9 Cf. 1014 © supra(...xdddous δὲ καὶ μορφῆς καὶ σχημάτων 
μετριότητος ἐνδεῶς εἶχεν) and Plato, Timaeus 53 8 5-6 and 
69 B 2-5. 

207 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1017) διανοεῖσθαι καὶ περὶ ψυχῆς, ὡς τὴν μὲν οὔθ᾽ ὑπὸ 
τοῦ θεοῦ γενομένην οὔτε κόσμου ψυχὴν οὖσαν ἀλλά 
τινα φανταστικῆς" καὶ δοξαστικῆς ἀλόγου δὲ καὶ 
ἀτάκτου φορᾶς καὶ ὁρμῆς δύναμιν αὐτοκίνητον καὶ 

Β ἀεικίνητον τὴν δ᾽ αὐτὸς ὁ θεὸς διαρμοσάμενος" 
τοῖς προσήκουσιν ἀριθμοῖς καὶ λόγοις ἐγκατέστη- 
σεν ἡγεμόνα τοῦ κόσμου γεγονότος γενητὴν" οὖσαν. 

10. “Ore δὲ περὶ τούτων διενοεῖτο ταῦτα καὶ οὐ 
θεωρίας ἕνεκα τοῦ τε κόσμου [μὴ " γενομένου καὶ 
τῆς ψυχῆς ὁ ὁμοίως" ὑπετίθετο σύστασιν καὶ ,«γένεσιν' 
ἐκεῖνο πρὸς πολλοῖς τεκμήριόν ἐστι μέγα" τὸ τὴν 
μὲν ψυχὴν ὑπ᾽ αὐτοῦ καὶ ἀγένητον" ὥσπερ εἴρηται 

1 φανταστικὴν -Υ. 

2 ἣν δὴ -ἴὸ ; ἣν δὲ -εἰ (ἣν remade to τὴν by 685). 

3. ὃ θεὸς αὐτὸς διαρμοσάμενος -B; αὐτὸς ὁ δημιουργησάμε- 
vos -Ἰ. 

4 γεννητὴν -f, m, r 

5 μὴ -omitted by B, f, m, r; μὴ Ἑ : “ -e, U3 μὴ -Escor. 


72. 

6 MSS.; ὅμως -Wyttenbach (with μὴ γενομένου supra). 

7 καὶ γένεσιν -omitted by r. 

8 μέγα “Hh des (cf. Moralia 91 pv, 624 F, 1101 ©); μέτὰ -e, 
Escor. 12; wera -U : ἔστι. .΄. Vac. 5-H: vac 6-0. ogee 
ἐστι τὸ -f, m, r, Aldine. 

® ἀγέννητον -f, m, r (so also infra γεννητὴν and γεννητὸν 
ἀγέννητον δὲ). 


a Cf. Thévenaz (L’ Ame du Monde, p. 22, note 99): 
‘“ Dans tout ce passage (scil. chap. 9) Plutarque applique 
aussi ἃ l’4me ce que Platon ne disait que du corps.”’ Plutarch 
in fact here abandons the literal interpretation that he pro- 
fesses to maintain, for the Timaeus speaks not of a precosmic 
soul regulated or organized by the demiurge but of soul pro- 
duced by him “‘ substance ”’ and all (cf. Proclus, In Platonis 
Timaeum i, p. 383, 25-31 and ii, p. 119, 10-24 [Diehl] with 
insistence upon the ἐκ τῶνδε . . ., omitted by Plutarch in 


208 


GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1017 


the case of soul also,* that, whereas the one ὃ neither 
was brought into being by god nor is the soul of the 
universe ὁ but is a certain self-moved and so per- 
petually activated potency? of imaginative and 
opinionative but irrational and disorderly transport 
and impulse,’ the other was regulated by god him- 
self with the appropriate numbers and ratios’ and 
then being generated was installed by him as chief 9 
of the universe that had come to be. 

10. That this is what he really thought about these 
matters and that he was not for the sake of examina- 
tion supposing in like manner a composition and 
generation of the soul and of the universe which has 
come to be,” of this a strong indication in addition to 
many is the notorious fact that, while, as has been 
said,? he speaks of the soul both as ungenerated and 


his quotation of Timaeus 34 B 10—35 a 1 [see supra page 199, 
note e}). 

> See 1016 c supra: ἀγένητον μὲν... ψυχὴν τὴν πρὸ τῆς 
κόσμου γενέσεως .. . γενομένην δὲ... ἣν ὁ θεὸς... .. 

¢ Contrast 1024 α infra: νῦν οὐχ ἁπλῶς ψυχὴν ἀλλὰ κόσμου 
ψυχὴν. ... 

4 For δύναμιν see 1015 B supra (τὴν . . . τρίτην ἀρχὴν καὶ 
δύναμιν) ; for the implication of καί cf. Hermias, /n Platonis 
Phaedrum, p. 103, 20-21 (with p. 104, 7-8) and p. 112, 33-34 
(Couvreur) and see swpra 1016 a, note d. 

¢ See 1024 a infra (τὴν δοξαστικὴν καὶ φανταστικὴν . .. 
κίνησιν . - .) and supra 1014 c, note 9. 

7 See supra page 175, note c. 

9 See supra 1013 F, note b. 

» See supra 1013 a (chap. 8 init.). 

#1016 a supra (... ὁμοῦ καὶ ἀγένητον ... καὶ γενομένην, 
ἀγένητον μὲν ev Φαίδρῳ τὴν ψυχὴν ἐν δὲ Τιμαίῳ γενομένην). 
Resolved by Plutarch in his fashion in 1016 c supra (chap. 9 
init.), this was used by Proclus (In Platonis Timaeum i, 
p. 287, 18-23 [Diehl]) as evidence that Plato in the 7%maeus 
could call the universe γενητόν also though holding it to be 
ἀγένητον κατὰ χρόνον. 


209 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1017) καὶ γενητὴν λέγεσθαι. τὸν δὲ κόσμον ἀεὶ μὲν γεγο- 
νότα καὶ γενητὸν ἀγένητον δὲ μηδέποτε μηδ᾽ ai- 
διον. τὰ μὲν οὖν ἐν Τιμαίῳ τί δεῖ προφέρειν ;" 
ὅλον γὰρ καὶ πᾶν τὸ σύγγραμμα περὶ κόσμου γενέ- 
σεως ἄχρι τέλους ἀπ᾽ ἀρχῆς" ἐστι. τῶν δ᾽ ἄλλων 

C ἐν μὲν ᾿Ατλαντικῷ προσευχόμενος ὁ Τίμαιος ὀνο- 
μάζει τὸν πάλαι μὲν ἔργῳ γεγονότα νῦν δὲ λόγῳ" 
θεόν, ἐν Ἰ]ολιτικῷ δὲ 6 Ἰ]αρμενίδειος ἕένος τὸν 
κόσμον ὑπὸ τοῦ θεοῦ συντεθέντα φησὶ πολλῶν ἀγα- 
θῶν μεταλαβεῖν, εἰ δέ τι φλαῦρόν € ἐστιν ἢ «χαλεπόν, 
ἐκ τῆς προτέρας ἕξεως ἀ ἀναρμόστου καὶ ἀλόγου συμ- 
μεμιγμένον ἔχειν: ἐν δὲ τῇ Ἰ]ολιτείᾳ περὶ τοῦ 
ἀριθμοῦ, ὃν γάμον ἔνιοι καλοῦσιν, ὁ Σωκρά- 

> , f cc 49) 66 / 
τῆς ἀρχόμενος λέγειν “ἔστι δέ᾽᾽ φησι “θείῳ 
\ ~4 ; A 5 »? \ , 
μὲν γενητῷ, περίοδος ἣν" ἀριθμὸς περιλαμβάνει 
1 B (προ -E in margin); προσφέρειν -all other mss. 
2 an’ ἀρχῆς ἄχρι τέλους -Β. 
3 λόγοις -Plato, Critias 106 a 4. 
4 γεννητῷ -f, m, r, —— 72, Plato (Republic 546 5 3). 


5 ἢ -u. 








* Contrast Joannes Lydus, De Mensibus iii, 3 (p. 38, 
13-16 [Wuensch]). What Plutarch here states as a fact 
(cf. Philoponus, De Aeternitate Mundi vi, 24 [pp. 199, 26- 
200, 3, Rabe]), taking it to be compatible with his previous 
assertion that Plato τὸ σῶμα τοῦ κόσμου πῇ μὲν ἀγένητον 
ἀποφαίνει πῇ δὲ γενητόν (1016 ἢ supra with note / there), 
would have been denied by those who read Timaeus 27 c 5 
in the way reported and rejected by Proclus (Jn Platonis 
Timaeum i, Ὁ. 219, 13-18 [Diehl]) ; and it would be untrue 
also if Timaeus 40 Β 5 in the version of A, adopted by modern 
editors, were surely right, but the ἀΐδια there used of the 
‘* fixed stars ’’ was not in the texts read by Cicero, Proclus, 
and Chalcidius and so may not have been in that known to 
Plutarch. 

> Critias 106 a 3-4: τῷ δὲ πρὶν μὲν πάλαι ποτ᾽ ἔργῳ νῦν 


210 


GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1017 


as generated, he always speaks of the universe as 
having come to be and as generated and never as 
ungenerated or everlasting. As to the Timaeus, 
what need to cite passages in it? For the whole 
work in its entirety from beginning to end is about 
the generation of the universe. Among his other 
writings, however, in the Account of Atlantis Timaeus 
invokes by name the god that in fact of old but now 
in word has come to be,® and in the Politicus the 
Parmenidean Stranger says © that the universe con- 
structed by god partook of much good and that 
anything defective or troublesome in it is an in- 
gredient retained from its prior discordant and ir- 
rational state ; and in the Republic Socrates, when 
he begins to speak about the number that some call 
Nuptial,? says: “ A divine object of generation has 
a period that is comprised by a perfect number,’ ¢ 


δὲ λόγοις ἄρτι θεῷ γεγονότι προσεύχομαι (cf. P. Frutiger, Les 
Mythes de Platon, p. 909, n. 1 and p. 195, ἢ. 2 on Timaeus 
20 ἢ 7 and 26 © 4-5). Plutarch’s transposition of the words 
tends to diminish their ambiguity and so may not have been 
unintentional. 

¢ Cf. Politicus 269 p 8-9 and 273 5 4- 1 (see 1015 c-p 
supra (chap. 7 init.}). 

ἃ Republic 546 5 3-Ὁ 3. With Plutarch’s expression here 
ef. Nicomachus, Arithmetica Introductio τι, xxiv, 11 (p. 131, 
8-9 [Hoche]): κατὰ τὸν τοῦ λεγομένου γάμου τόπον ἐν TH 
Πολιτείᾳ. . . . lamblichus refers to the passage as τὸν ἐν τῇ 
Πλάτωνος πολιτείᾳ γαμικὸν ἀριθμόν (In Nicomachi <Arith- 
meticam Introductionem, Ὁ. 82, 20-21 | Pistelli]), and Plutarch 
himself in De Iside 373 ¥ speaks of τὸ γαμήλιον διάγραμμα 
there formulated. 

¢ Republic 546 8 3-4. In 1018 c infra Plutarch says that 
six is τέλειος and is called γάμος but does not suggest any 
connexion between that and this sentence of Plato’s, the 
ἀριθμὸς τέλειος Of which is not the ‘ nuptial number ” any- 
way but is distinguished from it. 


211 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1017) τέλειος,᾽᾿ οὐκ ἄλλο καλῶν θεῖον yevnrov’ ἢ τὸν 
κόσμον. 

1022 α 21. (᾿Αλλ᾽ οὐδὲ περὶ τοῦ κόσμου καὶ τῆς ψυχῆς 
ὁμοίως) ἐνζταῦθα λέγει τὸ ἀμέριστον καὶ ἀεὶ" 
κατὰ ταὐτὰ ἔχον" ὡς μορφὴν καὶ εἶδος, τὸ δὲ περὶ 
τὰ σώματα“ γιγνόμενον μεριστὸν ὡς ὑποδοχὴν καὶ 
ὕλην, τὸ δὲ μῖγμα κοινὸν ἐξ ἀμφοῖν ἀποτετελεσμέ- 
νον. ἡ μὲν οὖν ἀμέριστος οὐσία καὶ ἀεὶ κατὰ 
ταὐτὰ καὶ ὡσαύτως ἔχουσα μὴ μικρότητι καθάπερ 
τὰ ἐλάχιστα τῶν σωμάτων νοείσθω φεύγουσα τὸν 


1 γεννητὸν -f, m, r, Escor. 72. 

2 κυ ss) e@v<.. .>).-supplied by Ἢ. ἔκ xoomoy. (0s wae 
-E; vac.8-B... followed by δὲ ἡ τῶν τριῶν (chap. 11 [1017 
σ] infra) through dpriwy καὶ 7 (chap. 20 [1022 E] infra)... 
vac. 4-1/2 lines -E; vac. 2-1/2 lines -B .. . followed by 
κατὰ τὰ αὐτὰ (chap. 21 [1022 ©] here) through τῶν δυεῖν 
δευτέρα (chap. 30 [1027 ¥] infra) followed immediately by 
περιττῶν. τὴν yap (chap. 30 b [1027 F] infra) to the end -E, 
Bs: κόσμον ... «Νϑρ,ὅ 4; vae. 3-9.” ..dus . ἄπει ee 
followed by δὲ ἡ τῶν τριῶν through ἀρτίων καὶ ἐπὶ . . . vac. 
14 -f; vac. 18 -m,r... followed by κατὰ τὰ αὐτὰ through 

᾿ τῶν δυοῖν. δευτέρα (δευτέρα δὲ -f) τῶν περιττῶν. τὴν yap -f, 


[ΚΤ ; κόσμον. ἔνθα (ἐν... vac. 2 -Escor. 72) δὲ ἡ τῶν τριῶν 


through ἀρτίων καὶ ἐπὶ κατὰ (κατὰ -Escor. 72 ; ἐπϊκατὰ -τ)} τὰ 
αὐτὰ through τῶν δυοῖν δευτεριττῶν (ρατῶνπε -Escor. 72 in 
margin) τὴν γὰρ -e, u, Esecor. 72 ; κατὰ τὰ αὐτὰ... τῶν δυεῖν 
δευτέρα (chaps. 21-30) and δὲ ἡ τῶν τριῶν . . . ἀρτίων καὶ 
(chaps. 11-20) transposed by Maurommates (1848) and B. 
Miiller (1870 and 1873). 

3. Β ; ἔχων -all other mss. 

4 περὶ σῶμα -f. 

5 ἀποτελεσμένον -€, U, f. 

« Cf. Proclus, In Platonis Rem Publicam ii, pp. 14, 8-15, 
20 and p. 30, 6-10 (Kroll); and In Platonis Timaeum i, 
p. 292, 6-9 (Diehl). 

> The supplements proposed by B. Miiller (1870 [p. 398] 


212 


GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1017, 1022 


what he calls a divine object of generation being 
nothing other than the universe.4 

41. <Nor in our passage’ either does he with 
regard to the universe and the soul alike speak of 
what is indivisible and ever) invariable as shape or 
form, of what becomes divisible in the case of bodies 
as receptacle or matter, and of the mixture as having 
been produced from both in common.’ Now, the 
indivisible and ever invariable and identical being is 
to be thought of as eluding division not because of 
minuteness as do the smallest of bodies,¢ for it is the 


and 1873 [p. 33]), which like the earlier one by Maurom- 
mates (1848 [p. 38]) introduce the name of Crantor, were 
criticized by H.-R. Schwyzer (Rhein. Mus., lxxxiv [1935], 
pp. 361-363) and by Thévenaz (L’ Ame du Monde, pp. 61- 
62), who later (Rev. Etudes Grecques, lii [1939], pp. 358-366) 
gave in French paraphrase a supplement of his own, gratui- 
tously assuming on the basis of De Iside 373 r—374 a that 
Plutarch here too had introduced the triangle supposedly 
used in the nuptial number and had confused the latter with 
the τέλειος ἀριθμός just mentioned but correctly observing 
that chap. 21 must continue the theme introduced at the 
beginning of chap. 10 by οὐ. .. τοῦ τε κόσμου... . καὶ τῆς 
ψυχῆς ὑπετίθετο σύστασιν καὶ γένεσιν. 

ὁ ὁ, ὁ. Timaeus 35 a 1-8 4 (1012 B-c supra); see νῦν in 
1023 a infra. 

¢ For identification of the indivisible with shape or form 
and of the divisible with matter H.-R Schwyzer (Rhein. 
Mus., Ixxiv [1935], p. 363) cites “‘ Timaeus Locrus’”’ 94 a 
(ὕλαν ... τὰν δὲ περὶ τὰ σώματα μεριστὰν εἶμεν ...) and 97 κε 
(ἀρχαὶ . . . ὡς μὲν ὑποκείμενον a ὕλα ὡς δὲ λόγος μορφᾶς τὸ 
εἶδος). to which add 95 Ἑ (. .. κρᾶμα . . -. ἔκ τε τᾶς ἀμερίστω 
noes καὶ τᾶς μεριστᾶς οὐσίας, ws ἕν κρᾶμα ἐκ δύο τουτέων 
εἶμεν). 

e This does not imply that anyone had taken the “ in- 
divisible being ”’ of Timaeus 35 a to mean “* minimal body ”’ 
(though it is treated as quantitatively indivisible, i.e. as a 
spatial point, by Aristotle in his criticism of Timaeus 37 a 
[cf. Cherniss, Aristotle’s Criticism of Plato .. ., n. 316 on 


213 


‘ 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1022) μερισμόν: τὸ yap ἁπλοῦν Kal ἀπαθὲς καὶ καθαρὸν' 
αὐτῆς καὶ μονοειδὲς ἀμερὲς εἴρηται καὶ ἀμέριστον, 
ᾧ καὶ τῶν συνθέτων καὶ μεριστῶν καὶ διαφερο- 
μένων ἁμωσγέπως θιγοῦσα" παύει τὸ πλῆθος καὶ 

F καθίστησιν εἰς μίαν διὰ ὁμοιότητος ἕξιν. τὴν δὲ 
περὶ τὰ σώματα γιγνομένην" μεριστὴν εἰ μέν τις 
ἐθέλοι' καλεῖν ὕλην ὡς καὶ ὑποκειμένην ἐκείνῃ καὶ 
μεταληπτικὴν ἐκείνης φύσιν, ὁμωνυμίᾳ χρώμενος, 
οὐ διαφέρει πρὸς τὸν λόγον: οἱ δὲ σωματικὴν ἀξι- 
οῦντες ὕλην συμμίγνυσθαι τῇ ἀμερίστῳ. διαμαρ- 

1 καθαρὸν καὶ ἀπαθὲς -B. 
2 θιγοῦσα -Ditbner ; θήγουσα -Β, u1; θίγουσα -all other mss. 
3 Maurommates ; γενομένην -MSS. 4 ἐθέλει -B, u, r. 


p. 394 and p. 407]) but is a warning against the common 
association of ἀμερές and ἐλάχιστον (cf. Xenocrates, frag. 51 
{Heinze}; Alexander, Metaph., p. 247, 22-24; Simplicius, 
Categ., p. 39, 12-16) and, as is indicated by Plat. Quaest. 
1002 c-p (see note ὁ there), was probably suggested by such 
misleading expressions aS ἡ ἀμέριστος οὐσία. . . ἐστιν εἰς 
βραχὺ συνηγμένη .. . (Plat. Quaest. 1001 Ὁ): cf. the warning 
against taking indivisibly one to mean ἕν ὡς ἐλάχιστον (Da- 
mascius, Dub. et Sol., pp. 2, 24-3, 2 [Ruelle]=Speusippus, 
frag. 36 [Lang] and Anon. in Platonis Parmenidem 1, 20- 
94.-- Rhein. Mus., xivii [1892], p. 602=P. Hadot, Porphyre 
et Victorinus ii [Paris, 1968], p. 66). 
¢ Cf. the characteristics ascribed to the νοῦς of Anaxagoras 
by Plutarch (Pericles iv, 6 [154 c] ) and by Aristotle (Physics 
256 Ὁ 24-25; De Anima 405 a 16-17, 405 Ὁ 19-21, 429 Ὁ 23- 
24) and by the latter to his own νοῦς ποιητικός (De Anima 
430 a 17-18); and for Plutarch himself see infra 1024 a 
(τὸ yap νοερὸν -.. ἀπαθὲς .. .) and 1026 D(... ἔκ τε τῆς θείας 
καὶ ἀπαθοῦς . . .) and De Facie 945 c-p (ὁ δὲ νοῦς ἀπαθής). 
In Plat. Quaest. 1002 σ-Ὁ ἁπλοῦν καὶ εἰλικρινὲς καὶ καθαρὸν 
ἁπάσης ἑτερότητος καὶ διαφορᾶς (= μονοειδές here) characterizes 
the incorporeal and intelligible (as does ἀπαθές in Amatorius 
765 A, τὰ νοητὰ . . - τῆς ἀσωμάτου καὶ ἀπαθοῦς οὐσίας εἴδη). but 
Plutarch treats νοῦς itself as ἃ νοητόν (see note g on Plat. 
Quaest. 1002 c and note ὃ on 1002 £ supra). 


214 


GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1022 


simplicity and impassivity and purity and uniformity 
of it? that is meant by its being without parts and 
indivisible, that with which when it somehow just 
touches ὃ objects composite and divisible and differing 
it puts a stop to their multiplicity and reduces it to a 
state that is single through similarity.¢ As to the 
being that becomes divisible in the case of bodies, if 
anyone should wish to call it matter homonymously 
in the sense of a nature underlying the former and 
capable of participating in it,¢ this use of the term 
makes no difference to the meaning ; but those who 
maintain that corporeal matter is mixed with the 
indivisible being are utterly mistaken,? first because 


ὑ Cf. Timaeus 37 a 5-6 (ὅταν . .. ἐφάπτηται. . .) and 
Aristotle’s criticism (De Anima 407 a 15-18) as well as his 
own use of the metaphor (Metaphysics 1072 b 20-21 and 
1051 Ὁ 24-25); cf. also Theophrastus, etaph. 9 B 13-16 
and Speusippus, frag. 30, 10-11 (Lang) and among the many 
later occurrences especially Hermias, Jn Platonis Phaedrum, 
p. 64, 15-17 (Couvreur). 

¢ Cf. Themistius, Anal. Post., p. 64, 18-20 (τὴν δὲ καθόλου 
ἐπιφορὰν ὁ νοῦς ποιήσεται. τούτου yap ἔργον ἤδη τὰ πολλὰ ἑνοῦν 
καὶ τὰ ἄπειρα, ὅπερ φησὶ Πλάτων, πέρατι συνδήσασθαι [Philebus 
27 p 9]) and at 1025 c infra the description of the function 
of ““sameness”’: ὧν ἂν ἅψηται. . . συνάγειν καὶ συνιστάναι 
διὰ ὁμοιότητος ἐκ πολλῶν μίαν ἀναλαμβάνοντος μορφὴν καὶ δύναμιν. 

4 So Plutarch himself has called it: see 1013 c supra 
with note 6 on page 203 supra and cf. De Iside 374 © (τὴν 
ψυχὴν . . . ὡς ὕλην . .. τῷ λόγῳ . . » παρέχομεν). 

¢ See 1013 Β-6 supra with note ¢ there. So here Crantor, 
while not the only one (see note ὦ on 1022 πὶ supra), is, 
however unjustifiably and Schwyzer to the contrary not- 
withstanding (Rhein. Mus., Ixxxiv [1935], p. 362), one 
among those whom Plutarch has in mind. In addition to 
the subsequent arguments of Plutarch’s see the one adduced 
against Eratosthenes by Proclus (In Platonis Timaeum ii, 
p. 152, 28-29 [Diehl]): κρᾶσις yap οὐκ ἄν ποτε γένοιτο ... 
ἀμερίστου Kal σώματος. 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


1023 τάνουσι, “πρῶτον μὲν᾽' ὅτι τῶν ἐκείνης. ὀνομάτων 
οὐδενὶ νῦν ὁ Πλάτων κέχρηται (δεξαμενὴν γὰρ 
εἴωθε καὶ πανδεχῆ καὶ τιθήνην ἀεὶ καλεῖν ἐ ἐκείνην, 
οὐ περὶ τὰ σώματα μεριστὴν μᾶλλον δὲ σῶμα 
μεριζόμενον εἰς τὸ καθ᾽ ἕκαστον) ἔπειτα τί διοίσει 
τῆς τοῦ κόσμου γενέσεως ἡ τῆς ψυχῆς, εἴπερ ἀμ- 
φοτέροις ἔ ἔκ τε τῆς ὕλης καὶ τῶν νοητῶν “γέγονεν ἡ ἡ 
σύστασις; αὐτός γε μὴν ὁ Ἠλάτων, ὥσπερ ἀπ- 
ὠθούμενος" τῆς ψυχῆς τὴν ἐκ σώματος γένεσιν, 
ἐντὸς αὐτῆς φησιν ὑπὸ τοῦ θεοῦ τεθῆναι τὸ σωμα- 
τικὸν εἶτ᾽ ἔξωθεν ὑπ᾽ ἐκείνης περικαλυφθῆναι". καὶ 

Β ὅλως ἀπεργασάμενος τῷ λόγῳ τὴν ψυχὴν ὕστερον" 
ἐπεισάγει τὴν περὶ τῆς ὕλης ὑπόθεσιν, μηδὲν ad- 
τῆς πρότερον ὅτε τὴν ψυχὴν ἐγέννα δεηθείς, ὡς 
χωρὶς ὕλης γενομένην. 

φῳ Ὅμοια δὲ τούτοις ἔστιν a ἀντειπεῖν καὶ τοῖς περὶ 
ΠΠοσειδώνιον. οὐ γὰρ μακρὰν τῆς ὕλης ἀπέστη- 
1 μὲν -omitted a f, m, r, Escor. 72. 
ἢ -U. 
3 EK, B; ἀποθέμενος -all other mss. 
* περικεκαλυφθῆναι -τ. 
ὃ ὕστερος -U. 





@ See page 213, note c supra; and Pi: νῦν δ byte sense 866 
1024 a infra, Plat. Quaest. 1009 c supra, and J. H. Quincey 
(J.H.S., Ixxxvi [1966], p. 149, n. 17) on Moralia 22 r. 

> δεξαμενή occurs in Timaeus 53 4 3 (cf. Plutarch, De 
Iside 374 3; [Plutarch], De Placitis 882 c=Dox. Graeci, 
p. 308 a 4-9 and B 5-9), πανδεχές in Timaeus 51 a 7, and 
τιθήνη in Timaeus 49 a 6, 52 v 5, 88 p 6. See pages 185, 
note c and 197, note a supra. 

¢ This last (cf. De Defectu Orac. 429 8, εἰς πλείονα μέρη 
τοῦ αἰσθητοῦ καὶ σωματικοῦ μεριζομένου διὰ τὴν σύμφυτον ἀνάγκην 
τῆς ἑτερότητος) is implicitly denied by Plato in Temaeus 51 ἃ 
4-7, where the receptacle is declared to be ‘‘ not earth or 
air or fire or water μήτε ὅσα ἐκ τούτων μήτε ἐξ ὧν ταῦτα yéyovev.”” 


216 


GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1023 


Plato in the present passage? has used none of the 
names for the former (for that it is his custom always 
to call receptacle and omnirecipient and nurse,? not 
divisible in the case of bodies but rather body that is 
divided into particularity ὁ) and secondly wherein 
would the generation of the soul differ from that of 
the universe if both have had as constituents of their 
composition matter and the intelligibles?¢ In any 
case, Plato himself, as if warding off from soul the 
coming to be out of body, says that the corporeal 
was placed by god within her and then enveloped 
with her on the outside ὁ; and, quite generally, it is 
after having produced the soul in his account that he 
introduces in addition the theory about matter,f 
having had no need of it before when he was generat- 
ing the soul, as it presumably came to be apart from 
matter. 

22. Similar objections can be made also to Posi- 
donius and his followers.’ For they did not withdraw 

4 See 1013 s-c and note 6 on 1022 F supra. 

¢ Timaeus 34 8 3-4 and 36 p 9-x 3 (cf. Cherniss, Aristotle’s 
Criticism of Plato ..., pp. 406-407 and n. 334), and see 
supra Plat. Quaest. 1002 B-c with note f there. 

7 Plutarch means the account of the receptacle, which is 
introduced at Timaeus 48 © 2—49 a 6; but he conveniently 
forgets both the earlier treatment of the corporeality of the 
universe (31 B 4—32 c 4), to which he had himself referred 
at 1016 r—1017 a supra, and the warning about the sequence 
given in Timaeus 34 B 10—35 a 1 and quoted by himself 
at 1016 a-B supra (cf. Helmer, De An. Proc., p. 15 and 
Cherniss, Aristotle’s Criticism of Plato ..., pp. 424-425). 

9 For this chapter (=F 141 a [Edelstein-Kidd]) cf. 
especially Thévenaz, L’ Ame du Monde, pp. 63-67 and in 
P. Merlan’s last extensive treatment, Platonism to Neo- 
platonism, pp. 34-58, the bibliography on pp. 55 and 57, to 
which add Marie Laffranque, Poseidonios d’ Apamée (Paris, 
1964), pp. 373-374, pp. 379-380, and pp. 431-432. The 


217 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1023) σαν,᾿ ἀλλὰ δεξάμενοι τὴν τῶν περάτων οὐσίαν περὶ 
τὰ σώματα λέγεσθαι μεριστὴν καὶ ταῦτα τῷ νοητῷ 
μίξαντες ἀπεφήναντο τὴν ψυχὴν ἰδέαν εἶναι τοῦ 
πάντῃ διαστατοῦ κατ᾽ ἀριθμὸν συνεστῶσαν ἁρμο- 

1 ἀπέστησαν τὴν ψυχήν -Epitome 1080 κ infra. 


phrase τοῖς περὶ Ποσειδώνιον (cf. Wyttenbach, Animadver- 
stones on De E 385 a) might of itself mean only “ Posidonius ”’ 
(so Turnebus, Xylander, and Amyot) or only his pupils or 
‘ circle” (cf. Laffranque, op. cit., Ὁ. 379, n. 37); but, as by 
οἱ περὶ τὸν Kpavropa (1012 τ supra) after of δὲ Kpdvrop.. . 
προσέθεντο, μιγνύντι ... (1012 vp supra) Plutarch must have 
meant ‘‘ Crantor and his followers,” so here too he probably 
meant to refer both to Posidonius himself and to his fol- 
lowers. His immediate source for the subsequent Posidonian 
interpretation, then, may have been something by one of 
those followers such as the work of Phanias (cf. Diogenes 
Laertius, vii, 41) or even the work by Eudorus that seems 
to have been his source for the interpretations given by 
Xenocrates and Crantor (see note c on 1012 © and note ¢ 
on 1013 B supra; cf. P. Merlan, Philologus, Ixxxix [1934], 
p. 211 and Helmer, De An. Proc., p. 17, n. 22). Such use 
of a secondary source, however, would not of itself prove that 
he did not know the original as well (cf. W. Crénert’s 
observation concerning Galen, Gnomon, vi [1930], p. 155). 

α 2,6. so interpreting τῆς ad περὶ τὰ σώματα γιγνομένης μερι- 
στῆς (οὐσίας) of Timaeus 35 a 2-3, which, contrary to Marie 
Laffranque’s assertion (op. cit., p. 379), is tantamount to 
saying that the following definition is ‘une glose posi- 
donienne du Timée,” though not that it stood in a “ com- 
mentary ἢ on the Timaeus. For the controversy about the 
existence of such a commentary see L. Edelstein, 4.J/.P., 
lvii (1936), p. 304, n. 72; E. Bickel, Rhein. Mus., N.F. ciii 
(1960), pp. 8-10; K. Abel, Rhein. Mus., N.F. νὴ (1964), 
pp. 371-373. 

> i.e. τὰ πέρατα, “the limits.” Merlan (Platonism to 
Neoplatonism, Ὁ. 38) calls this ‘‘ Plutarch’s somewhat care- 
less reference to ‘ the substance of the limits,’ ”’ 1.6. τὴν τῶν 
περάτων οὐσίαν, and insists that this phrase means “ that 
which is within the wépara,” “ the kind of being which * has ’ 
or ‘ accepts’ limits,’’ οὐσία itself being ‘ the πεπερασμένον 


218 


GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1023 


far from matter ; but, having taken divisible in the 
case of bodies to mean ¢ the being of the limits and 
having mixed these? with the intelligible, they de- 
clared the soul to be the idea of what is everyway 
extended,° herself constituted according to number 


without its limits,’’ that is, in fact, for a Stoic ὕλη. This 
cannot be what the phrase meant to Plutarch, however, any 
more than τῆς ψυχῆς . - . τὴν οὐσίαν a few lines below means 
“the kind of being that ἡ has’ or ‘ accepts’ soul,” for his 
first refutation of the Posidonians explicitly assumes that in 
their interpretation of the psychogony they use the limits 
themselves (τοῖς τῶν σωμάτων πέρασιν [1023 c infra)) and not 
any ‘‘ substance of the limits ’’ in Merlan’s sense, while at 
the beginning of the next chapter again (1023 p infra) the 
two constitutive factors of soul ascribed to them are the 
intelligible and the limits tout court (τοῖς πέρασι). Nor does 
this leave unexplained, as Merlan contends it would do, 
Plutarch’s imputation of “ materialism ”’ to the Posidonians, 
for it has already been said in reference to their interpretation 
(1014 p supra, page 187, note c) that the nature said in the 
Timaeus to become divisible in the case of bodies must not 
be held to be μήκη καὶ πλάτη. .. ἃ σώμασι προσήκει Kai 
σωμάτων μᾶλλον ἢ τῆς ψυχῆς ἐστιν. Whether Plutarch’s im- 
putation is justified is another question. He knew that 
according to the Stoics limits are incorporeal (De Comm. Not. 
1080 κε infra) but probably knew also that, while existing 
only in thought for the Stoics (S.V.F. ii, frag. 488), they 
exist in reality (καθ᾽ ὑπόστασιν) as well for Posidonius (Dio- 
genes Laertius, vii, 135); and, since according to the latter 
being that is κατὰ τὴν ὑπόστασιν differs from matter only in 
thought (Dow. Graeci, p. 458, 10-11), one might reasonably 
suppose that for him the limits, which exist in reality, must 
also be material. 

¢ So much of the definition is identical with that ascribed 
by [amblichus to Speusippus (frag. 40 {Lang]); in an 
obviously Stoic version it is ascribed to Plato himself 
(Diogenes Laertius, iii, 67: ἰδέαν τοῦ πάντῃ διεστῶτος πνεύματος 
{ef. ibid. vii, 157: soul is πνεῦμα ἔνθερμον for Posidonius et 
al.|); and the first word by itself, zdea, is the Posidonian 
definition in the list given by Macrobius (Jn Somnium 


219 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1023) νίαν' περιέχοντα" τά τε yap μαθηματικὰ τῶν πρώ- 
των νοητῶν μεταξὺ καὶ τῶν αἰσθητῶν τετάχθαι, 
τῆς τε ψυχῆς, τῶν νοητῶν τὸ ἀίδιον καὶ τῶν ᾿αἰσθη- 

C τῶν" τὸ παθητικὸν ἐ ἐχούσης, προσῆκον" ἐν μέσῳ τὴν 
οὐσίαν ὑπάρχειν. ἔλαθε γὰρ καὶ τούτους ὁ θεὸς 
τοῖς τῶν σωμάτων πέρασιν ὕστερον, ἀπειργασμέ- 


νῆς ἤδη τῆς ψυχῆς, χρώμενος ἐπὶ τὴν τῆς ὕλης 
διαμόρφωσιν, τὸ σκεδαστὸν αὐτῆς καὶ ἀσύνδετον 
ὁρίζων καὶ περιλαμβάνων ταῖς ἐκ τῶν τριγώνων 
waits μα ἈΘΉ ΕΟ ἐπιφανείαις. ἀτοπώτερον δὲ τὸ" 

1 ἁρμονίαν -B and Epitome 1080 F infra; α... νας. δ... 
av -Εἰ (ἁμαρτίαν εἶχε : ἁρμονίαν ἢ οὐσίαν -in margin); ἁμαρτίαν 
Fe other mss. 

2 αἰσθητῶν -E (τῶν over erasure), B; αἰσθητικῶν -all other 
MSS. 

8 προσῆκον -Mss. and Lpitome 1031 a infra (cf. Philo Jud., 
De Vita Mosis ii, ὃ 69=iv, p. 216, 18-19 [Cohn]) ; προσήκειν 
-Bernardakis (cf. 1022 pinfra). * rov-e, u, Escor. 72}. 


Scipionis | 1, xiv, 19). That Plutarch took ἐδέα to mean a 
Platonic “‘ idea’ is clear from his second refutation (1023 c 
infra: ἀτοπώτερον δὲ .. .) : but that it was not so meant is 
equally clear if, as he here reports, the soul according to 
the Posidonians has her being between the intelligibles and 
the perceptibles. The word is used in Timaeus 35 a 7 itself 
and not in the sense of *‘ idea ”’ (see 1012 c supra with note 
ὁ there), as Plutarch himself knew (see 1025 B infra: , 
τὸ πᾶν... τῆς ψυχῆς εἶδος) ;_ and that passage of the Timaeus 
whether directly or through Speusippus is the source of its 
use in the Posidonian definition, where, if the exegesis of 
Plato was meant to be Posidonian doctrine as well, the mean- 
ing intended was “ rational configuration ”’ (cf. Proclus, Jn 
Primum Euclidis El. Lib., Ὁ. 148, 8-21 [Friedlein] : .. TOV 
λόγον τοῦ σχήματος ...aitiov... τῆς περιοχῆς With L. Edel- 
stein, ASF, lil [ 1936], p. 303) of the tridimensional (for 
πάντῃ [cf Timaeus 36 © 2: πάντῃ διαπλακεῖσα] -- τριχῇ «7. 
Aristotle, De Caelo 268 a 7-10 and 24-28 with Simplicius, 
De Caelo, p. 9, 17-29 ; Philo Jud., De Opificio Mundi 36=1, 
p. 11, 9-10 [(Cohn]). As to the intention of Speusippus see 


220 


GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1023 


that embraces concord,* for (they said) the mathe- 
maticals have been ranked between the primary 
intelligibles and the perceptibles® and it is an 
appropriate thing for the soul likewise, possessing as 
she does the everlastingness of the intelligibles and 
the passivity of the perceptibles,* to have her being 
in the middle.“ In fact these people too failed to 
notice that only later, after the soul has already been 
produced, does god use the limits of the bodies for 
the shaping of matter*® by bounding and circum- 
scribing its dispersiveness and incoherence with the 
surfaces made of the triangles fitted together.f 


Cherniss, Aristotle’s Criticism of Plato ..., pp. 509-511 and 
The Riddle, pp. 73-74 with the rejoinder by Merlan, Platon- 
ism to Neoplatonism, pp. 40-48 and p. 56. 

¢ Cf. lamblichus, De Comm. Math. Scientia, Ὁ. 40, 15-23 
(Festa): ... κατ᾽ ἀριθμοὺς ἁρμονίαν περιέχοντας ὑφεστώσης 

. and Theolog. Arith., Ὁ. 30, 7-9 (De Falco) = Anatolius, 
p. 32, 21-22 (Heiberg)=Sextus, Adv. Math. iv, 8 (p. 723, 
17-20 [Bekker]). 

ὃ For this doctrine, which Aristotle ascribes to Plato by 
name in Metaphysics 987 b 14-18 and 1028 b 19-21, ef. 
Cherniss, The Riddle, pp. 75-78 and E. M. Manasse, 
Philosophische Rundschau, Beiheft 2 (1961), pp. 96-97 and 
pp. 149-156 ; see also note c on Plat. Quaest. 1002 a supra. 

¢ See note ὃ on 1013 a supra. 

4 Cf. Proclus, In Platonis Timaeum ii, Ὁ. 153, 18-19 
(Diehl) without reference, however, to the Posidonians or 
Speusippus: of μὲν μαθηματικὴν ποιοῦντες τὴν οὐσίαν τῆς ψυχῆς 
ὡς μέσην τῶν τε φυσικῶν καὶ τῶν ὑπερφυῶν. .. . 

¢ Timaeus 53 ὁ 4—56 B 6 (cf. 53 5 4: ... πρῶτον διε- 
σχηματίσατο . . .), the fabrication of the soul having been 
completed at 36 p 7 (cf. 36 p 8-9). For this argument of 
Plutarch’s see the end of the preceding chapter (1023 bn 
supra with note f on page 217). 

t See Plat. Quaest. 1001 B-c supra with note καὶ there ; 
and for τὸ σκεδαστόν See infra 1023 © (= Timaeus 37 a 5-6) 
and 1024 a (. . . φερομένης καὶ σκεδαννυμένης . . - ὕλης) and 
Plat. Quaest. 1001 pv supra with note ὁ there. 

221 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1023) τὴν ψυχὴν ἰδέαν ποιεῖν" ἡ μὲν γὰρ ἀεικίνητος" 
ἡ δ᾽ ἀκίνητος, καὶ ἡ μὲν ἀμιγὴς πρὸς τὸ αἰσθητὸν ἡ 7 
δὲ τῷ" σώματι συνειργμένη. πρὸς δὲ τούτοις ὁ θεὸς 
τῆς μὲν ἰδέας ὡς παραδείγματος γέγονε μιμητὴς 
τῆς δὲ ψυχῆς ὥσπερ ἀποτελέσματος δημιουργός. 

D ὅτι δ᾽ οὐδ᾽ ἀριθμὸν ὁ Πλάτων τὴν οὐσίαν τίθεται" 
τῆς ψυχῆς ἀλλὰ ταττομένην ὑπ᾽ ἀριθμοῦ, προεί- 


ρηται. 
38. Πρὸς δ᾽ ἀμφοτέρους τούτους κοινόν ἐστι τὸ 


μήτε, τοῖς πέρασι μήτε τοῖς ἀριθμοῖς μηδὲν | ἴχνος 
ἐνυπάρχειν ἐκείνης τῆς δυνάμεως ἧ τὸ αἰσθητὸν 


1 Wyttenbach from ρίξοηιο 1031 infra; εὐκίνητος 
-Μ88. 

2 τῷ -omitted by f, m, r 

3 τίθεται τὴν οὐσίαν -b. 


So ey ee ee oS ey EE 


¢ See 1013 ὁ supra with note b on page 174. 

> Cf. Timaeus 38 a 3 (τὸ δὲ ἀεὶ κατὰ ταὐτὰ ἔχον ἀκινήτως) 
and Aristotle, Topics 148 a 20-21 (ἀπαθεῖς yap καὶ ἀκίνητοι 

iMG COALS ate 

οἰ Cf. Symposium 211 ἘΞ 1-3(... εἰλικρινές, καθαρόν, a ἄμεικτον 

..), Phaedrus 247 ς 6-7, and Timaeus 52 ΑἹ -4(.. . οὔτε αὐτὸ 
εἰς ἄλλο ποι ἰόν, .. . ἀναίσθητον). The ideas are ἡ separate,” 
by which is meant TO ἀμιγὲς πάσης ὕλης καὶ μηδενὶ παθητῷ 
συμπεπλεγμένον (Dox. Graeci, p. 304 a 6-8 and B 27-31; ef. 
Olympiodorus, In Platonis ’Phaedonem, pp. 103, 25-104, 2 
| Norvin]). 

a Cf. συνέρξας in Timaeus 34 c 2, quoted in 1016 B supra, 
where the soul is mistress of the body, so that the verb here 
is not likely, as Thévenaz supposes (L’dme du Monde, 
p. 26, n. 121), to refer to the notion that the body is the 
prison of the soul, the less so since the envelopment of the 
corporeal by the worid-soul has just been emphasized by 
Plutarch (1023 a supra with note ὁ there). 

e Cf. Timaeus 28 a 6-B 2, 28 ὁ 6—29 a 6, 37 c 6-p 1, 
and 39 κε 3-7 with Plutarch, Quaest. Conviv. 720 B-c. 

f See 1014 ¢ and 1016 c supra and 1027 a infra, but 
222 


GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1023 


What is more absurd, however, is to make the soul 
an idea, for the former is perpetually in motion @ but 
the latter is immobile® and the latter cannot mix 
with the perceptible® but the former has been 
coupled with body ὁ; and, besides, god’s relation to 
the idea is that of imitator to pattern? but his 
relation to the soul is that of artificer to finished 
product.? As to number, however, it has been 
stated above 2 that Plato regards the substance of 
soul not as number either but as being ordered by 
number. 

23. It is an argument against both of these in 
common,” moreover, that neither in limits nor in 
numbers is there any trace of that faculty with which 
the soul naturally forms judgments of what is 


notice also Plat. Quaest. 1001 c (. .. οὐκ ἔργον ἐστὶ τοῦ θεοῦ 
μόνον ἀλλὰ καὶ μέρος .. .). 

9 In 1018 σὉ supra (see page 175, note c). By this 
reference Plutarch cannot mean, as both Helmer (De An. 
Proc., Ὁ. 18 [3]) and Thévenaz (L’ Ame du Monde, p. 67) 
think he must, that the earlier refutation of Xenocrates is 
somehow applicable to the Posidonian definition too, for, as 
Thévenaz himself remarks, κατ᾽ ἀριθμὸν συνεστῶσαν in this 
definition (1023 Β supra) corresponds to κατ᾽ ἀριθμὸν συνεστάναι 
(1013 p supra), which Plutarch used in refuting the Xeno- 
cratean identification of soul with number. He recurs to 
Xenocrates now because, as the Posidonian definition unlike 
the Xenocratean was obnoxious to the charge of materialism 
brought against others in the preceding chapter, so both the 
Xenocratean and the Posidonian are open to quite different 
objections about to be advanced in the subsequent chapter, 
where, as will be seen, the two interpretations are referred 
to as distinct despite the common defect imputed to them. 

δ i.e. the Posidonians and the Xenocrateans. Thévenaz 
(L’Ame du, Monde, p. 27, n. 124) adopts from the Epitome 
1031 b the erroneous reading ἀμφοτέροις τούτοις and so can- 
not account for κοινόν, which in his translation is omitted or 
disguised as “‘ il va dé soi.”’ 

923 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1023) ἡ ψυχὴ πέφυκε κρίνειν. νοῦν μὲν γὰρ αὐτῇ καὶ 
(τὸν νοητὸν" ἡ τῆς νοητῆς μέθεξις ἀρχῆς ἐμπε- 
ποίηκε᾽" δόξας δὲ καὶ πίστεις καὶ τὸ φανταστικὸν 
καὶ τὸ παθητικὸν" ὑπὸ“ τῶν περὶ τὸ σῶμα ποιοτή- 
των, τοῦτ᾽" οὐκ ἄν τις ἐκ μονάδων οὐδὲ γραμμῶν 
οὐδ᾽ ἐπιφανειῶν ἁπλῶς νοήσειεν ἐγγιγνόμενον. καὶ 
μὴν οὐ μόνον αἱ τῶν θνητῶν ψυχαὶ" γνωστικὴν τοῦ 
αἰσθητοῦ δύναμιν ἔχουσιν, ἀλλὰ καὶ τὴν τοῦ 

K κόσμου φησὶν" ἀνακυκλουμένην αὐτὴν πρὸς ἑαυτήν, 
ὅταν οὐσίαν ,“σκεδαστὴν ἔχοντός τινος ἐφάπτηται 
καὶ ὅταν ἀμέριστον, λέγειν" κινουμένην διὰ πάσης 
ἑαυτῆς, ὅτῳ ic av Tu” ταὐτὸν ἦ καὶ ὅτου τῶν 
ἕτερον, πρὸς ὃ τι τε μάλιστα καὶ ὅπῃ καὶ ὅπως" 
συμβαίνει κατὰ τὰ γιγνόμενα" πρὸς ἕκαστον 


1 «τὸ -added by H. C. 

2 mss. and Lpitome 1031 B infra; νοητικὸν -lurnebus ; 
νόησιν -Wyttenbach ; but cf. Plat. Quaest. 1002 © supra (τῆς 
ἐν ἡμῖν νοητῆς Kat νοερᾶς δυνάμεως) with note ὁ there. 
παθητὸν -E (with τ dotted and cross in margin), B. 
ὑπὲρ -Y. 
τοῦτ᾽ -H. C.; 6-mss.; [6] -deleted by Ditbner. 

ἡ τῶν θνητῶν ψυχὴ -e. 

7 αἰσθητοῦ -Turnebus (so ὠρτιέοιηε 1031 c); αἰσθητικοῦ 
-Μ88. 

8 φύσιν -B, ul. 

9 λέγειν -e, αι, Escor. 721; λέγῃ -E, B, f, m, r, Escor. 
7Qcorr. 

10 τι -Wyttenbach from Timaeus 37 a 7 (so Boer: in 
Epitome 1031 6) ; τις -Mss. 

11 7 ~Stephanus from Timaeus 37 a 7 (so Boot: in Epitome 
— )3 MSS. 

ὅτου παρ φακλξηίος from Timaeus 37 a 7 (so Ἔθοσες ah 

iipstorah 1031 c) ; ὅτῳ -Μ88. 

18 ὅπως «καὶ ὁπότεξ ~Pohlenz from Timaeus 37 8 1 (cf. quid 
quoque loco aut modo aut tempore -Turnebus). 

14 Dibner from Timaeus 37 B 23; xaraywopeva -MSS.; Kal 
τὰ γινόμενα -Epitome 1031 c. 


224 


a oO Pp ὦ 





GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1023 


perceptible. Intelligence and intelligibility have 
been produced in her by participation in the in- 
telligible principle ὃ ; but opinions and beliefs,° that 
is to say what is imaginative and impressionable by 
the qualities in body,¢ there is not anyone who could 
conceive of this arising in her simply from units or 
from lines or surfaces.¢ Now, not only do the souls 
of mortal beings have a faculty that is cognizant of 
the perceptible ; but he says? that the soul of the 
universe also as she is revolving upon herself, when- 
ever she touches anything that has being either 
dispersed or indivisible, is moved throughout herself 
and states of anything’s being the same and different 
with regard to whatever it is so precisely the respect 
and context and manner of its happening to be or to 
have as attribute (either of these) in relation to each 


@ Whereas this had been taken into account by Crantor 
and his followers, μάλιστα τῆς ψυχῆς ἴδιον ὑπολαμβάνοντες ἔργον 
εἶναι τὸ κρίνειν τά τε νοητὰ καὶ τὰ αἰσθητὰ. .. (1012 F supra 
with note c there on this use of κρίνειν). 

ὃ In the account of the Poamionian interpretation (1023 
B supra) this would be represented by ταῦτα τῷ νοητῷ μίξαν- 
res. With Plutarch’s expression here cf. τοῦ δὲ νοῦ μετέσχεν 
ἀπὸ τῆς κρείττονος ἀρχῆς ἐγγενομένου (1026 E infra [chap. 27 
sub δεν 

¢ Timaeus 37 Β 8 quoted in 1023 & infra. 

4 See 1024 a infra: τὴν δοξαστικὴν καὶ φανταστικὴν Kal 
συμπαθῆ τῷ αἰσθητῷ κίνησιν. 

¢ The ‘ units”’ and the “lines or surfaces’”’ here refer 
respectively to the “‘ numbers ”’ of the Xenocratean and the 
‘* limits ’’ of the Posidonian interpretations just above (see 
1014 p supra with notes ὃ and ὁ there). 

7 Timaeus 37 a ὅ-Β 3, from which Plutarch omits 
as irrelevant to his argument the καὶ πρὸς τὰ κατὰ ταὐτὰ 
ἔχοντα ἀεί (B 3) and so the τε after γιγνόμενα (B 2); but 
then he ought also to have omitted the xa! ὅταν ἀμέριστον in 
or A. 


225 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1023) (ἕκασταλ' εἶναι καὶ πάσχειν. ἐν τούτοις ἅμα καὶ 


4 


" 


1024 


τῶν δέκα κατηγοριῶν ποιούμενος ὑπογραφὴν ἔ ἔτι 
μᾶλλον τοῖς ἐφεξῆς διασαφεῖ. Ἢ “λόγος ᾿᾽ γάρ φησιν 

“ἀληθὴς ὅταν μὲν περὶ τὸ αἰσθητὸν γίγνηται καὶ 
6 τοῦ" θατέρου κύκλος ὀρθὸς" ἰὼν εἰς πᾶσαν αὐτοῦ 
τὴν ψυχὴν διαγγείλῃ, δόξαι καὶ πίστεις “γίγνονται 
βέβαιοι καὶ ἀληθεῖς" ὅταν δ᾽ αὖ περὶ τὸ λογιστι- 
Kov* ἢ καὶ ὁ τοῦ ταὐτοῦ" κύκλος εὔτροχος ὧν 
αὐτὰ μηνύσῃ, ἐπιστήμη" ἐξ ἀνάγκης ἀποτελεῖται" 
τούτω δ᾽ ἐν ᾧ τῶν ὄντων ἐγγίγνεσθον, ἐάν ποτέ 
τις αὐτὸ ἄλλο. πλὴν ψυχὴν προσείπῃ, πᾶν μᾶλλον 
ἢ τὸ ἀληθὲς ἐρεῖ. πόθεν οὖν ἔσχεν ἡ ψυχὴ τὴν 
ἀντιληπτικὴν τοῦ αἰσθητοῦ καὶ δοξαστικὴν ταύτην 
κίνησιν, ἑτέραν τῆς νοητικῆς" ἐκείνης καὶ τελευ- 
τώσης εἰς ἐπιστήμην, ἔργον εἰπεῖν μὴ θεμένους 
βεβαίως ὅτι νῦν οὐχ ἁπλῶς ψυχὴν ἀλλὰ κόσμου 
ψυχὴν συνίστησιν ἐξ ὑποκειμένων" τῆς τε κρείτ- 
τονος οὐσίας καὶ ἀμερίστου" καὶ τῆς" χείρονος, ἣν 

1 Added by Maurommates from Kpitome 1031 c and 


 Timaeus 37 B 2. 


τοῦ -omitted by Εἰ, B. 

ὀρθῶς -pcorr. 

λογικὸν -r. 

τοῦ αὐτοῦ -u. 

νοῦς ἐπιστήμη τε -Limaeus 37 c 2. 
τοῦτο -E, Bs τούτῳ -u, r, Aldine. 
νοητῆς -E_pitome 1031 p. 
ὑποκειμένης Epitome 1031 ῃὉ-Ἑ. 
Kal τῆς ἀμερίστου τ. 

11 τῆς -omitted by f, m, r, Aldine. 


Se co =F & Gi Bf Gob 


α Cf. Albinus, Epitome vi, 10 (p. 159, 34-35 [Hermann | = 
Ρ. 37, 1-2 [Louis]), where they are said to have been adum- 
brated by Plato in the Parmenides and elsewhere. A work 
by Plutarch entitled Διάλεξις περὶ τῶν δέκα κατηγοριῶν is 
No. 192 in the Catalogue of Lamprias. 


226 


GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1023-1024 


among the things that come to be. As in these 
words he is simultaneously giving an outline of the 
ten categories ¢ too, in those that follow he states the 
case more clearly still, for he says®: ‘* Whenever 
true discourse is concerning itself about the per- 
ceptible and the circle of difference running aright 
conveys the message through all its soul, there arise 
opinions and beliefs steadfast and true ; but, when- 
ever on the other hand it is concerned about the 
rational and the circle of sameness running smoothly 
gives the information, knowledge 5 is of necessity 
produced ; and, if anyone ever calls by another name 
than soul that one of existing things in which these 
two come to be, he will be speaking anything but the 
truth.”” Whence, then, did the soul get this motion 
that can apprehend what is perceptible and form 
opinions of it, a motion different from that which is 
intellective and issues in knowledge? It is difficult 
to say without steadfastly maintaining that in the 
present passage ὦ he is constructing not soul in the 
absolute sense but the soul of the universe out of 
entities already available, the superior, that is to say 
indivisible, being and the inferior, which he has 

> Timaeus 37 5 3-c 5, from which Plutarch omits δὲ ὁ 
κατὰ ταὐτόν in B 3-4 and γιγνόμενος . . . ἠχῆς in B 4-6 and 
reduces νοῦς ἐπιστήμη τε in C 2 to ἐπιστήμη. 

¢ By reducing Plato’s νοῦς ἐπιστήμη τε to ἐπιστήμη alone 
Plutarch suppresses the embarrassing fact that νοῦς ἀγέρα is 
clearly treated as a state of soul and not a transcendent 
entity made an ingredient of it (cf. Proclus, Jn Platonis 
Timaeum ii, pp. 313, 24-314, 5 [Diehl] and Cherniss, 
Aristotle's Criticism of Plato ..., p. 607). 

4 This is not the last two passages cited (Timaeus 37 a ὅ- 
Β 3 and B 3—c 5) but the central passage under discussion, 


Timaeus 35 a 1-8 4 (1012 B-c supra); for νῦν see note a 
on 1023 a supra. 


227 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1024) περὶ τὰ σώματα μεριστὴν. κέκληκεν, οὐχ ἑτέραν 


οὖσαν ἢ τὴν δοξαστικὴν καὶ φανταστικὴν καὶ συμ- 
παθῆ τῷ αἰσθητῷ, κίνησιν, οὐ γενομένην ἀλλὰ 
ὑφεστῶσαν ἀίδιον ὥσπερ ἡ ἑτέρα. τὸ γὰρ νοερὸν 
« v7 " 4 Ἁ \ > > 
ἡ φύσις ἔχουσα καὶ τὸ δοξαστικὸν εἶχεν ἀλλ 
ἐκεῖνο μὲν ἀκίνητον (καὶ) " ἀπαθὲς καὶ περὶ τὴν ἀεὶ 
μένουσαν ἱδρυμένον" οὐσίαν τοῦτο δὲ μεριστὸν καὶ 
πλανητόν, ἅτε δὴ φερομένης καὶ σκεδαννυμένης 
ἐφαπτόμενον ὕλης. οὔτε γὰρ τὸ αἰσθητὸν εἰλήχει 
τάξεως ἀλλ᾽ ἦν ἄμορφον καὶ ἀόριστον, 7 τε περὶ 
τοῦτο τεταγμένη δύναμις οὔτε δόξας" ἐνάρθρους" 
1 τῶν αἰσθητῶν -Hpitome 1031 Ἑ. 
2 <xai> -supplied by Miiller (1873) from E’pitome 1031 τ. 
3 ἱδρυμένην -u, Escor. 72}. 
4 δόξαν -u. 

> ἀνάρθρους -e, u, Escor. 72, Aldine. 

β τὰς supra 1015 αὶ with note 6 and 1014 b ees Ἢ 
there. 

> See supra page 209 with notes a to 6 and 1014 c referred 
to there. 

° ἡ φύσις (called “ wohl corrupt” by B. Miiller [1873] 
ad loc.) is used here to designate the precosmic state as it is 
in 1015 © supra (οὐδ᾽ ἀρχὰς τῇ φύσει . . . παρέσχεν, ἀλλ᾽ οὔσης 
ἐν πάθεσι - . .). 

ὦ 2,6. “ἴπε former ” just mentioned, the “ indivisible being ”’ 
of Timaeus 35 a 1-2; ef. 1024 τὺ infra, where νοῦς Ξε τῷ 
ἀμερίστῳ 2. καὶ τῷ μηδαμῇ κινητῷ. 

¢ See 1024 c infra: 6 δὲ νοῦς αὐτὸς μὲν . . - μόνιμος ἦν 
καὶ ἀκίνητος. Plato says nothing of the kind; but, since 
immobility and impassivity are characteristics of the in- 
telligible being of the ideas (see page 223 supra with note 4 
there), Plutarch, who identifies the indivisible being of the 
intelligibles (cf. Plat. Quaest. 1001 p supra: ἡ yap ἀμέριστος 
οὐσία... τῶν νοητῶν) With precosmic νοῦς (see the immediately 
preceding note), naturally ascribes to the latter these charac- 
teristics of the former (see 1016 c supra with note ὁ [τῆς 
μονίμου τε Kal ἀρίστης οὐσίας ἐκείνης] and 1026 a infra [τῷ 


228 


GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1024 


called divisible in the case of bodies,? this latter 
being none other than the opinionative and imagin- 
ative motion sensitive to what is perceptible, not 
brought into being but having subsisted everlastingly 
just like the former.’ For nature ¢ possessing intel- 
lectuality ὦ possessed the opinionative faculty also, 
the former, however, immobile ὁ (and) impassive / 
and settled about the being that always remains 
fixed 9 but the latter divisible and erratic inasmuch 
as it was in contact with matter, which was in motion 
and in dispersion.» The fact is that the perceptible 
had not got any portion of order but was amorphous 
and indefinite +; and the faculty stationed about this 
had neither articulate opinions nor motions that were 


περὶ τὰ νοητὰ povinw}). Since at the same time he regards 
god as the source of rationality in the soul (see supra 1016 ¢ 
with note d), he was perhaps not uninfluenced by the Aristo- 
telian notion of god as νοῦς ἀκίνητος, which is read into Plato 
by Albinus in Epitome x, 2 (p. 57, 5-9 [Louis]=p. 164, 20- 
24 [Hermann]). The νοῦς as πρῶτος θεός may have been 
called μόνιμος even by Xenocrates, since he identified it with 
the μονάς (frag. 15 [Heinze]; and for νοῦς -- μονὰς διὰ τὸ 
μόνιμον cf. Alexander, Metaph., p. 39, 14-15 and A. Delatte, 
Etudes sur la littérature pythagoricienne [Paris, 1915], p. 
167, 3-4). 

t See supra 1022 x, page 215, note a. 

9 Cf. 1024 pv infra (περὶ τὸ μένον ἀεί) and Plat. Quaest. 
1007 bv supra (τὸ vonrov... ἀεὶ μένειν). 

hk See supra 1023 c, note f and Plat. Quaest. 1001 pb, note 
ὃ with the references there. The combination of μεριστὸν καὶ 
πλανητόν here (the former referring to σκεδαννυμένης, the 
latter to φερομένης) recalls the identification as precosmic 
disorderly soul of both the divisible being and the necessity 
of the Timaeus (1014 p-£ supra), since the latter is called 
a πλανωμένη αἰτία (Timaeus 48 a 6-7). 

* For the confusion involved in speaking of ‘‘ the per- 
ceptible ’’ and of “‘ corporeality ’’ (just below) in this pre- 
cosmic state taken literally see page 184, note c supra. 


229 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1024) οὔτε κινήσεις ἁπάσας elye’ τεταγμένας ἀλλὰ τὰς 
πολλὰς ἐνυπνιώδεις καὶ παραφόρους καὶ ταρατ- 
τούσας τὸ σωματοειδές, ὅσα μὴ κατὰ τύχην τῷ 
βελτίονι περιέπιπτεν" ἐν μέσῳ γὰρ ἦν ἀμφοῖν καὶ 
πρὸς ἀμφότερα συμπαθῆ καὶ συγγενῆ φύσιν εἶχε, 
τῷ μὲν αἰσθητικῷ τῆς ὕλης ἀντεχομένη τῷ δὲ 
κριτικῷ τῶν νοητῶν. 

24, Οὕτω δέ πως καὶ αὐτὸς" διασαφεῖ τοῖς ὀνό- 
μασιν" “ οὗτος "γάρ φησι ‘ παρὰ τῆς ἐμῆς ψήφου 
λογισθεὶς ἐν κεφαλαίῳ δεδόσθω λόγος, ὄν τε καὶ 

C χώραν καὶ γένεσιν εἶναι τρία τριχῇ καὶ πρὶν οὐ- 
ρανὸν γενέσθαι. χώραν τε γὰρ καλεῖ τὴν ὕλην 

1 (in margin), B; ἔχουσα -all other mss., Aldine, 
Epitome 1031 κε. 

2 Τ]λάτων ~-Hpitome 1032 





« Cf. in 1026 x infra the period ἐν 7 τὸ μὲν φρόνιμον ... 
καταδαρθάνει . . . and De Facie 944 Ἐ-Ε, where the substance 
of soul from which νοῦς has been separated is said to retain 
ἴχνη τινὰ βίου καὶ ὀνείρατα. 


> See 1015 © supra (τὴν ὕλην... ὑπὸ τῆς ἀνοήτου ταρατ- 
τομένην αἰτίας) with note g there, 
¢ Cf. Timaeus 69 Β 6 (. .. οὔτε τούτων, ὅσον μὴ τύχῃ, τι 


μετεῖχεν ...), referring to the ἴχνη of Timaeus 53 8 quoted 
by Plutarch in 1016 EP supra. 

¢ The subject of ἐν μέσῳ ἦν as of the preceding περιέπιπτεν 
must be the precosmic disorderly soul, the δοξαστικὴ καὶ φαντα- 
στικὴ - - -- κίνησις identified by Plutarch with ἡ ἡ περὶ τὰ σώματα 
eae, οὐσία of Timaeus 35 a (see also 1024 ς infra : τὴν ἐν 
μεταβολαῖς καὶ κινήσεσιν οὐσίαν ... μεταξὺ τεταγμένην ... μεριστὴ 
προσηγορεύθη . . .), though in the Timaeus it is not this being 
that is ἐν μέσῳ ‘but rather that produced by. the demiurge 
between it and indivisible being to be the οὐσία that is an 
ingredient of soul. See the next note infra. 

“ Though τὸ κριτικόν can refer to the exercise of αἴσθησις 
as well as of νοῦς (see 1024 x infra with note 6 there), here 
it can mean only the latter, for it is explicitly distinguished 


230 


GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1024 


all orderly, but most of them were dreamlike ὦ and 
deranged and were disturbing corporeality ὃ save in so 
far as it would by chance encounter that which is the 
better,¢ for it was intermediate between the two 4 
and had a nature sensitive and akin to both, with its 
perceptivity laying hold on matter and with its 
discernment on the intelligibles.¢ | 

24. In terms that go something like this he states 
the case clearly himself, for he says 7: “‘ Let this be 
he account rendered in summation as reckoned from 
my calculation, that real existence and space and 
becoming were three and distinct” even before 
heaven came to be.’ Now, it is matter that he calls 


from τῷ αἰσθητικῷ and moreover κριτήριον τοῦ νοητοῦ μόνον ἐστὶν 
ὁ νοῦς (Plat. Quaest. 1002 ἢ supra). ‘Thus Plutarch’s precos- 
mic disorderly soul, though called ἀνόητος (1014 ὁ and 1015 Ἐ 
supra) and just distinguished (1024 a supra) as τὸ δοξαστικόν 
from the precosmic νοερόν, which comes to the former he 
maintains only by the action of god in the psychogony (see 
1016 c supra [τῷ αἰσθητικῷ τὸ νοερὸν .. . ad’ αὑτοῦ παρασχὼν 
.-]3 ef. 1026 & infra [τοῦ δὲ νοῦ μετέσχεν ἀπὸ τῆς κρείττονος 

ἀρχῆς ἐγγενομένου), is here given the intermediate position 
that properly belongs to the ** created ”’ soul (see the immedi- 
ately preceding note) and with it the faculty of νοῦς that it 
should not have at all until] after the psychogony. Similarly 
it is said in the next chapter (1024 c infra) to disperse in this 
world the semblances of the intelligible ideas, which in its 
context shows that the attempt to interpret literally the 
“ἢ precosmic chaos ”’ of Timaeus 52 p—53 B was what con- 
strained Plutarch here to contradict his own literal interpre- 
tation of the psychogony by ascribing to his precosmic dis- 
orderly soul characteristics proper according to his own 
account only to the “ὁ created ”’ soul. 

7 Cf. P. Shorey, Class. Phil., xvii (1922), pp. 261-262 on 
Euthydemus 304 Ἑ. 

σ Timaeus 52 Ὁ 2-4. 

λ Cf. Proclus, In Platonis Timaeum i, Ὁ. 358, 11-12 
(Diehl): ὅταν λέγῃ τρία ταῦτα εἶναι χωρίς... .. 


231 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


σ Ὁ » Ψ \ 
(1024) womep ἕδραν ἔστιν ὅτε καὶ ὑποδοχήν, dv δὲ τὸ 
/ ’ \ a ,ὔ v4 
vonTov, γένεσιν δὲ τοῦ κόσμου μήπω γεγονότος 
3 Υ Μ aN \ 2 - 
οὐδεμίαν ἄλλην ἢ τὴν ἐν μεταβολαῖς καὶ κινήσεσιν 
οὐσίαν, τοῦ τυποῦντος καὶ τοῦ τυπουμένου μεταξὺ 
τεταγμένην, διαδιδοῦσαν' ἐνταῦθα τὰς ἐκεῖθεν εἰ- 
’ / ἃ “A : \ , 
Kovas. διά τε δὴ ταῦτα μεριστὴ προσηγορεύθη 
ἌΝ ~ 3 ~ A > / \ ~ 
καὶ ὅτι τῷ αἰσθητῷ τὸ αἰσθανόμενον καὶ TH φαν- 
ἴω \ / 3 ᾿ 4 / 
ταστῷ τὸ φανταζόμενον ἀνάγκη συνδιὰνέμεσθαι 
\ , € A > ἊΝ , 0 7 
Kal συμπαρήκειν' ἡ yap αἰσθητικὴ κίνησις, ἰδία 
ψυχῆς οὖσα, κινεῖται πρὸς τὸ αἰσθητὸν ἐκτός" ὁ δὲ 
ἜΝ mits 1 979 € A2 , s TT Te. 
νοῦς αὐτὸς μὲν ἐφ᾽ ἑαυτοῦ" μόνιμος ἦν Kat ἀκίνητος, 


1 διαδοῦσαν -Τ. 
2, Bee, us ἀφ᾽ ἑαυτοῦ -f, m, r, Kscor. 72, Aldine. 


α See note ¢ on page 184 supra. 

> Cf. Timaeus 52 a 1-4 with c ὅτ 1, 48 & 5-6, 27 p 6— 
2BA 4. 

¢ Taking Timaeus 52 p—53 B literally, Plutarch had to 
identify the precosmic soul that he posited with one of the 
three alone there named as being “‘ before heaven came to 
be.” Of these there remained to him only γένεσις. and he 
may even have thought this identification supported by 
ψυχὴν . . . τὴν πρώτην γένεσιν Of Laws 896 a 5-3 1 and 899 ὁ 
6-7 (see 1013 F supra with note a there). Yet he must have 
understood that γένεσις in the Timaeus is not an entity 
transmitting to this world or dispersing in it the semblances 
of the other but is itself τὰ γιγνόμενα, the “ offspring” of 
the intelligible and the receptacle and only in this sense 
something “‘ between’? them (cf. Timaeus 50 c ὕ- 4), for 
this is the conception that he elsewhere himself ascribes to 
Plato (De Iside 373 π [ὁ μὲν οὖν Πλάτων τὸ μὲν νοητὸν . .. 
πατέρα, τὴν δὲ ὕλην καὶ μητέρα... καὶ χώραν γενέσεως, τὸ δ᾽ 


232 


GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1024 


space, as he sometimes calls it abode and receptacle,¢ 
and the intelligible that he calls real existence ὃ ; and 
what he calls becoming, the universe not yet having 
come to be, is nothing other than that being involved 
in changes and motions which, ranged between what 
makes impressions and what receives them, disperses 
in this world the semblances from that world yonder. ° 
lor this very reason it was called divisible ὦ and also 
because it is necessary for that which is perceiving and 
that which is forming mental images to be divided in 
correspondence with what is perceptible and with 
what is imaginable and to be coextensive with them,? 
for the motion of sense-perception, which is the 
500} 5 own,f moves towards what is perceptible with- 
out 9 but the intelligence, while it was abiding and 
immobile all by itself,” upon having got into the soul 


ἐξ ἀμφοῖν ἔκγονον καὶ γένεσιν ὀνομάζειν εἴωθεν] and 372 F [εἰκὼν 
γάρ ἐστιν οὐσίας ἐν ὕλῃ γένεσις .. .]). In any case, Plutarch’s 
precosmic soul, here identified with γένεσις, is irrational ; and 
his giving it access to the intelligible world is an inconsist- 
ency resulting from his attempt to account for the “‘ traces ”’ 
and “ modifications ’’ in the chaos of Timaeus 52 p—53 Β as 
literally precosmic (see note 6 on 1024 8 supra). 

4 i.e. Timaeus 35 a, where, however, the μεριστὴ οὐσία 
is explicitly not μεταξὺ τεταγμένη (See note ὦ on 1024 B 
supra). 

¢ See 1024 a supra (μεριστὸν . .. ἅτε . . . σκεδαννυμένης 
ἐφαπτόμενον ὕλης) and cf. Simplicius, De An., p. 45, 8-10 ; 
for the term συμπαρήκειν cf. Boethus in Simplicius, Categ., 
p. 434, 3-4. 

f Because τὴν . . - συμπαθῆ τῷ αἰσθητῷ κίνησιν iS ἁπλῶς 
ψυχή (1024 a supra; cf. ψυχὴ καθ᾽ ἑαυτήν in 1014 Ὁ-Ὲ supra). 

σ Cf. [Plutarch], De Placitis 899 r= Dox. Graeci, p. 394 a 
15-20; Porphyry, Sententiae xliii (pp. 41, 24-42, 1 and 42, 
13-14 [Mommert])=Stobaeus, Eel. i, 48, 5 (pp 313, 15-17 
and 314, 5-7 [Wachsmuth]). 

» See note ὁ on 1024 a supra. 


233 


(1024) 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


) ἐγγενόμενος δὲ τῇ ψυχῆ καὶ κρατήσας εἰς ἑαυτὸν 
ἐπιστρέφει καὶ συμπεραίνει τὴν ἐγκύκλιον φορὰν 
περὶ τὸ μένον ἀεὶ μάλιστα ψαύουσαν τοῦ ὄντος. 
διὸ καὶ δυσανάκρατος ἡ κοινωνία γέγονεν αὐτῶν, 
τῷ ἀμερίστῳ τὸ μεριστὸν καὶ τῷ μηδαμῇ κινη- 
τῷ" τὸ πάντῃ φορητὸν μιγνύουσα καὶ καταβιαζο- 
μένη" θάτερον εἰς ταὐτὸν" συνελθεῖν. ἦν δὲ τὸ 
θάτερον οὐ κίνησις," ὥσπερ οὐδὲ ταὐτὸνἷ στάσις, 
ἀλλ᾽ ἀρχὴ διαφορᾶς καὶ ἀνομοιότητος. ἑκάτερον 
γὰρ ἀπὸ τῆς ἑτέρας ἀρχῆς κάτεισι, τὸ μὲν ταὐτὸν 
ἀπὸ τοῦ ἑνὸς τὸ δὲ θάτερον" ἀπὸ τῆς δυάδος" καὶ 
μέμικται πρῶτον ἐνταῦθα περὶ τὴν ψυχήν, ἀριθ- 


K pots καὶ λόγοις συνδεθέντα καὶ μεσότησιν ἐναρμο- 


1 τὸ μὲν ἀεὶ -U; τὸ ἀεὶ -f. 2 τὸν -e, u, Escor. 721, 
3 κινητὸν -F. 

Ξ καταβιβαζομένη ἡ 

ὅ ταὐτὸ -ii}, Β1 (ν superscript -E}, B4), r. 

6 


ἦν δὲ τὸ θάτερον ov κίνησις “margin of Εἰ (τὸ omitted) and 
of im‘; Epitome 1032 c; ἦν δὲ τὸ ἕτερον κίνησις -E (οὐκ ἦν in 
margin -E}, ἡ superscript between ν and «x -E? )3 οὐκ (two 


_ dots over ce ἦν δὲ TO ἕτερον ue κίνησις -Β ; ἦν δὲ τὸ θάτερον ἡ 


κίνησις -e, u, f, m, T, Escor. 72 » Aldine. 
? ὥσπερ δὲ ταὐτὸν (ὥσπερ δὲ οὐ ταὐτὸν in margin) -f, τὰ : 
ὥσπερ, δὴ ταὐτὸν (οὐ ταὐτὸν in margin) -r. 
τὸ δὲ ἕτερον -E, Β (θάτερον in margin -B?). 


«866 Plat. Quaest. 1003 a with note ὁ there for κρατήσασα 

. ἐπέστρεψεν used of the rational soul’s action upon the 
motions of matter. Similar language to describe the influ- 
ence of god upon the world-soul and its νοῦς is used by 
Albinus in Epitome x, 3 and xiv, 3 (pp. 59, 5-7 and 81, 4-9 
[Louis}=pp. 165, 1-3 and 169, 30-35 [Hermann]}), with 
which cf. also Chalcidius, Platonis Timaeus, Ὁ. 226, 8-9 
(Wrobel)=p. 205, 1-2 (Waszink). 

> Cf. Proclus, In Primum Euclidis El. Lib., p. 147, 15-18 
(Friedlein). For περὶ TO μένον ἀεὶ see 1024 a, ‘note g supra, 
and for the ‘ circular motion ᾽ see Plat. Quaest. 1004 c 
with note d there. 


234 











GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1024 


and taken control makes her turn around to him 4 
and with her accomplishes about that which always 
remains fixed the circular motion most closely in 
contact with real existence.? This is also why the 
union of them proved to be a difficult fusion, being a 
mixing of the divisible with the indivisible ὁ and of 
the altogether transient with the utterly immobile 
and a constraining of difference to unite with same- 
ness. Difference is not motion, however, as same- 
ness is not rest either,4 but the principle of dif- 
ferentiation and dissimilitude.? In fact, each of the 
two derives from another of two principles, sameness 
from the one and difference from the dyad‘; and it 
is first here in the soul that they have been com- 
mingled, bound together by numbers and ratios and 


¢ In Timaeus 35 a (see 1012 c supra) δύσμικτον is used 
not of the “‘ divisible ’’ or the “‘ indivisible’ but of “ differ- 
ence ’’ alone, and this Plutarch himself later emphasizes and 
defends just after having distinguished the “ divisible ” and 
the “indivisible”? from “ difference’? and ‘“ sameness ” 
(1025 5-Ὁ infra). 

4 See supra 1013 Ὁ with notes f and g there; ἦν here is 
the *‘ philosophical imperfect.” 

¢ Cf. 1025 c infra (τὸ μὲν ταὐτὸν ἰδέα τῶν ὡσαύτως ἐχόντων 
ἐστὶ τὸ δὲ θάτερον τῶν διαφόρως ... .) and De Defectu Orac. 428 c 
(ἡ τοῦ ἑτέρου δύναμις . . . ἐνείργασται . . . τὰς . - - ἀνομοιότητας). 

7 Cf. Nicomachus, Arithmetica Introductio τι, xvii, 1 
(p. 109, 2-6 [Hoche]) and on this passage Philoponus, 
B, ve, lines 12-15 (Hoche) and Asclepius, 1, in, lines 17-19 
(Taran); Moderatus in Porphyry, Vita Pythagorae, 49-50 
(p. 44, 8-18 [Nauck]); Plutarch, De Garrulitate 507 a 
(ἡ δὲ δυὰς ἀρχὴ διαφορᾶς ἀόριστος). With the derivation from 
these principles introduced here and reflected in the reference 
to “ dyadic ” and “‘ monadic ” parts in 1025 pb infra Plu- 
tarch comes near to giving soul an arithmetical character 
not unlike that to which he objects in the Xenocratean inter- 
pretation (1013 c-p and 1023 c-p [chap. 22 sub finem] supra). 
See similarly note 6 on 1025 a infra. 

235 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1024) vious, καὶ ποιεῖ" θάτερον μὲν ἐγγενόμενον τῷ ταὐτῷ 


διαφορὰν τὸ δὲ ταὐτὸν ἐν τῷ ἑτέρῳ τάξιν, ὡς δῆ- 
λόν ἐστιν ἐν ταῖς πρώταις τῆς ψυχῆς δυνάμεσιν' εἰσὶ 
δὲ αὗται τὸ κριτικὸν καὶ τὸ κινητικόν." 7 μὲν οὖν 
κίνησις εὐθὺς ἐπιδείκνυται περὶ τὸν οὐρανὸν ἐν 
μὲν" τῇ ταὐτότητι τὴν ἑτερότητα τῇ περιφορᾷ τῶν 
ἀπλανῶν" ἐν δὲ τῇ ἑτερότητι τὴν ταὐτότητα τῇ τάξει 
τῶν πλανήτων". ἐπικρατεῖ γὰρ ἐν ἐκείνοις τὸ ταὐ- 
τὸν ἐν δὲ τοῖς περὶ γῆν τοὐναντίον. ἡ δὲ κρίσις" 
ἀρχὰς μὲν ἔχει δύο, τόν τε νοῦν ἀπὸ τοῦ ταὐτοῦ 
πρὸς τὰ καθόλου καὶ τὴν αἴσθησιν ἀπὸ τοῦ ἑτέρου 
πρὸς τὰ καθ᾽ τάδ HGH de λόγος ἐξ ap- 

1 ποῖ -Y. 2 κινητόν -U. ev δὲ -f, m, r, Aldine. 


4 ἀπλανῶν -Mss.; under this iis πλανητῶν -E}, and in 
margin as correction -B?. 


5 τῶν πλανήτων -Epitome 1032 Ὁ: trav... vac.6... -E, 
B; τῶν ἀπλανῶν -e, u, Escor. 72, Aldine; τῶν A et i 
-f, τὴ, r. 6 κίνησις -u, Aldine. 


? τοῦ -E! (added superscript), B, Epitome 1032 pb; 
omitted by all other mss. and Aldine. 


α Not ‘‘ harmonic,” for which Plutarch uses the regular 
technical expression, ἁρμονικὴ μεσότης, and which he knows 
is only one of the two means used in Timaeus 36 a (see 
.. 1019 p and 1028 a infra) ; see page 175 supra with note c 
there on ἀριθμῷ καὶ λόγῳ καὶ ἁρμονίᾳ. 

ὃ Cf. 1025 τ and 1027 a (τῇ δὲ ταὐτοῦ καὶ τῇ ἑτέρου δυνάμει 
τάξιν. .. καὶ διαφορὰν... .) infra ; and for another use 
of the distinction between difference in sameness and same- 
ness in difference cf. Porphyry, Sententiae xxxvi and xxxvii 
(p. 31, 1-9 and pp. 32, 15-33, 8 [Mommert]) and Marius 
Victorinus, Adv. Arium i, 48, 22-28 (Henry-Hadot). 

¢ Cf. Aristotle, De Anima 432 a 15-17. 

4 Cf. De Virtute Morali 441 Ἐ-τ. In Timaeus 36 c 4-Ὁ 7 
the single and undivided outer revolution, into which all the 
“ fixed stars’ are set (40 a 2-8 6), is called the motion of 
sameness; and the inner revolution of seven circles, un- 
equal and with speeds different but rationally related (and 


236 





GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1024 


harmonious means,* and that difference come to be 
in sameness produces differentiation but sameness in 
difference order,? as is clear in the case of the soul’s 
primary faculties. These are the faculties of discern- 
ment and motivity.¢ Now, directly in the heaven 
motion exhibits diversity in identity by the revolution 
of the fixed stars and identity in diversity by the 
order of the planets, for in the former sameness pre- 
dominates but its opposite in the things about the 
earth.? Discernment, however, has two principles,’ 
intelligence proceeding from sameness to universals 
and sense-perception from difference to particulars‘ ; 


so “‘ ordered ”’), into each of which one of the planets is set 
(38 c 7-Ὁ 1), is called the motion of difference. All these 
circles, however, are homogeneous in constitution (35 B 1-3 
and 36 B 5—-c 4); and their designations are not meant to 
distinguish as their respective constituents the sameness and 
difference that were ingredients in the blending of soul (so 
apparently “‘ Timaeus Locrus”’ 96 c [. . . τάπερ aifépia... 
τὰ μὲν Tas ταὐτῶ φύσιος εἶμεν τὰ δὲ τᾶς τῶ ἑτέρω.}) or to 
indicate any predominance of one or the other of the latter 
in each of the two revolutions such as Plutarch here assumes 
and for which even Proclus tries to account though re- 
cognizing that the constitution of the two revolutions is 
homogeneous (Jn Platonis Timaeum ii, pp. 253, 23-255, 
8 and p. 255, 13-16 [Diehl]). 

e Cf. Aristotle, De Anima 432 a 16 (. .. τῷ τε κριτικῷ [See 
note ὁ supra] ὃ διανοίας ἔργον ἐστὶ καὶ αἰσθήσεως) and see supra 
1012 ¥, note c and 1023 pb, note ἃ on κρίνειν. With ἀρχὰς... 
δύο here cf. Albinus, Epitome iv, 4 (p. 13, 14-15 [Louis]=p. 
154, 28-29 [Hermann]). 

! Cf. Timaeus 37 8 6—c 3 (1023 Ἐ-Ὸ supra), where from 
the reports of the circle of sameness concerning the rational 
and of the circle of difference concerning the perceptible 
arise respectively knowledge and opinion; but the char- 
acters of these circles Plutarch here, as in the preceding 
sentence (see note ὦ supra), equates with the sameness and 
difference that are ingredients of soul, Jor universals as 


237 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1024) pot, νόησις ἐν τοῖς νοητοῖς καὶ δόξα γιγνόμενος ἐν 


1025 


" ἢ θ Maki Wiese V1 , 
τοῖς αἰσθητοῖς ὀργάνοις τε μεταξὺ φαντασίαις τε 
A , 2 , e \ \ > ~ A 
καὶ μνήμαις" χρώμενος, WY τὰ μὲν EV TH ταὐτῷ 
δι : ἐν Ἁ ϑυνϑ δ ὡς δ ἐνῷ ~ A 3 ’ » 
τὸ ἕτερον τὰ δ᾽ ἐν τῷ ἑτέρῳ ποιεῖ τὸ ταὐτόν. ἔστι 
A ἐ 4 “- - 
γὰρ ἡ μὲν νόησις κίνησις τοῦ νοοῦντος περὶ τὸ 
/ ς \ / \ “A > a εἰ \ 
μένον, ἡ δὲ δόξα μονὴ τοῦ αἰσθανομένου περὶ τὸ 
Φ / \ A / A 
κινούμενον. φαντασίαν δὲ συμπλοκὴν δόξης πρὸς 
wv > e > 4 \ 5 \ \ Α 
αἴσθησιν οὖσαν ἵστησιν ἐν μνήμῃ τὸ ταὐτὸν τὸ δὲ 


1 τε καὶ μεταξὺ -Aldine; τε ταῖς μεταξὺ -Stephanus. 
2 γνώμαις -Y. 


the objects of knowledge or intelligence contrasted to par- 
ticulars as the objects of sense-perception see 1025 © infra 
(... νοεῖν μὲν ἐκεῖνα ταῦτα δ᾽ αἰσθάνεσθαι ...) and cf. Aristotle, 
De Anima 417 Ὁ 22-23 and Physics 189 a 5-8: Areius 
Didymus, Hpitomes Frag. Phys. 16 (Dox. Graeci, Ὁ. 456, 
9-12); Proclus, In Primum Euclidis El, Lib., p. 30, 11-15 
(Friedlein). 

α i.e. the λόγος of Timaeus 37 8 3 (ratio in Cicero, Timaeus 
28, p. 177, 2 [Plasberg] and motus rationabilis in Chalcidius, 
Platonis Timaeus, p. 172, 11 and 19-21 [Wrobel]=p. 153, 


16 and 23-25 [Waszink]), which there, however, means 


δ" discourse’? (see 1023 © supra) but discourse which is 
articulate thought (cf. Theaetetus 189 © 6-7 and Sophist 
263 πὶ 3-6). 

> Of. Proclus, In Platonis Timaeum i, p. 255, 2-24 and 
ii, p. 299, 16-24 (Diehl); and cf. also the διττὸς λόγος of 
Albinus, Hpitome iv, 3 (p. 18, 8-11 [Louis]=p. 154, 22-25 
{Hermann]) with the duplex virtus of the rational part of the 
soul in Chalcidius, Platonis Timaeus, p. 198, 22-26 (Wrobel) 
=p. 177, 14-17 (Waszink). 

ὁ For the connexion of μνήμη and φαντασία cf. Aristotle, 
De Memoria 450 a 22-25 and 451 a 14-17; with ὀργάνοις cf. 
Plutarch, frag. xv (vii, p. 111, 12-14 [Bernardakis])=frag. 
23, 9-11 (Sandbach) and Adv. Colotem 1119 a (τὰ δὲ λοιπὰ 


238 


GENERATION OF THE SOUT, 1024-1025 


and reason @ is a blend of both, becoming intellection 
in the case of the intelligibles and opinion in the case 
of the perceptibles ® and employing between them 
mental images and memories as instruments,’ of 
which the former are produced by difference in same- 
ness and the latter by sameness in difference. For 
intellection is motion of what is cognizing about what 
remains fixed,? and opinion fixity of what is per- 
ceiving about what is in motion’; but mental 
imagining, which is a combination of opinion with 
sense-perception,’ is brought to a stop in memory 


. . . ὄργανα τῆς τούτου δυνάμεως) : and with μεταξύ cf. 
Plotinus, /nn. tv, iv, 13, line 18 and Proclus, In Primum 
Kuclidis Εἰ. Lib., Ὁ. 52, 10-21 (Friedlein). 

4 The antecedent of ὧν τὰ pev... τὰ δ᾽ is not, as Thévenaz 
thought (L’ Ame du Monde, pp. 29 and 81), rots νοητοῖς... 
τοῖς αἰσθητοῖς but φαντασίαις τε καὶ μνήμαις treated as neuter 
because οὗ ὀργάνοις. Their dependence upon difference and 
sameness is explained in the second half of the next sentence, 
as was that of νοῦς and αἴσθησις in the preceding one (page 
937, note f). The whole of this exposition has to do with the 
réles of sameness and difference not in the existence of in- 
telligibles and perceptibles but in the constitution of the 
soul’s faculties (see 1024 © supra). 

¢ See 1024 p supra with note ὁ there; and cf. Aristotle, 
De Anima 407 a 20-22 (on the Timaeus): νοῦ μὲν yap κίνησις 
νόησις. «ἢ. 

7 Contrast τὸ δοξαστικὸν . . . πλανητόν, ἅτε δὴ φερομένης . .. 
ἐφαπτόμενον ὕλης (1024 a supra) and τῷ αἰσθητῷ τὸ αἰσθανόμενον 
... ἀνάγκη . .. συμπαρήκειν (1024 c supra) ; but of. δόξαι... 
βέβαιοι of Timaeus 37 B 8 (1023 © supra) and the interpre- 
tation by Proclus, In Platonis Timaeum ii, p. 310, 5-10 (Diehl). 

9 Cf. Aristotle, De Anima 428 a 25-26 (οὐδὲ συμπλοκὴ 
δόξης καὶ αἰσθήσεως) against Plato, Sophist 264 B 1-2 (σύμμειξις 
αἰσθήσεως καὶ δόξης), where δόξα means “ἡ judgment,’’ how- 
ever, διανοίας ἀποτελεύτησις:, in distinction from its meaning in 
Timaeus 37 Β 8 (cf. Proclus, In Platonis Rem Publicam i, pp. 
262, 25-263, 8 [Kroll}). 


239 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1025) θάτερον' κινεῖ πάλιν ἐν διαφορᾷ" τοῦ πρόσθεν καὶ 


νῦν, ἑτερότητος ἅμα καὶ ταὐτότητος ἐφαπτομέ- 
vy. 

25. Δεῖ δὲ τὴν περὶ τὸ σῶμα τοῦ κόσμου γενο- 
μένην σύντη ξιν'" εἰκόνα λαβεῖν τῆς ἀναλογίας ἐν ἢ 
διηρμόσατο" ψυχήν." ἐκεῖ μὲν γὰρ ἦν ἄκρα TO’ πῦρ 
καὶ ἡ" γῆ, χαλεπὴν" πρὸς “ἄλληλα κραθῆναι φύσιν 
ἔχοντα μᾶλλον δὲ ὅλως ἄκρατον καὶ ἀσύστατον' 
ὅθεν ἐν μέσῳ θέμενος αὐτῶν τὸν μὲν ἀέρα πρὸ τοῦ 
πυρὸς τὸ δὲ ὕδωρ πρὸ τῆς γῆς, ταῦτα πρῶτον ἀλ- 
λήλοις ἐκέρασεν. εἶτα διὰ τούτων ἐκεῖνα πρός τε 
ταῦτα καὶ πρὸς" " ἄλληλα συνέμιξε καὶ συνήρμοσεν. 
ἐνταῦθα δὲ πάλιν τὸ ταὐτὸν καὶ τὸ θάτερον, ἐναν- 


1 τὸ δὲ ἕτερον -Ε, Β. ἐκ διαφορᾶς -U. 
3. ἐφαπτομένην -B. Miiller (1873) ; i -MSS. 

᾿ σύνταξιν -r, Epitome 1032 Ἐπ. 5 διηρμήσατο -e, U. 
6 


«τὴν» ψυχήν -Bernardakis (vi, p. 531: Addenda) from 
ΕΘΗ 1032 E. 
7 ἄκρα τὸ -Wyttenbach from Epitome 1039 Ἑ: ἄκρατον 
-MSS, 8 ἡ -omitted by f. 9. χαλεπὸν -r. 
i πρὸς ΣΝ ΕΣ κὶ in Epitome 1032 x. 
11 τὸ ἕτερον -Ἐὶ, B. 


“ Cf. Aristotle, De Memoria 451 a 14-16 (μνήμη. 
φαντάσματος ... ἕξις ) and 450 a 27—b 11 with Themistius 
(Sophonias), Parva Nat., P. 5, 13 ad loc. (μνήμη δ᾽ ἐστὶν ἡ 
ταύτης 150]. φαντασίας] μονὴ καὶ σωτηρία). For μνήμη referred 
to μονή ef. Plato, Cratylus 437 B 3 and the note on the Stoic 
definition i in De Comm. Not. 1085 a infra, μνήμας δὲ μονίμους 
kat σχετικὰς τυπώσεις (= φαντασίας). 

> As Thévenaz observed (D’ Ame du Monde, p p.: 82), 
ἵστησιν ... τὸ ταὐτὸν τὸ δὲ θάτερον κινεῖ (cf. τῇ ἑτέρου δυνάμει 

. μεταβολὴν . .. in 1027 a infra) asserts what Plutarch 
criticized Xenocrates for asserting (see supra page 167, 
note a and 1013 Ὁ with notes fand g). For a similar incon- 
sistency see note f on 1024 ἢ supra. 

¢ Cf. Aristotle, De Memoria 449 b 22-30, 450 a 19-22, 


240 





GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1025 


by sameness? and by difference again set moving? 
in the distinction of past and present,° as it is in 
contact with diversity and identity at once. 

25. The fusion ὦ that was carried out in the case of 
the body of the universe must be taken as a likeness 
of the proportion with which he ὁ regulated soul. In 
the former case, because there were extremes, fire 
and earth, of a nature difficult to blend together or 
rather utterly immiscible and incohesive, he accord- 
ingly put between them air in front of the fire and 
water in front of the earth and blended these with 
each other first and then by means of these com- 
mingled and conjoined those extremes with them and 
with each other.f And in the latter case again he 


and 452 Ὁ 28-29; and the Stoic definition of memory men- 
tioned by Plutarch, De Sollertia Animalium 961 c. 

ἃ For the noun σύντηξις in this sense cf. Proclus (com- 
menting on Timaeus 43 a 3), In Platonis Timaeum iii, p. 321, 
14-19 and p. 323, 9-12 (Diehl), where the erroneous variant 
σύνταξ- appears in some ss. also. 

ὁ 4,6. god, the demiurge; cf. ἐν μέσῳ θέμενος in the next 
sentence infra with ὁ θεὸς ἐν μέσῳ θείς of Timaeus 32 πὶ 4. 

7 Timaeus 32 8 3-7. The“ blending ᾽᾿ and “ mingling ”’ of 
Plutarch’s interpretation here (cf. also De Fortuna Romano- 
rum 316 ἘΓῈ and the role assigned to air between fire 
and water in De Primo Frigido 951 p-£) are entirely ab- 
sent from Timaeus 31 B 4—32 c 4; and the reason given 
there for inserting two means between the extremes of fire 
and earth is purely mathematical (see 1016 r—1017 a supra), 
as it remains in “'Timaeus Locrus” 99 a-s and Albinus, 
Epitome xii, 2 (pp. 69, 14-71, 4 [Louis]=p. 167, 25-32 
[Hermann]). For other “ physical” interpretations cf. 
Theon Smyrnaeus, Ὁ. 97, 8-12 (Hiller); Macrobius, Jn 
Somnium Scipionis 1, vi, 23-34 (n.b. permiscert in 24) ; 
Chalcidius, Platonis Timaeus, pp. 86, 10-88, 7 (Wrobel)= 
pp. 71, 24-73, 4 (Waszink); Proclus, /n Platonis Timaeum 
ii, pp. 39, 14-42, 2 (Diehl); Philoponus, De Aeternitate 
Mundi xiii, 13 (pp. 514, 24-516, 23 [Rabe]) and In Nico- 


241 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


’ , y 3 , 9 4 
(1025) τίας δυνάμεις καὶ ἀκρότητας ἀντιπάλους, συνήγα- 
: 5 \ Scie Stee , es 
γεν ov διὰ αὑτῶν,᾽ ἀλλ᾽ οὐσίας ἑτέρας μεταξύ, τὴν 
\ > / A “. lon A “- 
μὲν ἀμέριστον πρὸ τοῦ ταὐτοῦ" πρὸ δὲ τοῦ θατέ- 
\ # 3 ex 
ρου" τὴν μεριστήν, ἔστιν ἧ προσήκουσαν ἑκατέραν 
ἑκατέρᾳ τάξας εἶτα μιχθείσαις" ἐκείναις ἐπεγκεραν- 
νύμενος, οὕτως τὸ πᾶν συνύφηνε᾽ τῆς ψυχῆς 
> e Ss > / 5 / ¢ 4 
εἶδος, ws ἦν ἀνυστόν, ἐκ διαφόρων ὅμοιον ἔκ TE 
πολλῶν ἕν ἀπειργασμένος.Σ οὐκ εὖ δέ τινες εἰρῆ- 
4 7 ς \ “- is \ 
σθαι λέγουσι δύσμικτον ὑπὸ τοῦ WAdtwvos τὴν 
θ , , ) xO s χὰ 7 ν. 3 
ατέρου φύσιν, οὐκ ἄδεκτον οὖσαν ἀλλὰ καὶ φίλην 
Ο μεταβολῆς" μᾶλλον δὲ τὴν τοῦ" ταὐτοῦ, μόνιμον καὶ 
δυσμετάβλητον οὖσαν, οὐ ῥᾳδίως προσίεσθαι μῖξιν 
5 9 ao \ , ¢ € A hg 
GAN’ ἀπωθεῖσθαι καὶ φεύγειν, ὅπως ἁπλῆ διαμείνῃ 


Ύ 

1 αὑτῶν -Β ; αὐτῶν - ; αὐτῶν -all other Mss. 

2 πρὸ τοῦ ταὐτοῦ -Stephanus from Epitome 1032 F; πρὸ 
ταυτοῦ -Leonicus ; πρὸ τούτου -MSS. 

3 πρὸ δὲ τοῦ ἑτέρου -H, B. 

4 μιχθείσας -Diibner. 

5 K, Β, ἢ, m, r, Escor. 72 (ε over erasure); συνύφην ἐν -e; 
συνύφην ἕν -u, Aldine; συνύφηνεν -Basiliensis ; συνύφηνε ἕν 
-Stephanus ; συνύφηνεν ἕν -Hutten. 
ἀπειργασάμενος -f; ἀπεργασάμενος -E'pitome 1032 F. 
ἀλλὰ -omitted by Εἰ, B. 

8 τοῦ -Maurommates ; τῆς -Mss. 
διαμένῃ -F. 


I ὦ» 


machi Arith. Introd. B xxiv, 11 (p. 28 [Hoche, 1867]) ; 
Nemesius, De Natura Hominis v (pp. 153-154 [Matthaei]) ; 
J. H. Waszink, Studien zum Timaioskommentar des Cal- 
cidius I (1964), pp. 74-82. 

α Cf. Philoponus, In Nicomachi Arith. Introd. B xviii, 
1=£€, lines 12-16 (p. 18 {Hoche, 1867]) :... τὸ yap ταὐτὸν 
ἀδιαίρετον. ... So some derived sameness in the psychogony 
from the indivisible being and difference from the divisible 
or identified the two pairs (cf. Proclus, In Platonis Tumaeum 


242 


GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1025 


united sameness and difference, contrary forces and 
antagonistic extremes, not just by themselves ; but 
by first interposing other beings, the indivisible in 
front of sameness and in front of difference the 
divisible, as each of the one pair is in a way akin to 
one of the other,? and by then making an additional 
blend with those between after they had been com- 
mingled ὃ he thus fabricated the whole structure of 
the soul,* from what were various having made it as 
nearly uniform and from what were many as nearly 
single as was feasible. Some? say that it was not 
right of Plato to use “ refractory to mixture ” as an 
epithet of the nature of difference,’ since it is not 
unreceptive of change but is positively friendly to it, 
and that it is rather the nature of sameness which, 
being constant and hard to change, does not readily 
submit to mixture but rejects and shuns it in order 


ii, p. 155, 20-23 [Diehl]; Themistius, De Anima, p. 11, 
10-12; A. E. Taylor, 4A Commentary on Plato’s Timaeus, 
p. 128). 

ὃ See infra 1025 E (τὴν ἐκ τῆς ἀμερίστου καὶ τῆς μεριστῆς ὁ 
θεὸς ὑποδοχὴν τῷ ταὐτῷ καὶ τῷ θατέρῳ συνέστησεν) and 1025 F 
(δεῖται τρίτης τινὸς οἷον ὕλης ὑποδεχομένης .. .). For the way in 
which Plutarch elicited this misinterpretation from Timaeus 
35 a 4-B 1 see notes a and c on 1012 ὁ supra with the re- 
ference in the latter note to Proclus (dn Platonis Timaeum 
ii, p. 159, 5-14 [Diehl]), who construed the text correctly, 
inferring from it, however, contrary to Plutarch that (the 
intermediate) sameness and difference were combined first 
and the blend of them was then combined with (the inter- 
mediate) being. 

¢ Cf. τὸ τῆς ψυχῆς εἶδος in Plat. Quaest. 1008 c, and for 
συνεκεράσατο eis μίαν πάντα ἰδέαν of Timaeus 35 a 7 see supra 
1012 c with note ὁ there and 1023 B, note c. 

¢ ‘They have not yet been identified. 

¢ Timaeus 35 a 7-8 (see 1012 c supra and note ὁ on 1024 ἢ 
supra). 


243 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


\ > \ \ ~ 
(1025) καὶ εἰλικρινὴς καὶ ἀναλλοίωτος. οἱ δὲ ταῦτ᾽" 
9 A “- δῆς, 
ἐγκαλοῦντες ἀγνοοῦσιν ὅτι τὸ μὲν ταὐτὸν ἰδέα τῶν 
ς / > ; ~ 
ὡσαύτως ἐχόντων ἐστὶ TO δὲ θάτερον᾽ τῶν δια- 
, ἢ 7 ᾿ ” a ὃν “ 
φόρως καὶ τούτου μὲν ἔργον, ὧν ἂν ἅψηται, δι- 
, 4 ‘5 9 a \ \ - ΤΑ Ἐτὸ "5 \ 
voTavar® καὶ ἀλλοιοῦν καὶ πολλὰ ποιεῖν ἐκείνου δὲ 
συνάγειν καὶ συνιστάναι διὰ ὁμοιότητος ἐκ πολ- 
a , > , 7 \ \ , 
λῶν μίαν ἀναλαμβάνοντοςἷ μορφὴν καὶ δύναμιν. 
26. Αὗται μὲν οὖν δυνάμεις τῆς τοῦ παντός εἰσι 
ψυχῆς εἰς δὲ θνητὰ καὶ παθητὰ παρεισιοῦσαι" Op- 
γανα (σωμάτων). ἄφθαρτα καὶ αὐτὰ" [σωμάτων |” 
> , 12 \ ~ a 13 Naty , / 

Ὁ ἐν ταύταις" τὸ τῆς δυαδικῆς" καὶ ἀορίστου μερίδος 
ἐπιφαίνεται, μᾶλλον εἶδος, {τὸ δὲ τῆς ἁπλῆς καὶ 
μοναδικῆς ἀμυδρότερον ὑποδέδυκεν. οὐ μὴν ῥᾳ- 
δίως ἄν τις οὔτε πάθος ἀνθρώπου παντάπασιν 


1 εἰληκρινὴς -f, τη. r. 


ταῦτα -E,-B; ταύτας -all other mss. (ς -r). 

τὸ δὲ ἕτερον - Εἰ, B. 

διεστάναι -u, Aldine. 

διιστάναι δι᾽ ὁμοιότητος (omitting καὶ ἀλλοιοῦν . . . καὶ 
συνιστάναι) -f, Υ. 

6 ἐκ -E, B; ἐκεῖ -all other mss., Aldine. 

7H. C.3 dvadapBavovra -Mss.; ἀναλαμβανόντων -Turnebus, 
Stephanus. 

8. KE, B, ἢ, m, r, Basiliensis ; παρεισιοῦται -e, ιν, Escor. 72, 
Aldine; <ai> παρεισίασιν -B. Miller (1873); ai δ᾽ eis... 
παρεισίασιν -Bernardakis. 

9 «σωμάτων; -added by H. C. 

10 ἄφθαρτα καὶ αὐτὰ -Μ88. ; φθαρτῶν καὶ αὐτὰ -Stephanus ; 
«φθαρτῶν» ἄφθαρτοι αὐταὶ -Diibner; ἀῴφθαρτοι καὶ αὐταὶ -Β. 
Miiller (1873) ; ἄφθαρτοι ζφθαρτῶνΣ αὐταὶ -Bernardakis. 

11 [σωμάτων] -deleted by H. C. 

12 τούτοις -Stephanus. 

13 τῆς ἁπλῆς δυαδικῆς -f. 

14 ἐπιφέρεται -B1 (ρ remade to ν -B?). 


24:4 


δι fF & bP 





GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1025 


to remain simple and pure and unsubject to altera- 
tion. They who make these objections fail to under- 
stand, however, that sameness is the idea 4 of things 
identical and difference of things various and that the 
function of the latter is to divide and diversify and 
make many whatever it touches but of the former 
is to unite and combine,’ recovering from many by 
means of similarity a single form and force.¢ 

26. Now, these are faculties of the soul of the sum 
of things? but enter besides ὁ into mortal and passible 
organs {οὗ bodies). Indestructible as they are 
themselves, in these faculties the form of the dyadic 
and indefinite part makes itself more apparent, while 
<that» of the simple and monadic part is submerged 
in greater obscurity.’ It would not be easy, how- 
ever, to observe in man either an emotion entirely 

« Cf. Plato, Sophist 255 x 5-6 and 256 a 12-8 3 (see 1013 ἢ 
supra with note g there) and see ἰδέα in 1023 c supra. 

> See note 6 on 1024 ἢ supra with De Defectu Orac. 428 c 


referred to there and De # 391 ο(... ταὐτοῦ δὲ τὴν μιγνύου- 
σαν ἀρχὴν θατέρου δὲ τὴν διακρίνουσαν) ; and cf. Proclus, ln 
Platonis Timaeum ii, p. 155, 14-20 and p. 158, 18-31 (Diehl). 

¢ See 1022 F supra with note c there; cf. Plato, Phaedrus 
265 p 3-4 and Hermias, Jn Platonis Phaedrum, p. 171, 8-11 
(Couvreur). 

4 Cf. Timaeus 41 v 4-5 (τὴν τοῦ παντὸς ψυχὴν . . .) and De 
Virtute Morali 441 F (ἣἥ 7° ἀνθρώπου ψυχὴ μέρος ἣ μίμημα τῆς 
τοῦ παντὸς οὖσα... .). 

¢ The text has been thought to be corrupt chiefly because 
of the failure to recognize παρεισιοῦσαι as a periphrastic 
present (cf. Weissenberger, Die Sprache Plutarchs I, p. 9: 
H. Widmann, Beitrdge zur Syntax Epikurs, p. 135). 

f i.e. in these that have entered into the mortal organs of 
bodies. 

9 The dyadic part is manifested as difference and the 
monadic as sameness (see 1024 p supra with note / there). 


15 «τὸ» -added by Wyttenbach. 
245 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


3 / ~ 
(1025) ἀπηλλαγμένον λογισμοῦ κατανοήσειεν οὔτε διανοίας 
ΨᾺΡ ς“ \ > f ἋἋ ,ὔ; Bh A 
κίνησιν ἡ μηδὲν ἐπιθυμίας ἢ φιλοτιμίας ἢ τοῦ 
, λ / / ~ 
χαίροντος ἢ λυπουμένου πρόσεστι. διὸ τῶν φιλο- 
/ ¢ \ \ / / A “ 
σόφων οἱ μὲν τὰ πάθη λόγους ποιοῦσιν, ὡς πᾶσαν 
ἐπιθυμίαν καὶ λύπην καὶ ὀργὴν κρίσεις οὔσας" οἱ δὲ 
τὰς ἀρετὰς ἀποφαίνουσι παθητικάς, καὶ γὰρ ἀν- 
δρείᾳ' τὸ φοβούμενον καὶ σωφροσύνῃ τὸ ἡδόμενον 
\ ͵ \ , 2 \ \ 
καὶ δικαιοσύνῃ τὸ κερδαλέον elvar.? Kat μὴν θεω- 
E ρητικῆς ye τῆς ψυχῆς οὔσης ἅμα καὶ πρακτικῆς 
καὶ θεωρούσης μὲν τὰ καθόλου πραττούσης δὲ τὰ 
καθ᾽ ἕκαστα καὶ νοεῖν μὲν ἐκεῖνα ταῦτα δ᾽ αἰσθά- 
χιλνδρέά ΒΓ: 
5. ἐνεῖναι -Bernardakis. 
καὶ θεωρούσης μὲν τὰ καθόλου πραττούσης δὲ -f1 (in margin), 


m! (in margin) ; καὶ θεωρούσης δὲ (δὲ -omitted by E, B) τὰ καθ᾽ 
ἕκαστα -Mss., Aldine. 


3 


ee eee 


* See 1024 F supra (ἡ μὲν νόησις κίνησις τοῦ νοοῦντος . - .). 
For διάνοια used of the intellectual faculty of the soul cf. 
De Virtute Morali 441 c (Stoics) and 448 s-c (Plutarch him- 
self of τὸ θεωρητικόν, cf. 451 B [τὸ διανοητικόν] and Plat. 
(uaest. 1004 p supra); Galen, De Placitis Hippoc. et Plat. 

ix, 1 (p. 733, 11-14 [Mueller]). 

δ Cf. De Virtute Morali 443 B-c (. . . τὸ θυμούμενον ἐν 
ἡμῖν καὶ ἐπιθυμοῦν... οὐκ ἀποικοῦν οὐδ᾽ ἀπεσχισμένον [scil. τοῦ 
φρονοῦντος] .- . . ἀλλὰ φύσει μὲν ἐξηρτημένον ἀεὶ δὲ ὁμιλοῦν . . .). 

¢ Stoic doctrine (cf. De Virtute Morali 441 c-p and 
446 r—447 a, De Sollertia Animalium 961 τ ; and Diogenes 
Laertius, vii, 111 [S.V.F. i, frag. 202 and iii, frags. 382, 
456, 459, 461, and 462)). 

@ Cf. De Virtute Morali 443 c-p (. . . τὰς ἠθικὰς ἀρετάς, οὐκ 
ἀπαθείας οὔσας ἀλλὰ συμμετρίας παθῶν καὶ μεσότητας, .. . {ef 
Aristotle, Eth. Nic. 1104 Ὁ 24-26]) and Albinus, Lpitome, 
xxxii, 1 (Ὁ. 155, 1-5 [Louis]=p. 185, 21-25 [Hermann]): ai 
πλεῖσται ἀρεταὶ περὶ πάθη γίνονται... The doctrine is originally 
Peripatetic: cf. Aristotle, Hth. Nic. 1104 Ὁ 13-16, 1109 b 30, 


246 





GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1025 


divorced from reason or a motion of the mind ¢ in 
which there is present nothing of desire or ambition 
or rejoicing or grieving.’ This is why some of the 
philosophers make the emotions varieties of reason, 
on the ground that all desire and grief and anger are 
judgments,° while others declare that the virtues 
have to do with emotions,? for fearing is the province 
of courage and enjoyment that of sobriety and 
acquisitiveness that of justice.¢ Now, as the soul is 
at once contemplative and practical’ and contem- 
plates the universals but acts upon the particulars 9 
and apparently cognizes the former but perceives the 


and 1178 a 10-21 with Aspasius, Hth. Nic., p. 42, 21-24; 
[Aristotle], Magna Moralia 1206 ἃ 36—b 29 ; Areius Didymus 
in Stobaeus, Hel. ii, 7, 20 (p. 142, 6-7 [Wachsmuth]) ; 
and the Pseudo-Pythagoreans, Metopus and Theages, in 
Stobaeus, Anth. iii, 1, 115, and 118 (pp. 71, 16-72, 1 and 
p. 81, 11-14 [Hense}). 

6 For courage and sobriety cf. Eth. Nic. 1104 a 18-b 8 
and Magna Moralia 1185 Ὁ 21-32, and for justice cf. Eth. 
Eud. 1221 a 4 and 23-24; ef. also Stobaeus, Ecl. ii, 7, 20 
(p. 141, 5-18 [Wachsmuth]) and Plutarch, De Virtute Morali 
445 a (Babut, Plutarque de la Vertu Ethique, p. 78 and 
Plutarque et le Stoicisme, pp. 331-332). 

t Cf. Albinus, Epitome ii, 2 and iv, 8 (pp. 7, 1-2 and 21, 
4-8 [Louis]=pp. 153, 2-4 and 156, 13-17 [Hermann]); 
Proclus, In Platonis Timaeum iii, p. 335, 2-10 (Diehl) on 
Timaeus 43 c 7-p 4; Simplicius, De Anima, p. 95, 26-27. 
This bipartition, foreshadowed in Plato’s Politicus 258 © 4-7, 
goes back to Xenocrates (frag. 6 [Heinze]) and Aristotle (De 
Anima 407 a 23-25 and 433 a 14-15, Politics 1333 a 24-25) ; 
and despite the tripartition frequently used by the latter 
(Metaphysics 1025 b 25, Eth. Nic. 1139 a 26-31) it became 
the conventional Peripatetic distinction ([Plutarch], De 
Placitis, 874 r—875 a=Dow. Graeci, pp. 273 a 25—274 a 
17 ; Diogenes Laertius, v, 28). 

9 Cf. Aristotle, Metaphysics 981 a 15-24; Lth. Nic. 1141 
b 16 and 1143 a 32-33. 


247 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1025) νεσθαι δοκούσης, ὁ κοινὸς λόγος ἀεὶ περί τε 


A > 4 “ ~ 
ταὐτὸν ἐντυγχάνων τῷ θατέρῳ' καὶ ταὐτῷ" περὶ 
/ ᾽ an ι 
θάτερον ἐπιχειρεῖ μὲν ὅροις καὶ διαιρέσεσι χωρί- 
4 \ “a \ οἷ \ ‘ \ > \ \ \ 
tew τὸ €v καὶ τὰ πολλὰ καὶ TO ἀμερὲς καὶ TO 
\ a 
μεριστὸν" οὐ δύναται δὲ καθαρῶς ἐν οὐδετέρῳ yeve- 
.. 4 
σθαι διὰ τὸ Kal* τὰς ἀρχὰς ἐναλλὰξ᾽ ἐμπεπλέχθαι 
καὶ καταμεμῖχθαι δι᾿ ἀλλήλων. καὶ διὰ τοῦτο τῆς 
οὐσίας τὴν ἐκ τῆς ἀμερίστου καὶ τῆς μεριστῆς ὁ 
θεὸς ὑποδοχὴν τῷ ταὐτῷ" καὶ τῷ θατέρῳ συν- 
9 ~ : A 
ἔστησεν ἵν᾽ ἐν διαφορᾷ τάξις γένηται: τοῦτο yap 
ἦν γενέσθαι, ἐπεὶ χωρὶς τούτων" τὸ μὲν ταὐτὸν 
> > ἃ σ > 0" / OA / 
οὐκ εἶχε διαφορὰν wor οὐδὲ κίνησιν οὐδὲ γένεσιν 
\ , 9 O\ , ἢ ᾽ Ee τ Cs ee 
τὸ θάτερον" δὲ τάξιν οὐκ εἶχεν ὥστ᾽ οὐδὲ σύστασιν 
3 A / \ \ > ~ 3 ἴω 7 
οὐδὲ γένεσιν. καὶ γὰρ εἰ τῷ ταὐτῷ συμβέβηκεν 
1 
8 


-E 


τῷ ἑτέρῳ -Ἐ, B. 2 καὶ ταυτὸ -B. 

καὶ τὸ μεριστὸν -f, M3; καὶ τὸ ἀμεριστὸν -Τὶ : καὶ μεριστὸν 
B, e, u, Escor. 72, Aldine. 

καὶ -B; omitted by all other mss. 

ἐναναλλαξ' (sic) -f, τη. 

E, B; τῷ αὐτῷ -all other mss., Aldine. 

f,m, 13; τῷ ἑτέρῳ -all other mss., Aldine. 

τούτων -f, m, τ, Aldine; ὄντων -all other mss. 

® τὸ θάτερον -C.C.C. 99, Diibner; θάτερον (τὸ omitted) -e, 
-u, in, r, Escor. 72, Aldine; τὸ ἕτερον -E, B; τὸ θάτερον... 
οὐδὲ σύστασιν οὐδὲ γένεσιν -omitted by f. 


Ψ»ἦ 


orn ὁ σι» 


¢ See 1024 Ἐ-- supra with note f on page 237. 

> 4.e. common to both the contemplative aspect and the 
practical (cf. De Virtute Morali 443 © [. .. τοῦ λόγου . .. 
τὸ μὲν ... θεωρητικόν ἐστι τὸ δ᾽... πρακτικόν] with Aristotle, 
Politics 1333 ἃ 25 and Eth. Nic. 1139 a 6-15 [cf. Gauthier 
et Jolif ad loc., ii, pp. 440-442]); but it is so just because 
it is a blend of both principles, the one proceeding to uni- 
versals and the other to particulars, and so becomes νόησις 
ἐν τοῖς νοητοῖς, 1.6. contemplative, and δόξα ἐν τοῖς αἰσθητοῖς, 
i.e. practical (1024 r supra with notes a and ὁ there). So 
both Thévenaz (L’ Ame du Monde, p. 31, note 159) and 


248 


GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1025 


latter,* the reason common to both,” as it is continu- 
ally coming upon difference in sameness and upon 
sameness in difference, tries with definitions and 
divisions ὁ to separate the one and the many, that is 
the indivisible and the divisible,? but cannot arrive 
at either exclusively, because the very principles 
have been alternately intertwined and thoroughly 
intermixed with each other. It was just for this 
reason that god made from being the compound of 
the indivisible and the divisible as a receptacle for 
sameness and difference,’ that order might come to 
be in differentiation ; in fact, ‘come to be”’ amounted 
to this, since without these sameness had no dif- 
ferentiation so that it had no motion either and so 
no coming to be and difference had no order so that 
it had no coherence either and so no coming to be.9 


Helmer (De An. Proc., p. 53), whose interpretation he rejects 
and Hubert here adopts, are partially right. 

¢ See 1026 pv infra: ἡ δὲ ὁριστικὴ δύναμις . . . καὶ τούὐναν- 
τίον ἡ διαιρετικὴ. .. - 

@ Cf. Plato, Sophist 245 a 8-9 with ἕν τε καὶ ἀμερές in 
Theaetetus 205 © 2 and Parmenides 138 a 5-6; and Aristotle, 
Metaphysics 1054 a 20-23 on τὸ ἕν καὶ τὰ πολλά as the 
indivisible and the divisible. 

ὁ Cf. Plato, Philebus 15 Ὁ 4-8. 

t See 1025 8 supra with note ὁ there. 

9 See 1024 © supra with note b there. The next sentence 
shows that χωρὶς τούτων means without the compound of 
indivisible and divisible being as a receptacle. The οὐδὲ in 
both occurrences of οὐδὲ γένεσιν, the second of which Hubert 
mistakenly daggers, is consecutive (cf. infra De Comm. Not. 
1070 ©, note a): γένεσις presupposes motion (cf. Alexander, 
Quaestiones, Ὁ. 82, 3-4 [Bruns]; Philoponus, De Generatione, 
p. 306, 3-4), but it also implies something coherent that 
comes to be (cf. in Adv. Colotem 1114 8B the objection to 
infinitude as a principle for coming to be: ἡ δ᾽ ἄτακτος... 
ἀπερίληπτος, αὑτὴν ἀναλύουσα Kal ταράττουσα ... .). 


249 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


e A na “ 

(1025) ἑτέρῳ εἶναι' τοῦ ἑτέρου καὶ τῷ ἑτέρῳ πάλιν αὑτῷ" 
9 / 3 A ε / / > γ΄ ~ 

ταὐτόν, οὐδὲν ἡ τοιαύτη μέθεξις ἀλλήλων ποιεῖ 
γόνιμον, ἀλλὰ δεῖται τρίτης τινὸς οἷον ὕλης ὑπο- 

1026 δεχομένης. καὶ διατιθεμένης ὑ ὑπ᾽ ἀμφοτέρων. αὕτη 
ἐστὶν ἣν πρώτην συνέστησε τῷ περὶ τὰ νοητὰ 


μονίμῳ τοῦ περὶ τὰ σώματα κινητικοῦ τὸ ἄπειρον 
ὁρίσας. 

27. ‘Os δὲ φωνή τίς ἐστιν ἄλογος καὶ ἀσήμαν- 

> “A a 

tos λόγος δὲ λέξις ἐν φωνῇ σημαντικῇ" διανοίας, 
ς 
ἁρμονία δὲ τὸ ἐκ φθόγγων καὶ διαστημάτων καὶ 

1 ἕτερον εἶναι -Benseler (De Hiatu, p. 529). 

2 f,m; αὐτῶ -E}, e, u (αὐτῶι), Escor. 72; ταὐτῶ -E?, 
B; αὐτὸς -r!, - 

ὃ σημαντικὴ -B, u 

οὐ ἐμ μωγὸ 
4 δέ τι -u. 


* For συμβέβηκε in this sense see Plat. Quaest. 1003 F 
supra (τοῦτο δὲ καὶ τῇ μονάδι συμβέβηκε). Even Aristotle 
at times uses συμβέβηκε and συμβεβηκός simpliciter (De Anima 
402 a 8-10, De Part. Animal. 643 a 30-31 with Metaphysics 
1025 a 30-32) in referring to what he calls more exactly συμβε- 
βηκότα καθ᾽ αὑτά (Anal. Post. 75 Ὁ 1-2 and 83 b 19-20, Meta- 
physics 995 b 19-20). Cf. 1018 pv infra (chap. 14): (tov τῷ 
τελευταίῳ συμβέβηκε, τῷ KC’. 

> i.e. the intercommunion of ideas in Plato, Sophist 254 
Ὁ 4—259 B 7 (cf. 256 B 1 and 259 a 7 for the term μέθεξις) : 
by such “ participation ”’ in difference sameness like all the 
ideas is different from difference as it is from all the others, 
and difference like all the others is the same as itself by 
“ participation ’’ in sameness (cf. Proclus, In Platonis 
Parmenidem, cols. 756, 33-757, 8 [Cousin?]). For the ideas, 
sameness and difference, see supra 1025 c with note a there. 

¢ In Timaeus 48 κε 3—49 A 6 the γενέσεως ὑποδοχὴ καὶ 
τιθήνη is introduced as ἃ τρίτον γένος : and Aristotle refers 
to his substrate of contraries, themselves ἀπαθῆ ὑπ᾽ ἀλλήλων, 
i.e. to matter, as τρίτον τι (Metaphysics 1069 b 8-9 and 
1075 a 30-32, cf. Physics 190 Ὁ 33—191 a 1). Plutarch in 
De Iside 370 r—371 a also ascribes to Plato τρίτην τινὰ 
φύσιν between ταὐτόν and θάτερον (see note c on 1015 B supra) ; 


250 


“2. “ἀο'όσπ eee ee eee 


GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1025-1026 


For, even if it is a characteristic α of sameness to be 
different from difference and of difference again to 
be the same as itself, mutual participation of this 
kind ὃ has no fruitful result; but a third term is 
required, a kind of matter serving as a receptacle for 
both and being modified by them,°¢ and this it is that 
he first compounded when with that which abides 
about the intelligibles ὦ he bounded the limitlessness 
of that which is motive in the case of bodies.¢ 

27. As some sound is not speech and not significant 
but speech is an utterance in sound that signifies 
thought, and as concord is what consists of sounds 
and intervals and a sound is one and the same thing,’ 


but there he takes ταὐτόν to be the good principle and 
θάτερον the evil, i.e. the evil “* world-soul ” that he professes 
to find in the Laws and which in the present essay (1014 
n-E supra) he identifies instead with the “ divisible being ”’ 
here compounded with the “ indivisible’ to be itself the 
‘‘ third term,”’ the receptacle for both ταὐτόν and θάτερον. 

¢ See note 6 on pages 228 f. supra. 

¢ See 1015 © supra (τὴν κινητικὴν τῆς ὕλης καὶ περὶ τὰ 
σώματα γιγνομένην μεριστὴν . . . κίνησιν) with notes ὁ and c 
there and 1027 a infra (τῷ μὲν ἑνὶ τὴν ἀπειρίαν ὁρίσαντος ἵν᾽ 
οὐσία γένηται πέρατος μετασχοῦσα) With note a there. 

f Cf. S.V.F. iii, p. 213, 18-21 and ii, p. 48, 28-30. The 
use of φωνή for “‘ sound” in the generic sense (so Plat. 
Quaest. 1000 B, 1001 Fr, and 1006 B; cf. Timaeus 67 B 2-4 
and Divisiones Aristoteleae ὃ 30 [24]=pp. 37, 23-38, 14 
{Mutschmann]) is called catachrestic by [Plutarch], De 
Placitis 902 n=Dowx. Graeci, p. 408 a 3-8 (cf. Aristotle, 
De Anima 420 Ὁ 5-16 and 27-33). For speech (λόγος) as 
articulate sound that is “ significant ’”’ see also Plat. Quaest. 
1009 v-E. 

9 Cf. Nicomachus, Harmonices Man. 12 (Musici Scrip- 
tores Graeci, Ὁ. 261, 4-6 [Jan]); Aristoxenus, Hlementa 
Harmonica i, 15, 15-16 with P. Marquard’s note ad loc., 
pp. 224-227 ; Theon Smyrnaeus, pp. 49, 18-20 from Adrastus 
and 60, 13-16 (Hiller). 


251 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1026) φθόγγος μὲν ἕν καὶ ταὐτὸν διάστημα δὲ φθόγγων 
ἑτερότης καὶ διαφορά, μιχθέντων δὲ τούτων wor 
γίγνεται καὶ μέλος" οὕτως τὸ παθητικὸν τῆς ψυχῆς 
ἀόριστον ἦν καὶ ἀστάθμητον, εἶθ᾽ ὡρίσθη πέρατος 
ἐγγενομένου; καὶ εἴδους τῷ μεριστῷ καὶ παντο- 
δαπῷ τῆς κινήσεως. συλλαβοῦσα δὲ τὸ ταὐτὸν καὶ 
τὸ θάτερον" ὁμοιότησι καὶ ἀνομοιότησιν ἀριθμῶν 

Β ἐκ διαφορᾶς ὁμολογίαν ἀπεργασαμένων᾽' ζωή" τε 
τοῦ παντός ἐστιν ἔμφρων καὶ ἁρμονία καὶ λόγος 


ἄγων πειθοῖ μεμιγμένην" ἀνάγκην, ἣν εἱμαρμένην 

ε \ A > a \ / e - 
ot πολλοὶ καλοῦσιν, ᾿Εμπεδοκλῆς δὲ φιλίαν ὁμοῦ 
καὶ νεῖκος, Ἡράκλειτος δὲ παλίντροπον, ἁρμονίην 


1 ἐγγινομένου -f, m, r. 
2 ἕτερον -E, B, u. 
καὶ -F. 
4 FE, B; ἐπεργασαμένων -e, u, Escor. 72, Aldine; ézepya- 
σμένων -f, τη, Τ. 
5Ὴ, Β: “ζῶν -all other mss., Aldine. 
8 μεμιγμένων -Τ. 
7 μ88. (580 in De Tranquillitate Animi 473 r—474 a all 
mss. except D, which has παλίντονος as do all mss. in De [side 
369 B); παλίντονον -Turnebus. 


*¢ Cf. Aelian Platonicus and Thrasyllus in Porphyry, Jn 
Ptolemaei Harmonica, p. 35, 15-22 and p. 91, 13-18 (Diiring) ; 
Bacchius, [sagoge 6 (Musici Scriptores Graeci, p. 292, 20-21 
[Jan]). In 1020 τ infra it is defined 85 πᾶν τὸ περιεχόμενον 
ὑπὸ δυεῖν φθόγγων ἀνομοίων τῇ τάσει. 

> So also Qu aest. Conviv. 141 C3 cf. τὸ ἐκ φθόγγων καὶ 
διαστημάτων καὶ χρόνων συγκείμενον in Bacchius, Jsagoge 78 
(Musici Scriptores Graeci, p. 309, 13-14 [Jan]) and the 
objection of Aristoxenus, Klementa Harmonica i, 18, 16-19, 1. 

¢ See the end of the preceding chapter with note e on 
1026 a and 1016 c supra with note 6 on page 203. 

@ Probably a reference to similar and dissimilar numbers, 
for which cf. Theon Smyrnaeus, pp. 36, 12-37, 6 (Hiller) 
and Iamblichus, In Nicomachi Arithmeticam Introductionem, 


252 





GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1026 


an interval the diversity and difference of sounds.® 
and the mixture of these results in song and melody,’ 
so the affective part of the soul was indeterminate and 
unstable and then was bounded when there came to 
be limit and form in the divisible and omnifarious 
character of the motion.¢ And, once having compre- 
hended sameness and difference with the similarities 
and dissimilarities of numbers ὦ that produced con- 
sensus out of dissension, it is for the sum of things 
rational life and concord ὁ and reason guiding neces- 
sity that has been tempered with persuasion’ and 
which by most people is called destiny,7 by Empe- 
docles love together with strife,» by Heraclitus 
concord of the universe retroverse like that of lyre 


pp. 82, 10-18 and 84, 10-88, 15 (Pistelli) ; see 1017 £ infra: 
ai συζυγίαι τῶν ὁμοίων ἔσονται πρὸς τοὺς ὁμοίους. 

¢ See 1080 c infra; for ζωή. .. ἔμφρων cf. Timaeus 36 Ἑ 
3-4, quoted by Plutarch at 1016 B supra. 

¢ An inexact reminiscence of Timaeus 47 πὶ 5—48 a 5; 
cf. Plutarch’s Phocion ii, 9 (742 ©), and for his interpretation 
of ἀνάγκη in the Timaeus see 1014 p—1015 a supra. 

9 Cf. lamblichus, De Mysteriis viii, 7 (p. 269, 13-14 
[Parthey]) and Corpus Hermeticum xvi, 11 (ii, p. 235, 22 
{Nock-Festugiére]). Plutarch himself substitutes ἀνάγκη 
for εἱμαρμένη (see supra 1015 a, note e); cf. also [Plutarch], 
De Placitis 884 Ἐ-τὶ (Dow. Graeci, p. 321 a 6-9 and p. 322 
a 1-3) and Cicero, De Natura Deorum i, 55 (‘ illa fatalis 
necessitas quam εἱμαρμένην dicitis ᾽᾽). 

4 Empedocles, frag. A 45 (D.-K.); of. Empedocles, frag. 
B 115, 1-2 (D.-K.) with Hippolytus, Refutatio vii, 29, 23 
(p. 214, 17-24 [Wendland]) and frags. A 32 and A 38 (D.-K.) 
with Simplicius, Phys., p. 197, 10-13, p. 465, 12-13, and 
p. 1184, 5-17. Zeller’s estimate of this evidence (Phil. 
Griech. i, 2, p. 969, note 2) is still valid despite such attempts 
at rehabilitation and embellishment as that of J. Bollack’s 
(Empédocle i [Paris, 1965], pp. 153-158 and 161); οἱ 
H. Schreckenberg, Ananke (Miinchen, 1964), pp. 111-113 
with note 97, 


253 


PLUTARCH’S MORATLIA 


/ U 
(1026) κόσμου oKwomep λύρης καὶ τόξου, Ilappevidyns δὲ 
φῶς καὶ σκότος, ᾿Αναξαγόρας δὲ νοῦν καὶ ἀπειρίαν, 
Ζωροάστρης δὲ θεὸν καὶ δαίμονα, τὸν μὲν ᾿᾽Ὧρο- 
μάσδην καλῶν τὸν δ᾽ ᾿Αρειμάνιον.: Εὐριπίδης δ᾽ 
οὐκ ὀρθῶς ἀντὶ τοῦ συμπλεκτικοῦ τῷ διαζευκτικῷ 
κέχρηται 
Levs εἴτ᾽ ἀνάγκη φύσεος εἴτε νοῦς" βροτῶν 
Ο καὶ γὰρ ἀνάγκη καὶ νοῦς ἐστιν ἡ διήκουσα διὰ 
πάντων δύναμις. Αἰγύπτιοι μὲν οὖν μυθολογοῦν- 


ει 
1 ἀριμάνιον -B!; ἀριμάνιον -all other mss. 
| re -α. 
8 Stephanus ; φύσεως -MSS. 
4 vods -omitted by r. 


« Heraclitus, frag. B 51 (D.-K. and Walzer)=frags. 45 
and 56 (Bywater): cf. Dow. Graeci, p. 303 8 8-10 (... 
εἱμαρμένην δὲ λόγον ἐκ τῆς ἐναντιοδρομίας δημιουργὸν τῶν ὄντων) 
and Diogenes Laertius, ix, 7 (p. 440, 2-3 [Long]). Both in 
De Tranquillitate Animi 473 r—474 a and in De Iside 369 
B the quotation from Heraclitus is followed by that of Euri- 
pides, frag. 21, 3-4 (Nauck, Trag. Graec. Frag.”, p. 369). 
Neither in the former of these nor in the present passage is 
there reason to doubt that Plutarch wrote παλίντροπος, whe- 

_ ther it was this or παλίντονος, as in the De Jside, that Hera- 
clitus had written (cf. W. K. C. Guthrie, 4 History of Greek 
Philosophy i (Cambridge, 1962], p. 439, note 3 with refer- 
ences; M. Marcovich, Heraclitus [Merida, 1967], pp. 125- 
126). 

> See Plutarch, Adv. Colotem 1114 8. Cf. Simplicius, 
Phys., p. 38, 18-24 (quoting Alexander); p. 25, 15-16; 
pp. 30, 14-31, 2; and pp. 179, 20-180, 12 with Parmenides, 
frag. B 8, 53-61 and B 9 (D.-K.). The belief that the second 
part of Parmenides’ poem, called the κοσμογονία by Plutarch 
in Amatorius 756 ©, was meant to be a valid account of the 
phenomenal world (Adv. Colotem 1114 c-£) goes back to 
Aristotle (Jetaphysics 986 Ὁ 31-34; cf. Cherniss, Crit. 
Presoc. Phil., p. 48, note 192); but Plutarch is alone in 
identifying its two ‘‘ principles ’’ with ἀνάγκη, for which see 
254 





GVUNERATION OF THE SOUT, 1026 


and bow,* by Parmenides light and darkness,’ by 
Anaxagoras intelligence and infinitude,¢ and by 
Zoroaster god and spirit, the former called by him 
Oromasdes and the latter Areimanius.4 Euripides 
has erred in using the disjunctive instead of the 
copulative conjunction in the prayer, 


Zeus, whether natural necessity 
Or the intelligence of mortal men,’ 


for the power that pervades all things’ is both 
necessity and intelligence. Now, the Egyptians in 
a mythical account say enigmatically that, when 


rather Parmenides, frag. B 10, 6-7 (D.-K) and frag. A 37 
(p. 224, 7-9 [D.-K.]) with frag. B 12 (D.-K.). 

ὁ See De Iside 370 Ἑ (νοῦν καὶ ἄπειρον). Cf. Theophrastus, 
Phys. Opin., frag. 4 (Dox. Graecit, p. 479, 14-15); and for 
Plutarch’s ἀπειρία here cf. Aristotle, Metaphysics 988 a 28. 
Against the identification with ἀνάγκη see Plutarch himself 
in Pericles iv, 6 (154 n-c); but on the other hand see De 
Defectu Orac. 435 νηῷ... τὸ κατ᾽ ἀνάγκην . .- -. μετιὼν ἀεὶ .. .) 
and Aristotle, Afetaphysics, 985 a 18-21 (cf. Cherniss, Crit. 
Presoc. Philos., pp. 234-235). 

4 See supra 1012 © with note c there on “ Zaratas”’; 
De Iside 369 p—370 c; and Diogenes Laertius, i, 8. Cf. 
Bidez-Cumont, Les Mages Hellénisés i, pp. 58-66 and ii, 
pp. 70-79 ; and J. Hani, Rev. Ktudes Grecques, Ixxvii (1964), 
pp. 489-525. 

¢ Euripides, Troiades, 886. For the “ correction’ sug- 
gested by Plutarch in Stoic fashion cf. Babut, Plutarque et 
le Stoicisme, p. 141. 

* For this phrase ef. Cornutus, xi (p. 11, 91 [Lang]) and 
{ Aristotle], De Mundo 396 8 28-29. It is used of the Platonic 
world-soul by Atticus, frag. viii (Baudry)= Eusebius, Praep. 
Evang. xv, 12, 3 (ii, p. 375, 17-19 [Mras]), though it is Stoic 
in origin: ef. Plutarch, De Iside 367 c with Diogenes 
Laertius, vii, 147; [Plutarch], De Placitis 882 a and 885 a 
(Dox. Graeci, p. 306 a 5-8 and p. 323 A 1-6); Alexander, 
De Micxtione, p. 225, 1-3 (Bruns); Plotinus, Hnn. m1, i, 4, 
lines 1-9. 

255 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1026) τες" αἰνίττονται, τοῦ Ὥρου" δίκην ὀφλόντος, τῷ 
μὲν πατρὶ τὸ πνεῦμα καὶ τὸ αἷμα τῇ δὲ μητρὶ τὴν 
σάρκα καὶ τὴν πιμελὴν προσνεμηθῆναι. τῆς δὲ 
ψυχῆς οὐδὲν μὲν εἰλικρινὲς | οὐδ᾽ ἄκρατον οὐδὲ χωρὶς 
ἀπολείπεται τῶν ἄλλων: ἁρμονίη γὰρ ἀφανὴς φα- 
νερῆς κρείττων καθ᾽ Ἡράκλειτον, ἐν ἡ τὰς δια- 
φορὰς καὶ τὰς ἑἕτερότητας ὁ μιγνύων θεὸς ἔκρυψε 
καὶ κατέδυσεν᾽ ἐμφαίνεται δὲ ὅμως αὐτῆς τῷ μὲν 
ἀλόγῳ τὸ ταραχῶδες τῷ δὲ λογικῷ τὸ εὔτακτον, 
ταῖς δ᾽ αἰσθήσεσι τὸ κατηναγκασμένον τῷ δὲ νῷ 

D τὸ αὐτοκρατές. ἡ δὲ ὁριστικὴ δύναμις τὸ καθόλου 
καὶ τὸ ἀμερὲς διὰ συγγένειαν ἀγαπᾷ, καὶ τοὐναν- 
τίον ἡ διαιρετικὴ πρὸς τὰ καθ᾽ ἕκαστα φέρεται τῷ 
μεριστῷ᾽ χαίρει δὲ ὁλότητι" διὰ τὸ ταὐτὸν ἐφήδε- 
ταί Ate) μεταβολῇ" διὰ τὸ θάτερον ἢ οὐχ ἥκιστα 
δὲ ἥ τε πρὸς τὸ καλὸν διαφορὰ καὶ τὸ αἰσχρὸν ἥ 


1 μυθολογοῦνται -Υ. 2 r; wpov -all other mss. 
3 Diibner ; ὄφλοντος -Mss. 
4 ὁλότητι -Bury (Proc. Cambridge Philol. Soc., N.S. 
[1950-51], p. 81) ; ὅλον τῇ -Mss. 
5 ἐφήδεταί <re> -Bury (loc. cit.) : ἐφ᾽ ἃ δεῖται -Mss. 
* Tm, vy Aldine ; sobs -all ethiae MSS. 
7 διὰ τὸ ἕτερον -E, 


® See De Iside 358 © and De Libidine et Aegritudine 6 (vii, 
p. 7, 2-16 [Bernardakis]=vi, 3, p. 56, 7-20 [Ziegler-Pohlenz, 
1966]); cf. J. Hani, Rev. Etudes Grecques, Ixxvi (1963), 
pp. 111-120. 

δ See 1025 ἢ supra with note ὁ there and Plat. Quaest. 
1008 c supra. In De Tranquillitate Animi 474 a, De Sol- 
lertia Animalium 964 pv-E, and De Iside 369 c it is rather 
human affairs or life, nature, and the sublunar world that 
are said to contain nothing pure or unmixed. 

¢ Heraclitus, frag. B 54 (D.-K. and Walzer)=frag. 47 
(Bywater): 

@ Cf. τὴν δὲ ταραχώδη Kai ἀνόητον (1014 c supra) and ἡμῶν 
τὸ ταραχῶδες (Quaest. Conviv, 746 a). 


256 


GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1026 


Horus was convicted, the breath and blood were as- 
signed to his father and the flesh and fat to his 
mother. Of the soul, however, nothing remains 
pure or unmixed or separate from the rest,? for 
stronger than manifest concord according to Hera- 
clitus is the unmanifest,° wherein god, making the 
mixture, sank and concealed the differences and the 
diversities ; but nevertheless turbulence makes itself 
evident in the irrational part of it ἃ and orderliness in 
the rational,¢ necessitation in the senses 7 and inde- 
pendence in the intelligence.’ Its faculty for 
defining has a fondness for the universal and the 
indivisible by reason of kinship, and contrariwise that 
for dividing is moved to particulars by the divisible ἃ ; 
and it rejoices in integrity by reason of sameness 
<and») exults in change by reason of difference.‘ 
More than anything else, however, the dissension in 
regard to fair and foul and again in regard to pleasant 
¢ Cf. τὸ νοερὸν καὶ... TO τεταγμένον (1016 c supra). 

Cf. Plato, Timaeus 42 a 3-B 1 and 69 c -Ὁ 6; the 
senses are dependent upon external stimuli (Timaeus 43 c 
4-7 and Philebus 33 p 2—34 a 9). 

σ Cf. De Facie 945 νυ (ὁ δὲ νοῦς . . . αὐτοκράτωρ) and De 
Amore Prolis 493 Ὁ-Ὲ (. . . αὐτοκρατὴς λόγος) with Anaxa- 
goras, frag. B 12 (ii, p. 37, 18-20 [D.-K.]) and Plato, Cratylus 
413 ὁ 5-7. 

δ See 1025 © supra (ἐπιχείρει μὲν ὅροις καὶ διαιρέσεσι χωρί- 
few. . . τὸ ἀμερὲς καὶ τὸ μεριστὸν . . .) and cf. [amblichus, 
De Comm. Math. Scientia, p. 65, 11-15 and 23-24 (Festa). 
For τὸ καθόλου καὶ τὸ ἀμερές cf. Aristotle, Anal. Post. 100 Ὁ 
2; Platonic diaeresis does not extend to τὰ καθ᾽ ἕκαστα, of 
course, save in the sense of “‘ infimae species ’’ sometimes 
given this term by Aristotle (Anal. Post. 97 b 28-37, De Part. 
Animal. 642 b 35-36). 

# Of the many emendations proposed for the corrupt text 


of this clause only Bury’s, which is here adopted, has any 
plausibility in the context. 


257 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1026) τε πρὸς τὸ ἡδὺ καὶ τὸ ἀλγεινὸν αὖθις of τε τῶν 
ἐρώντων ἐνθουσιασμοὶ καὶ πτοήσεις καὶ διαμάχαι 
τοῦ φιλοκάλου πρὸς τὸ ἀκόλαστον ἐνδείκνυνται τὸ 
μικτὸν ἔκ τε τῆς θείας καὶ ἀπαθοῦς ἔκ τε τῆς 
θνητῆς καὶ περὶ τὰ σώματα παθητῆς μερίδος, ὧν 
καὶ αὐτὸς ὀνομάζει τὸ μὲν ἐπιθυμίαν ἔμφυτον 

K ἡδονῶν τὸ δ᾽ ἐπείσακτον δόξαν ἐφιεμένην τοῦ ἀρί- 
στου. τὸ γὰρ παθητικὸν ἀναδίδωσιν ἐξ ἑαυτῆς 
ἡ ψυχή, τοῦ δὲ νοῦ μετέσχεν ἀπὸ τῆς κρείττονος 


ἀρχῆς ἐγγενομένου. 
28. Τῆς δὲ διπλῆς κοινωνίας ταύτης οὐδὲ ἡ 


περὶ τὸν οὐρανὸν ἀπήλλακται φύσις, ἀλλὰ" ἑτερορ- 
ρεποῦσα νῦν μὲν ὀρθοῦται τῇ ταὐτοῦ περιόδῳ 
κράτος ἐχούσῃ καὶ διακυβερνᾷ τὸν κόσμον" ἔσται, 
δέ τις χρόνου μοῖρα καὶ γέγονεν did πολλάκις, ἐν 


1 Μ88. ; ἐγγινομένου -Aldine. ἀλλ᾽ ἡ -Τ. 
8 E, Β : ὁρᾶται -all other mss., Aldine. * ἔστοιδι 

5 See De Virtute 447 ς (οὐχ ἑνός τινος μεταβολῆς ἀλλὰ δυεῖν 
ἅμα μάχης καὶ διαφορᾶς) with Quomodo Adulator ab Amico 
Internoscatur 61 v-¥F; cf. Galen, De Placitis Hippoc. et Plat. 
iv, 7 (p. 401, 7-8 [Mueller}). 

> See 1029 τ infra (τῷ κρατίστῳ καὶ θειοτάτῳ μέρει) and 
supra 1024 a (τὸ γὰρ νοερὸν... ἐκεῖνο μὲν . . . ἀπαθὲς... 
with note a on page 215. 

¢ See 1023 ἢ supra (τὸ παθητικὸν ὑπὸ τῶν περὶ TO σῶμα 
ποιοτήτων). For this part of the human soul as mortal οὔ. 
Timaeus 61 c 7-8 and 69 c 7--Ὲ 4, where, however, it is a 
confection of the “‘ created gods ” (cf. also Timaeus 42 Ὁ 5- 
Ἑ 4) and not derived from “ the divisible being ” of the psy- 
chogony as it is according to Plutarch (see with what follows 
in this par agraph 1024 a supra [. . . οὐχ ἑτέραν οὖσαν ἢ τὴν 

. . συμπαθῆ τῷ αἰσθητῷ κίνησιν . . .]: cf. Jones, Platonism 
of Plutarch, p. 12, note 36 and p. 85, note 41). 

@ Plato, Phaedrus 237 vp 7-9, cited by Plutarch in Quaest. 
Conviv. 746 pv, where as here he writes ἐπείσακτον instead of 
Plato’s émixrnros and where he explicitly identifies the latter 


258 





GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1026 


and painful and the raptures and ecstasies of passion- 
ate lovers and the conflicts of probity with in- 
continence ὦ make plain the mixture of the divine and 
impassive part? with the part that is mortal and 
passible in the case of bodies.¢ Of these Plato him- 
self denominates the latter an innate desire of 
pleasures and the former an extraneous sentiment 
longing for what is best,4 for the soul puts forth of 
herself the affective part ὁ but partook of intelligence 
because it got into her from the superior principle.’ 

28. From this dual association the nature of the 
heavens is not exempt either; but it inclines this 
way or that, at present being kept straight by the 
dominant revolution of sameness 9 and piloting the 
universe, whereas there will be and often has already 
been a period of time in which its prudential part 
with λόγος and the former with πάθος. For the meaning of 
δόξα in this passage of the Phaedrus cf. G. J. de Vries, A 
Commentary on the Phaedrus of Plato, p. 85 ad 237 κ 2-3 
and J. Sprute, Der Begriff der Doxa in der platonischen 
Philosophie (G6ttingen, 1962), p. 113. 

¢ See 1027 a infra (σύμφυτον ἔχουσαν ἐν ἑαυτῇ THY τοῦ κακοῦ 
μοῖραν) and 1024 c supra (ἡ yap αἰσθητικὴ κίνησις, ἰδία 5 Set 
οὖσα, ...) with note f there. Contrast De Virtute Morali 
451 a (ὥσπερ ἐκ ῥίζης τοῦ παθητικοῦ τῆς σαρκὸς ἀναβλαστά- 
νοντος). 

866 1024 c supra (ὁ δὲ νοῦς... ἐγγενόμενος δὲ τῇ ψυχῇ) 
and 1023 v supra (νοῦν... αὐτῇ... ἡ τῆς νοητῆς μέθεξις 
ἀρχῆς ἐμπεποίηκε) ; and 866 also 1016 σ supra (3 Geog. ".". 
καθάπερ εἶδος... TO voe ες ἀφ᾽ αὑτοῦ παρασχὼν .. .) with 
Plat. Guasit. 1001 c an ade b t ere. There is no reason to 
suppose, however, as ‘Thévenaz does (L’ Ame du Monde, p. 
71), that by “‘ the superior principle ’’ here Plutarch meant 
τὸ ev Which in 1024 p supra he called the principle of same- 
ness ; but see infra 1027 a, note a on page 263. 

σ Cf. Timaeus 36 c 7- 1 (κράτος δ᾽ ἔδωκεν τῇ ταὐτοῦ... 
περιφορᾷ) ; on the “ revolution of sameness’ see supra 
1024 x, note d. 


259 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1026) ἧ τὸ μὲν φρόνιμον ἀμβλύνεται καὶ καταδαρθάνει 
ήθης ἐμπιπλάμενον' τοῦ οἰκείου τὸ δὲ σώματι 
σύνηθες ἐξ ἀρχῆς καὶ συμπαθὲς ἐφέλκεται καὶ 
βαρύνει καὶ ἀνελίσσει τὴν ἐν δεξιᾷ τοῦ παντὸς 
πορείαν ἀναρρῆξαι δ᾽ οὐ δύναται παντάπασιν, 

F ἀλλ᾽ ἀνήνεγκεν αὖθις τὰ βελτίω καὶ ἀνέβλεψε 
πρὸς τὸ παράδειγμα θεοῦ συνεπιστρέφοντος καὶ 

1027 συναπευθύνοντος ." οὕτως ἐνδείκνυται πολλαχόθεν 
ἡμῖν τὸ μὴ πᾶν ἔργον εἶναι θεοῦ τὴν ψυχὴν ἀλλὰ 
σύμφυτον ἐ ἔχουσαν ἐν ἑαυτῇ τὴν τοῦ κακοῦ μοῖραν 
ὑπ᾽ ἐκείνου διακεκοσμῆσθαι, τῷ μὲν ἑνὶ τὴν ἀπει- 

1 ἐμπιμπλάμενον -f, m. 


α 
2 Eeorr. (2,96, συνεπ -Ε), Β' ; συνεπευθύνοντος -all other 
Μ55.. Aldine. 


« Of. Politicus 273 c 6—p 1, quoted by Plutarch at 1015 p 
supra, and with Plutarch’s ἀμβλύνεται cf. ἀμβλύτερον in 
Politicus 273 33. In Phaedrus 248 c 7 the subject of λήθης 
τε καὶ κακίας πλησθεῖσα βαρυνθῇ is the individual soul. In 
neither case does Plato mention “ falling asleep ” ; but in 
1024 B supra (see note a there) “ dreamlike ”’ is applied to 
the precosmic soul, and Albinus speaks of the soul of the 
universe or its intelligence as being awakened by god, who 
turns it to himself (Hpitome x, 3 and xiv, 3=pp. 59, 6 
and 81, 6-7 [Louis]=pp. 165, 2 and 169, 31-33 [Hermann]). 
Cf. R. M. Jones, Class. Phil., xxi (1926), pp. 107-108; and 
J. H. Loenen, Mnemosyne, 4 Ser. x (1957), pp. 51-52, who 
argues that Albinus got this notion from Plutarch. 

> See 1024 a supra (... τὴν δοξαστικὴν . . . καὶ συμπαθῆ 
τῷ αἰσθητῷ κίνησιν... ὑφεστῶσαν ἀίδιον ort 

e Cf. Timaeus 36 ὁ 5-6 (τὴν μὲν δὴ ταὐτοῦ ... ἐπὶ δεξιὰ 
περιήγαγεν .. ., on which ¢f. ἐχιρέρνα, iv [1959], pp. 220-221 
[ + 1089) and Plutarch, De Iside 369 c (δυεῖν ἀντιπάλων δυνά- 
μεων, τῆς μὲν ἐπὶ τὰ δεξιὰ «ον ὑφηγουμένης τῆς δ᾽ ἔμπαλιν ava- 
στρεφούσης καὶ avaxAwons). 

4 Cf. Politicus 270 p 3-4 and 286 B 9, and see 1015 a 
supra with note 6 there. 

¢ For the “ pattern ’’’ see supra 1023 c (page 223, note ¢) 


260 








GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1026-1027 


becomes dull and falls asleep, filled with forgetful- 
ness of what is proper to 10,5 while the part intimate 
with body and sensitive to it from the beginning ὃ 
puts a heavy drag upon the right-hand course of the 
sum of things ὁ and rolls it back ¢ without being able, 
however, to disrupt it entirely, but the better part 
recovers again and looks up at the pattern ὁ when god 
helps with the turning and guidance.f Thus many 
considerations make it plain to us that the soul is not 
god’s work entirely 9 but that with the portion of evil 
inherent in her” she has been arranged by god, who 


and cf. Plato, Republic 540 a 7-9 of the individual soul. The 
“ pattern ” here for Plutarch is not god or the “ thoughts of 
god” (cf. Jones, Platonism of Plutarch, p. 102, note 72), 
whereas according to Albinus in Epitome xiv, 3 (p. 81, 6-9 
{Louis]=p. 169, 31-35 [Hermann]}) the soul or its intelligence 
is awakened by god ὅπως ἀποβλέπουσα πρὸς τὰ νοητὰ αὐτοῦ 
δέχηται τὰ εἴδη καὶ τὰς μορφάς, ἐφιεμένη τῶν ἐκείνου νοημάτων 
(cf. in x, 3, p. 59, 2-4 [Louis]=p. 164, 35-37 [Hermann]). 

7 Cf. Politicus 269 c 4-6 (τὸ πᾶν τόδε τοτὲ μὲν αὐτὸς ὁ θεὸς 
συμποδηγεῖ πορευόμενον καὶ συγκυκλεῖ.. . .). 270 a 3, and 273 
E 1-4; and Republic 617 c 5-7 (τὴν μὲν Κλωθὼ τῇ δεξιᾷ χειρὶ 
ἐφαπτομένην ovvemiorpepe . . . THY ἔξω wensgnnts Plutarch 
in De Defectu Orac. 426 c speaks of the gods τῶν κόσμων... 
τῇ φύσει συναπευθύνοντας ἕκαστον. In the present passage the 
unexpressed object.of συνεπιστρέφοντος καὶ συναπευθύνοντος iS 
to be understood from 77. . . τοῦ παντὸς πορείαν supra, though 
the phrase has sometimes been interpreted in the light of 
eis ἑαυτὸν ἐπιστρέφει (1024 D supra with note a there) as 
“ conversion ”’ of the soul or intelligence itself (Jones, Platon- 
ism of Plutarch, p. 83, note 35; Witt, Albinus, p. 131; 
‘Thévenaz, L’ Ame du Monde, p. 72). In De Iside 376 B it is 
the rational motion of the universe itself that ἐπιστρέφει ποτὲ 


καὶ προσάγεται... πείθουσα τὴν... τυφώνειον εἶτ᾽ αὖθις... 
ἀνέστρεψε. . .. 
od See 1014 c and 1016 c cited in note f, page 223 supra ; 


cf. J. H. Loenen, Mnemosyne, 4 Ser. x (1957), p. 47. 
h See supra 1026 © (with note 6 there), 1015 a (with note f 
there) and 1015 ἘἙ. 
261 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1027) ρίαν ὁρίσαντος wv’ οὐσία γένηται πέρατος pera- 
σχοῦσα τῇ δὲ ταὐτοῦ καὶ τῇ ἑτέρου' δυνάμει τάξιν 
“αἱ μεταβολὴν καὶ διαφορὰν καὶ ὁμοιότητα συμμί- 
ξαντος πᾶσι δὲ τούτοις, ὡς ἀνυστὸν ἦν, κοινωνίαν 
πρὸς ἄλληλα καὶ φιλίαν epyacapevou δι᾽ ἀριθμῶν 
καὶ ἁρμονίας. 

29. Ilepi ὧν εἰ καὶ πολλάκις ἀκηκόατε καὶ πολ- 
λοῖς ἐντετυχήκατε λόγοις καὶ γράμμασιν, οὐ χεῖρόν 
ἐστι κἀμὲ βραχέως διελθεῖν, προεκθέμενον τὸ τοῦ 

Β Πλάτωνος" “'᾿μίαν ἀφεῖλε τὸ" πρῶτον ἀπὸ παντὸς 
μοῖραν, μετὰ δὲ ταύτην ἀφήρει διπλασίαν ταύτης, 
τὴν δ᾽ αὖ τρίτην ἡμιολίαν μὲν τῆς δευτέρας τρι- 
πλασίαν δὲ τῆς πρώτης, τετάρτην δὲ τῆς δευτέρας 
διπλῆν, “πέμπτην δὲ τριπλῆν τῆς τρίτης, τὴν δὲ" 
ἕκτην τῆς πρώτης ὀκταπλασίαν, ἑβδόμην de* ἑπτα- 
καιεικοσαπλασίαν᾽" τῆς πρώτης. μετὰ δὲ ταῦτα 
συνεπληροῦτο τά τε διπλάσια καὶ τριπλάσια δια- 
στήματα, μοίρας ἔτι ἐκεῖθεν ἀποτέμνων καὶ τιθεὶς 
εἰς τὸ μεταξὺ τούτων, ὥστ᾽ ἐν ἑκάστῳ διαστήματι 
δύο εἶναι μεσότητας, τὴν μὲν ταὐτῷ μέρει τῶν 
ἄκρων αὐτῶν ὑπερέχουσαν καὶ ὑπερεχομένην τὴν 

Ο δ᾽ ἴσῳ μὲν κατ᾽ ἀριθμὸν ὑπερέχουσαν ἴσῳ δὲ ὑπερ- 

θάτέρου -Mau. 

B. Miller (1873) from Timaeus 35 wn 4: ἀφείλετο -Mss. 
τῆς δὲ -e, u, Escor. 72}. 

τὴν δὲ ἑβδόμην δὲ -E 3 τὴν δὲ ἑβδόμην -B. 


f (but with ¢ instead of a before 7), m, r; ἑπτακαιεικο- 
σαπλασίω -E, B; ἑπτὰ καὶ εἰκοσαπλασίω -e, τι, Escor. 72, 


Aldine. 


aor ὦ NM μὸ 


9 See supra 1014 Ὁ ΡΘΗ 185, note a), the end of chap. 26 
(1026 A with note 6 there), and τοῦ ἑνὸς ὁρίζοντος τὸ πλῆθος 
καὶ τῇ ἀπειρίᾳ πέρας ἐντιθέντος (1012 © supra) in the Xeno- 
cratean interpretation of the psychogony, which Plutarch 


262 





GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1027 


with the one bounded her infinitude that by par- 
ticipation in limit it might become substance ὦ and 
through the agency of sameness and of difference 
commingled order and change and differentiation 
and similarity ὃ and in all these produced, so far as 
was feasible, amity and union with one another by 
means of numbers and concord.°¢ 

29. These last, though you have often heard and 
read much talk and writing on the subject, it is as 
well for me to explain briefly too after giving Plato’s 
passage ὦ as a preface: © T‘irst from the total amount 
he subtracted one portion, and thereafter he sub- 
tracted one twice as large as this, and then the third 
half as large again as the second and three times the 
first, and the fourth double of the second, and the 
fifth triple of the third, and the sixth eight times the 
first, and the seventh twenty-seven times the first. 
After that he filled in the double and triple intervals 
by putting in between the former portions portions 
that he continued to cut off from that original source 
so as to have in each interval two means, one that 
exceeds and falls short of the extremes by the same 
fraction of them and one that exceeds and falls short 


rejects (1013 c-p and 1023 v supra) but from this part of 
which his own present formulation differs only in that the 
product for Xenocrates was ἀριθμός while for him it is now 
οὐσία. It is noteworthy moreover that in 1024 p supra (see 
note f there) Plutarch in opposition to the Xenocratean in- 
terpretation declared τὸ ἕν to be the principle of sameness as 
distinguished from the ἀμέριστος οὐσία of the psychogony. 

> See supra 1024 κε (with note ὁ there) and 1025 F. 

¢ See supra 1013 c (page 175, note c). 

ἃ Timaeus 35 Β 4—36 B 5, which follows immediately the 
passage quoted by Plutarch at the beginning of this essay, 
1012 B-c supra. 


263 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1027) ἐχομένην." ἡμιολίων δὲ διαστάσεων καὶ ἐπιτρίτων 
καὶ ἐπογδόων γενομένων ἐκ τούτων τῶν δεσμῶν ἐν 
ταῖς πρόσθεν διαστάσεσι, τῷ τοῦ ἐπογδόου διαστή- 
ματι τὰ ἐπίτριτα πάντα συνεπληροῦτο λείπων" αὐ- 
τῶν ἑκάστου μόριον, τῆς τοῦ" μορίου ταύτης δια- 
στάσεως λειφθείσης" ἀριθμοῦ πρὸς ἀριθμὸν ἐ ἐχούσης 


τοὺς ὅρους ἐξ καὶ πεντήκοντα καὶ διακοσίων" πρὸς 
τρία" καὶ τετταράκοντα καὶ διακόσια. ἐν τούτοις 


ζητεῖται πρῶτον περὶ τῆς ποσότητος τῶν ἀριθμῶν, 
δεύτερον περὶ τῆς τάξεως, τρίτον περὶ τῆς δυνά- 
\ \ a / ees ΑΔ > 

pews? περὶ μὲν τῆς ποσότητος τίνες εἰσίν, οὗς ἐν 
τοῖς διπλασίοις καὶ τριπλασίοις" διαστήμασι λαμ- 
͵ 4 \ — r ͵, 2979 εν ͵ 
D βάνει: περὶ δὲ τῆς" τάξεως πότερον ἐφ᾽ ἑνὸς στί- 
10 ΄ πὰ f ς , BD a ς 
you” πάντας" ἐκθετέον ὡς Θεόδωρος ἢ μᾶλλον ὡς 
Κράντωρ ἐν τῷ A” σχήματι, τοῦ πρώτου κατὰ 
κορυφὴν τιθεμένου καὶ χωρὶς μὲν τῶν διπλασίων 
χωρὶς δὲ τῶν τριπλασίων ἐν δυσὶ" στίχοις" ὑὕποτατ- 


1 τὴν μὲν ταὐτῷ. .. ἴσῳ δὲ ὑπερεχομένην -f, m, r (but with 
ἄκρων repeated and ὑ ὑπερέχουσαν ἴσῳ δὲ omitted by r), Timaeus 
36 43-53 καὶ ὑπερεχομένην τὴν δ᾽ ἴσῳ μὲν Kar’ ἀριθμὸν ὑ ὑπερέχου- 
σαν -omitted by e, U, Escor. 72, Aldine ; ; τὴν μὲν ἑκατέρῳ τῶν 
ἄκρων ἴσῳ τε ὑπερέχουσαν καὶ ὑπερεχομένην τὴν δὲ ταὐτῷ μέρει 
τῶν ἄκρων αὐτῶν ὑπερέχουσαν καὶ ὑπερεχομένην 

2 Dibner from Timaeus 36 B 1-2 (A), see 1020. B infra (f, 
m, r) and Proclus (In Platonis Timaeum ii, pp. 227, 30 and 
230, 8 [Diehl]); συνεπλήρου τὸ λεῖπον -E, B, 6, ucor- 
(συνεπλῆρον τὸ λειπὸν -u"), Escor. 723 συνεπλήρου λείπων -f, 
m, ©. 8 τῆς δὲ τοῦ -f, τὴ, r 

4 ληφθείσης -E, B* (ει superscript over first ἡ --ϑοστ.), 
Proclus (In Platonis Timaeum ii, Ὁ. 230, 29 { Diehl]). 

oe Kal ν καὶ σ -Β. § zpia -omitted by f. 

7 πρὸς γ καὶ μ καὶ o -Β. 

8. καὶ τριπλασίοις -omitted by ἐπ f, πὶ, r, Escor. 72, 
Aldine. 9. τῆς -omitted by e, u 

10 στείχου -U (cf. ad ἐν δυσὶ στίχοις infra). 

1 EK, B; πάντα -all other mss., Aldine. 


264 








GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1027 


by amounts numerically equal.? Since as a result of 
these links in the previous intervals there came to be 
intervals of three to two and of four to three and of 
nine to eight, he filled in all the intervals of four to 
three with the interval of nine to eight leaving a 
fraction of each of them, this remaining interval of 
the fraction having the terms of the numerical ratio 
256 to 248. ὃ Here the first question is concerned 
with the quantity, the second with the arrangement, 
the third with the function of the numbers ¢: con- 
cerning the quantity what numbers they are that he 
adopts in the double and triple intervals, concerning 
the arrangement whether one is to set them out as 
Theodorus ὦ does all in a single row or rather as 
Crantor ὁ does in the figure of a lambda with the 
first placed at the apex and the double and triple 
numbers ranged separately from each other in two 

* The former is the harmonic mean and the latter the 
arithmetical mean (see 1019 c-& and 1028 a infra). 

> For the procedure described and the numerical values 
resulting from it cf. B. Kytzler, Hermes, Ixxxvii (1959), 
pp. 405-406. 

¢ Three but not quite the same three questions are posed 
by Chalcidius, Platonis Timaeus, pp. 99, 17-100, 2 (Wrobel) = 
p. 83, 20-27 (Waszink) ; cf. B. W. Switalski, Des Chalcidius 
Kommentar zu Plato’s Timaeus (Miinster, 1902), pp. 81-82. 

4 Theodorus of Soli; see chap. 20 (1022 c-p) infra and 
De Defectu Orac. 427 a-x. 

ε Crantor, frag. 7 (Kayser)=frag. 7 (Mullach, Frag. 
Philos. Graec. iii, p. 145) ; see chap. 20 (1022 c-x) infra, and 
for Crantor as the first exegete of Plato see 1012 pb, note ς 
supra. 


12 λάμβδα -E, B. 

18. ἐν τρισὶ -Ὁ΄ 

14 στείχοις -u (cf. ad στίχου supra and 1022 c infra: δύο 
στίχους [στοίχους -f, τη, r]). 


265 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


4 \ \ “~ / \ πιὰ ld / 
(1027) τομένων’ περὶ δὲ τῆς χρείας καὶ τῆς δυνάμεως τί 
ποιοῦσι παραλαμβανόμενοι πρὸς τὴν σύστασιν τῆς 
ψυχῆς. | 
“-.μ > \ ~ / , 
30. Πρῶτον οὖν περὶ τοῦ πρώτου παραιτησό- 
μεθα' τοὺς λέγοντας ὡς ἐπὶ τῶν λόγων αὐτῶν 
ἀπόχρη θεωρεῖν ἣν ἔχει τά τε διαστήματα φύσιν 
αἵ τε ταῦτα συμπληροῦσαι μεσότητες, ἐν οἷς ἄν τις 
ἀριθμοῖς ὑπόθηται χώρας ἔχουσι δεκτικὰς" μεταξὺ 
τῶν εἰρημένων ἀναλογιῶν ὁμοίως περαινομένης 
EK τῆς διδασκαλίας. Kav γὰρ ἀληθὲς" 7 τὸ λεγόμε- 
νον, ἀμυδρὰν ποιεῖ τὴν μάθησιν ἄνευ παραδειγ- 
μάτων ἄλλης τε θεωρίας ἀπείργει χάριν ἐχούσης 
’ > Υ nn oo > \ A ’ 9 / 
οὐκ ἀφιλόσοφον. ἂν οὖν ἀπὸ τῆς μονάδος apéa- 
μενοι τοὺς διπλασίους καὶ τριπλασίους ἐν μέρει τι- 
θῶμεν, ὡς αὐτὸς ὑφηγεῖται, γενήσονται κατὰ TO° 
ἑξῆς ὅπου μὲν τὰ δύο καὶ τέσσαρα καὶ ὀκτὼ" ὅπου 
δὲ τρία καὶ ἐννέα καὶ εἰκοσιεπτά,Ϊ συνάπαντες μὲν 
1 ἀπαραιτησόμεθα -e, ἃ (ap Cancelled -uct-), Escor. 72 
(ἀπαιτησόμεθα -in margin) ; ἀπαρτησόμεθα -Aldine. 
2 δέ τινας -e1 (corrected 635), τι. 
35 Ἐν, Bs καὶ γὰρ ἂν ἀληθὲς -e, f, m, r, Escor. 72, Aldine; 


Kal yap ἀληθὲς -u. 
4K, B; ἀφηγεῖται -e, u, f, τὰ, Escor. 72, Aldine; 


ow 
ὑφηγεῖται -¥. 

5 τὸ -Wyttenbach; τὸν -E, B, e, u, Escor. 72, Aldine; 
τοὺς -f, τὰ, τ. 

6 +a δύο καὶ τὰ τέσσαρα καὶ ὀκτὼ -Maurommates (so also 
the versions of Xylander and Amyot); τὸ δεύτερον καὶ τὸ 


τέταρτον καὶ ὄγδοον -MSS. 
7 τρία καὶ ἐννέα καὶ εἰκοσιεπτά -Maurommates (so also the 


versions of Xylander and Amyot) ; τρίτον καὶ ἔνατον (ἔννατον 
-E, B) καὶ εἰκοστοέβδομον -Μ88. 


266 











GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1027 


rows underneath, and concerning their use or func- 
tion what effect is produced by their employment for 
the composition of the soul. 

30. First, then, with regard to the first question 
we shall decline to follow those who say® that it 
suffices to observe in the ratios themselves the nature 
of the intervals and of the means with which they 
are filled in, as the directions are carried out alike 
with whatever numbers one may assume that have 
spaces between them to receive the prescribed pro- 
portions.? Our reason is that, even if what they say 
be true, by the absence of examples it obscures the 
understanding of the subject © and debars us from 
another speculation that has a charm not unphilo- 
sophical.4 So, if beginning from the unit we place 
the double and triple numbers alternately’ as 
indicated by Plato himself,f the result will be in 
succession on one side two, four, and eight and on 
the other side three, nine, and twenty-seven, seven 


¢ Perhaps Eudorus, following Crantor (see 1020 c-p 
infra). 

> See 1020 a infra (. . . τῶν αὐτῶν λόγων διαμενόντων, ὑπο- 
δοχὰς ποιοῦσιν ἀρκούσας ...) and 1020 v infra (λόγον μὲν ἔχον 
τὸν αὐτὸν ἀριθμὸν δὲ τὸν διπλάσιον): and with the latter cf. 
Theon Smyrnaeus, p. 69, 7-9 (Hiller) in the same context : 
οὐδὲν δὲ κωλύει καὶ ἐφ᾽ ἑτέρων ἀριθμῶν τὸν αὐτὸν εὑρίσκειν λόγον 

. οὐ γὰρ ἀριθμὸν ὡρισμένον ἔλαβεν ὁ Ἰ]λάτων ἀλλὰ λόγον 
ἀριθμοῦ. 

¢ Cf. eg. Plato, Politicus 277 υ 1-2. 

@ i.e. the arithmological speculations about the ‘‘ remark- 
able numbers ”’ (1017 &© infra), to which Plutarch devotes 
most of the next three chapters (cf. Burkert, Weisheit und 
Wissenschaft, p. 375, n. 59). 

¢ See 1017 © infra (ἐναλλὰξ καὶ ἰδίᾳ τάττεσθαι... τοὺς ap- 
tious . . . Kal πάλιν τοὺς περιττούς. 

f See 1017 © infra (ἧ καὶ δῆλός ἐστι βουλόμενος... .) and 
1027 r—1028 a infra (μονονουχὶ δεικνύων ἡμῖν... .). 


267 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1027) ἑπτὰ κοινῆς δὲ λαμβανομένης τῆς μονάδος ἄχρι 
τεσσάρων' τῷ πολλαπλασιασμῷ προιόντες ." οὐ 
43 
γὰρ ἐνταῦθα μόνον ἀλλὰ πολλαχόθι τῆς τετράδος ἡ 
Ε πρὸς τὴν ἑβδομάδα συμπάθεια γίγνεται κατάδηλος. 
7 μὲν οὖν ὑπὸ τῶν Πυθαγορικῶν ὑ ὑμνουμένη τετρα- 
κτύς, τὰ ἕξ καὶ τριάκοντα, θαυμαστὸν ἔχειν δοκεῖ 
> συγκεῖσθαι μὲν ἐκ πρώτων ἀρτίων τεσσάρων 
καὶ πρώτων περιττῶν τεσσάρων γίγνεσθαι" δὲ συ- 
ζυγία τετάρτη τῶν ἐφεξῆς συντιθεμένων. πρώτη 
μὲν γάρ ἐστι συζυγία ἣ τοῦ ἑνὸς καὶ τῶν δυεῖν 
1017 C δευτέρα (11. δὲ ΠΕ τῶν εριῶν" καὶ τεσσάρων" 
D τρίτη δὲ ἡ τῶν €' καὶ ς΄, wy” οὐδεμία ποιεῖ τετρά- 
γωνον οὔτ᾽ αὐτὴ καθ᾽ a οὔτε μετὰ τῶν ἄλλων: 
e \ ~ , \ 7Ὰ13 , , 9 t 
{7 δὲ τῶν ζ΄ καὶ η΄)" τετάρτη μέν ἐστι συντιθεμένη 
1 mss. 3 τεσσα ixovra in margin of f, τη, r. 
ὁ προιόντες - aurommates ; προιόντων -MSS. 


ἢ -f, m, Aldine. 
‘ oa τριάκοντα -B (cf. De Iside 381 F—382a) : καὶ τὰ 
τριάκοντα -4}} other mss. 5 ὦ -f, m, Fr. 


6 γίνεται -f, m, τ, Aldine. 

7 EB, B, ef. De Iside 382 a ; συντεθειμένων -all other mss, 
Aldine. 8 ἐστι -omitted by r. 

® δευτέρα περιττῶν (chap. 30 Ὁ [1027 Ὁ] infra) -E, B; 
δευτέρα (δευτέρα δὲ -Ε) τῶν περιττῶν -f, m, r, Aldine ; δεύγερμε 
τῶν -ε,α, Escor. 72 (ρατῶνπε -Escor. 72 in margin) ; see 1022 
Ἑ supra (chap. 21 init. ), apparatus criticus, page 212, note 2. 

10 δὲ ἡ τῶν τριῶν -all Mss., following 1017 c supra (chap. 10 


ad finem): κόσμον . . . vac. 4-E, vac. 8 -Β ; xoopov... vac. 
5 -f, m, vac. 3 - eee ev ene vac, 4. ove -f, mM, rT 3 κόσμον . ἔνθαϊ 
-e, ἃ ; κόσμον. ev... vac. ῶ.... -Εδβοοτ. 72; see 1022 Ἐ 


supra (chap. 91 init.), apparatus criticus, page 212, note 2. 
1 τεσσάρων St ne aa (τετράδος -Xylander); καὶ μιᾶς 
-MSS. (μιᾶς. . . vac. 3... -E with illegible correction in 
margin). 12 καὶ -F. 
18 <q δὲ τῶν ζ΄ καὶ η΄) -added by Maurommates; «ζ΄ καὶ 
n’> added after τετάρτη μέν ἐστι ~Xylander, and similarly 
Amyot’s version. 


268 











GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1027, 1017 


numbers in all but, the unit being taken as common,” 
progressing to four by multiplication.2. Not only 
here, in fact, but in many cases does the affinity of 
the tetrad with the hebdomad become manifest.° 
So thirty-six, the tetractys celebrated by the Pytha- 
goreans, is thought to have a remarkable property 
in being the sum of the first four even and the first 
four odd numbers and in coming to be as the fourth 
pair of the successive numbers added together ὦ : for 
the first pair is that of one and two and the second 
(11.) that of three and four and the third that of five 
and six, none of which pairs either by itself or to- 
gether with the others produces a square number ; 
<but that of seven and eight) is the fourth, and being 


@ See infra 1017 vb (τὴν μὲν μονάδα, κοινὴν οὖσαν ἀρχὴν . . .), 
1018 ¥F (ἡ μονὰς ἐπίκοινος οὖσα .. .), 1027 F (τὴν yap μονάδα 
κοινὴν οὖσαν ἀμφοῖν προτάξας... .); cf. Chalcidius, Platonis 
Timaeus, Ὁ. 104, 20 (Wrobel)=pp. 87, 26-88, 1 (Waszink) : 
** communi videlicet accepta singularitate.” 

> Cf. Theon Smyrnaeus, p. 95, 2-13 (Hiller). 

¢ Cf. Philo Jud., Quaestiones in Exodum ii, 87 (p. 527 
{Aucher]=p. 137 (L.C.L.]) and De Specialibus Legibus ii, 
40 (v, p. 95, 15-20 [Cohn]); Nicomachus, Hacerpta 6 
(Musici Scriptores Graeci, p. 277, 18-19 [Jan]) and Nico- 
machus in Iamblichus, Theolog. Arith., Ὁ. 58, 10-19 and 
p. 59, 10-18 (De Falco). 

4 Cf. De Iside 381 Fr—382 a; Chalcidius, Platonis 
Timaeus, p. 104, 10-15 (Wrobel)=p. 87, 19-22 (Waszink) ; 
Philo Jud., Quaestiones in Genesin iii, 49 (p. 233 [Aucher]= 
pp. 247-248 [D.C.L.]). In all these passages, as here, one is 
explicitly an odd number (cf. Theon Smyrnaeus, pp. 21, 
24-22, 5 [Hiller]; Speusippus, frag. 4, 22-25 [Lang]), 
whereas for Plutarch ordinarily three is the first odd number 
(see 1018 c infra: ... ἔκ τε τῆς ἀρχῆς Kal... τοῦ πρώτου 
περιττοῦ). For 36 as the sum of a “ tetractys ” formed in a 
different way cf. Nicomachus, Excerpta 7 and 10 (Musici 
Scriptores Graeci, pp. 279, 8-15 and 282, 10-14 [Jan]); and 
for the special properties of 36 see 1018 c-p infra. 


269 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1017) δὲ ταῖς προτέραις tpraxovraeé’ τετράγωνον παρ- 


, e δὲ ~ e \ / > , 3 
ἔσχεν. ἡ δὲ τῶν ὑπὸ Π]λάτωνος ἐκκειμένων ἀριθ- 
- A > , ” ; \ / 
μῶν τετρακτὺς ἐντελεστέραν ἔσχηκε THY γένεσιν, 
~ \ 9 , 3 ὔ , ~ 4 
τῶν μὲν ἀρτίων ἀρτίοις διαστήμασι τῶν δὲ περιτ- 
τῶν περιττοῖς πολλαπλασιασθέντων: περιέχει δὲ 
λ 2 
τὴν μὲν μονάδα, κοινὴν" οὖσαν ἀρχὴν ἀρτίων καὶ 
περιττῶν, τῶν δὲ ὑπ᾽ αὐτῇ τὰ μὲν δύο καὶ τρία 
πρώτους ἐπιπέδους, τὰ δὲ" τέσσαρα καὶ ἐννέα πρώ- 
τους τετραγώνους, τὰ δ᾽ ὀκτὼ καὶ εἰκοσιεπτὰ 
7 ΄, . | a, ~ ” , o , 
πρώτους κύβους ev* ἀριθμοῖς, ἔξω λόγου τῆς μονά- 
, 5 - \ a ee , > 
dos τιθεμένης.“ ἡ Kal δῆλός ἐστι βουλόμενος οὐκ 
ἐπὶ μιᾶς εὐθείας ἅπαντας ἀλλ᾽ ἐναλλὰξ καὶ ἰδίᾳ 
’ \ 3 ,ὔ 3 3 ’, \ ’, 
τάττεσθαι τοὺς ἀρτίους μετ᾽ ἀλλήλων καὶ πάλιν 
τοὺς περιττούς, ὡς" ὑπογέγραπται. οὕτως αἱ 
συζυγίαι τῶν ὁμοίων ἔσονται πρὸς τοὺς ὁμοίους 


1 προτέραις τριακονταὲξ -Diibner; προ. .. vac. 9... τ 
. vac. 3... τριάκοντα, εἰ (ἐξ. -B)... . vac. νον « rerpa- 

γωνον -Ἰὰ, Bs πρώταις τριάκοντα ἐξ (As -f, m, r) τετράγωνον -all 
other mss., Aldine. 

2 κοινὴν -omitted by r. 
τὰ δὲ τὰ δὲ -B. 
ev -omitted by r. 
θεμένης -f, m, τ, Aldine. 
ws -Xylander (so Amyot’s version); καὶ -MSS.; ws καὶ 
-B. Miller (1873). 

7 The figure as below in the margins of Εἰ, e, τι, Escor. 72 ; 
A with the same numbers in the margins of B, f, m; omitted 
altogether by r and Aldine (see page 272 infra). 


ον me ᾧᾧ 








α Yor the term “ tetractys ” used of this figure cf. Theon 
Smyrnaeus, p. 94, 12-14 and p. 95, 2-8 (Hiller) and Chal- 
cidius, Platonis Timaeus, Ὁ. 104, 15-22 (Wrobel)=pp. 87, 
29-88, 2 (Waszink): “‘. .. quadratura cognominatur quia 
continet quattuor quidem limites in duplici latere. ...” 


270 














GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1017 


added to the preceding pairs it gives thirty-six, a 
square number. The tetractys of the numbers set out 
by Plato,t however, has been generated in a more 
consummate way,” the multiplication of the even by 
even intervals and of the odd by odd ; and it contains 
the unit, to be sure, as being the common principle 
of even and odd numbers,°¢ but of the numbers under 
the unit contains two and three, the first plane 
numbers,? and four and nine, the first square num- 
bers, and eight and twenty-seven, the first cubic 
numbers,’ the unit being left out of account, which 
makes it quite obvious that he wishes 7 them to be 
arranged not all in one straight line but alternately, 
that is the even numbers together by themselves and 
on the other hand the odd numbers as drawn below.’ 
In this way numbers that are similar to one another 


> See 1019 8 infra (chap. 14 sub finem): ὥστε πολὺ τῆς 
Πυθαγορικῆς . . . τελειοτέραν. 

¢ Cf. Theon Smyrnaeus, p. 94, 15-16 (Hiller) and Chal- 
cidius, Platonis Timaeus, p. 104, 24-25 (Wrobel)=p. 88, 
3-4 (Waszink). 

@ See also 1022 ἢ infra (ἐπιπέδων ἐπιπέδοις . . .) and De 
Defectu Orac. 415 ©, where in the same context two and 
three are referred to as ‘‘ the first two plane numbers.” 
According to Nicomachus (Arithmetica Introductio 11, vii, 3 
[pp. 86, 21-87, 7, Hoche]) the plane numbers begin with 
three ; and Theon Smyrnaeus in this context calls both two 
and three “‘ linear’ (p. 95, 17-19 [Hiller], cf. p. 23, 11-14), 
although elsewhere he calls two itself “ oblong” (p. 31, 
15-17). In De Jside 367 Ἐ-τ Plutarch himself treats square 
and oblong numbers as species of plane numbers. 

¢ For the expression, ἐπιπέδους . . . τετραγώνους . . . KU- 
Bous ἐν ἀριθμοῖς, cf. lamblichus, Theolog. Arith., p. 82, 17 (De 
Faleco)=Speusippus, frag. 4, 8-9 (Lang). 

f See 1027 Ἑ supra with note / there. 

9 i.e. in accordance with Crantor’s interpretation (see 
1027 » supra with note e there), page 273 infra. 


271 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1017) καὶ ποιήσουσιν ἀριθμοὺς ἐπιφανεῖς κατά TE’ σύν- 
θεσιν. καὶ πολλαπλασιασμὸν ἐξ ἀλλήλων. 





Lf 


4 
12. Kara σύνθεσιν οὕτως" τὰ δύο Kat τὰ τρία" 
Ἁ / / 
πέντε γίγνεται, τὰ τέσσαρα καὶ τὰ ἐννέα" τριακαί- 
> \ 3 4 / A 
δεκα, τὰ δ᾽ ὀκτὼ Kal εἰκοσιεπτὰ πέντε καὶ τριά- 
Ν A A ς 
κοντα. τούτων γὰρ τῶν ἀριθμῶν οἱ Πυθαγορικοὶ 
, ¢ > \ , > 4 
τὰ μὲν πέντε τρόμον," ὅπερ ἐστὶ φθόγγον," ἐκά- 
“ ~ , ~ 
F λουν, οἰόμενοι τῶν τοῦ τόνου διαστημάτων πρῶτον 
\ \ , 7 \ \ 
εἶναι φθεγκτὸν τὸ πέμπτον. τὰ δὲ τριακαίδεκα 
aA δ ta \ 3 ww “ , 
λεῖμμα, καθάπερ IlAatwv τὴν εἰς toa τοῦ τόνου 
4 \ \ [4 A 4 
διανομὴν ἀπογιγνώσκοντες, TA δὲ πέντε καὶ τριά- 
1 +¢ -omitted by f, m, r, Escor. 72. 
2 καὶ τρία -f, m, Fr. 3 καὶ ἐννέα -f, m, r, Aldine. 
4 Aldine; cy -E, B, ἢ, m,r3 τρισκαίδεκα -e, ἃ, Escor. 72. 
5 Tannery (Mémoires Scientifiques ix [1929], pp. 379- 
380) ; τροφόν -Mss. δ φθόγγου -u. 
7 τὸ πέμπτον -omitted by B : τὸν πέμπτον -f, mer, 


9 See 1022 Ὁ infra (chap. 20 sub finem): ἐπιπέδων ἐπιπέδοις 
... συζυγούντων, and page 253, note d supra. 

» Despite the “ five tetrachords ”’ of 1029 a-s infra and 
the musical significance ascribed to five in De E 389 p-F 
and De Defectu Orac. 430 a there is to my knowledge no 
relevant parallel to this enigmatic passage ; and in default 
of one I adopt Tannery’s emendation and explanation as the 
most plausible yet suggested, adding only that the use of 
τόνος alone as here for ‘“‘ mode”’ or “ scale”’ is well estab- 


272 








GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1017 


will form the pairs* and both by addition and by 
multiplication with each other will produce remark- 
able numbers. 





12. By addition as follows: two plus three are 
five, four plus nine are thirteen, and eight plus 
twenty-seven are thirty-five. These numbers are 
remarkable, for of them the Pythagoreans called five 
“tremor,” which is to say “sound,” thinking that 
the fifth of the scale’s intervals is first to be sounded,? 
called thirteen “ leimma,” denying as did Plato that 
the tone is divisible into equal parts,’ and called 


lished (cf. De E 389 τ [... τοὺς πρώτους εἴτε τόνους ἢ τρόπους 
εἴθ᾽ ἁρμονίας χρὴ καλεῖν. . .] ; Cleonides, Introductio 12 
[ Musici Scriptores Graeci, pp. 202, 6-8 and 203, 4-6, Jan] ; 
Porphyry, Jn Ptolemaet Harmonica, Ὁ. 82, 3-6 [Diiring}), 
though it is disturbing to find it used in a different sense in 
the very next clause. For a different interpretation of τὸ 
πέμπτον cf. H. Weil et Th. Reinach, Plutarque : Dela Mu- 
sique (Paris, 1900), p. Lv1, note 5, 

¢ See 1018 & infra with note ὦ there (. . διὸ καὶ τὰ τρια- 
καίδεκα λεῖμμα καλοῦσιν .. .) and 1020 Ἐ-- infra (. . . οἱ δὲ 
Πυθαγορικοὶ τὴν μὲν εἰς toa τομὴν ἀπέγνωσαν αὐτοῦ... ... AS 
for καθάπερ Πλάτων, I take it with what follows (see 1021 
Ὁ-Ἑ infra [. . . καὶ τοῦτ᾽ ἐστὶν 6 φησιν ὁ Πλάτων . . .]), giving 
Plutarch the benefit of the doubt, for Plato did not “ call 
thirteen ‘ leimma,’”’ although some said that he had done 
so (cf. Theon Smyrnaeus, p. 69, 4-6 [Hiller]). 


273 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1017) κοντα ἁρμονίαν, ὅτι συνέστηκεν ἐκ δυεῖν κύβων 
πρώτων' ἀπ᾽ ἀρτίου καὶ περιττοῦ γεγονότων ἐκ 
/ > ~ a ~ ~ 
τεσσάρων δ᾽ ἀριθμῶν, τοῦ ς΄ καὶ τοῦ η΄ καὶ τοῦ 6 
A A \ \ 
καὶ τοῦ" ιβ΄, τὴν ἀριθμητικὴν καὶ τὴν ἁρμονικὴν 
1018 ἀναλογίαν περιεχόντων. ἔσται δὲ" “μᾶλλον ἡ, δύ- 
ναμις ἐκφανὴς ἐπὶ διαγράμματος. ἔστωτὸ αβγδὃ 
παραλληλόγραμμον ὀρθογώνιον ἔχον τῶν πλευρῶν 
τὴν a βὶ πέντε τὴν δὲ α ὃ ἑπτά: καὶ τμηθείσης τῆς 
μὲν ἐλάττονος εἰς δύο καὶ τρία κατὰ τὸ κ τῆς δὲ 
μείζονος εἰς τρία καὶ τέσσαρα κατὰ τὸ A διήχθωσαν 
ἀπὸ τῶν τομῶν εὐθεῖαι τέμνουσαι ἀλλήλας κατὰ τὸ 
K wv καὶ κατὰ TOA μ E καὶ ποιοῦσαι τὸ μὲν a κ 
war’ ἐξ τὸ δὲ κ B E μὲ ἐννέα τὸ δὲ X μ ν ὃ ὀκτὼ τὸ 
δὲ μ Ey v δώδεκα τὸ δὲ ὅλον παραλληλόγραμ- 
μον τριάκοντα καὶ πέντε, τοὺς τῶν συμφωνιῶν 
τῶν πρώτων λόγους ἐν τοῖς τῶν χωρίων ἀριθμοῖς 
Β εἰς ἃ διήρηται περιέχον. τὰ μὲν γὰρ" ἐξ καὶ ὀκτὼ 
τὸν ἐπίτριτον ἔχει λόγον, ἐν ᾧ τὸ διὰ τεσσάρων, 
τὰ δὲ ἕξ καὶ ἐννέα τὸν ἡμιόλιον, ἐν ᾧ τὸ διὰ πέντε, 
ΤΥ, \ (168 , Το \ - 
τὰ δὲ ἕξ καὶ ιβ΄" τὸν διπλάσιον, ἐν ᾧ τὸ διὰ πασῶν. 
πρῶτον Ὕ. 
τοῦ -omitted by E, Β, 6, Escor. 72, Aldine. 
δὲ -omitted by B. 
ἡ -omitted by ἢ 
Aus -r. 
ποιοῦσαι -omitted by ἢ, r3 καὶ ποιοῦσαι ... τὸ δὲ κβξμ 
-omitted by e, u, Escor. 72, m (καὶ [ποιοῦσαι omitted] τὸ μὲν 
ακλμ ἕξ τὸ δὲ ΧΡ ΙΣ -m? in margin), Aldine. 
7 ακλμ -f, m (in margin), r. 
» κβμξ -f, m (in margin) ; κβμξ “Yr. 
9 yap -Ε, B, e, U, Escor. 72; οὖν -f, m, r, Aldine. 
10 KE, B; xai 7a uf’ -e, u, f, m, r, Escor. 72, Aldine. 


an  ῳὡ ND » 


n 


¢ With this and the rest of the chapter through διὰ τοῦτο 
καὶ ἁρμονίαν . . ἐκάλεσαν cf. Lamblichus, Theolog. Arith., 


274: 





GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1017-1018 


thirty-five “ concord’? because it consists of the first 
two cubes produced from even and odd ὃ and of four 
numbers, six and eight and nine and twelve, which 
comprise the arithmetical and the harmonic pro- 
portion.° The force of this will be more evident in a 
diagram. Let afyé be a rectangular parallelogram 
with five as the side a8 and seven as the side αὃ ; 
and, the lesser having been divided into two and 
three at κ and the greater into three and four at A, 
from the points of section let there be produced 
along κμν and Ayvé straight lines that intersect and 
make axpaA six, «B&u nine, λμνδ eight, p&yv twelve, 
and the whole parallelogram thirty-five, comprising 
in the numbers of the areas into which it has been 
divided the ratios of the primary consonances.? For 
the areas six and eight have the sesquitertian ratio, 
in which the fourth consists ; the areas six and nine 
the sesquialteran, in which the fifth consists; the 
areas six and twelve the duple, in which the octave 
p. 63, 7-23 (De Falco), 1.6. Nicomachus (cf. tbid., p. 56, 8-9 
and Gnomon, V [1929], p. 554). 

ὃ 23 +38=35; ef. Iamblichus, Theolog. Arith., p. 63, 7-9 
(De Falco). 

¢ 4.e. 35=64+8+9+412, in which 8 is the harmonic mean 
and 9 is the arithmetical mean of the extremes, 6 and 12; 
see 1019 c-p infra and cf. Nicomachus, Arithmetica Intro- 
ductio τι, xxix, 3-4 (p. 146, 2-23 [Hoche]) and Iamblichus, 
In Nicomachi Arithmeticam Introductionem, pp. 122, 12- 
125, 13 (Pistelli). 

@ See 1019 pv infra (τὰ πρῶτα σύμφωνα) : cf. Theon 
Smyrnaeus, p. 51, 18-20 (Hiller), [Alexander], Metaph., 
p. 834, 1-2, and [Plutarch], De Musica 1139 c-p (... τὰ 
κυριώτατα διαστήματα ...). Since the octave consists of a 
fourth and a fifth, only the latter two were usually considered 
to be strictly “‘ primary ”’ in the sense of “ simple’’ con- 
sonances (cf. Ptolemy, Harmonica, p. 11, 24-25 [Diiring] ; 
Porphyry, Jn Ptolemaei Harmonica, p. 96, 12-20 [Diiring)). 


275 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


Ν A a 
(1018) ἔνεστι δὲ καὶ ὁ τοῦ τόνου λόγος ἐπόγδοος wy" ἐν 
a ? ’ ὁ ‘i A 
Tots ἐννέα καὶ ὀκτώ." διὰ τοῦτο καὶ" ἁρμονίαν τὸν 


α K B 









vg 










ἐξ 

os. 

λ a3 g 
τ τ 
ξ ὁ 
- yn 


ὃ ν Y 


περιέχοντα τοὺς λόγους τούτους ἀριθμὸν ἐκάλεσαν. 
ἑξάκις δὲ" γενόμενος τὸν τῶν" δέκα ποιεῖ καὶ δια- 


1 ὧν -omitted by Εἰ, Β. 

2 The figure infra set into text -Εἰ ; in margin (ἐπίτριτος 
omitted and ἐπόγδοος τόνος along the line yéB in the rectangles 
ιβ and @) -B; in margin with letters only -f, m; in margin 
(right angled parallelogram divided into four equal parts 


276 





; 


GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1018 


consists; and the ratio of the tone, being sesquioc- 
tavan, is present too in the areas nine and eight. This 


a κ β 


fifth 
alteran 





ὃ v Y 


is precisely the reason why they called “᾿ concord”’ the 
number that comprises these ratios. When multi- 
plied by six, moreover, it produces the number 210, 


with letters only, « and v omitted) -e, u, Escor. 72 (can- 
celled) ; figure omitted by r. 

8. καὶ -f, τὴ, r, Aldine; μὲν -E, B, e, u, Escor. 72. 

4 δὲ -omitted by r. 5 τὸν τὸν -Τ΄. 


2717 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1018) κοσίων ἀριθμόν, ἐν ὅσαις ἡμέραις λέγεται τὰ 
ἑπτάμηνα τῶν βρεφῶν τελεογονεῖσθαι. 
18. Πάλιν δ᾽ ἀφ᾽" ἑτέρας ἀρχῆς, κατὰ πολλαπλα- 
σιασμόν' ὁ μὲν δὶς γ΄ τὸν S ποιεῖ," ὁ δὲ τετράκις 
Ο ἐννέα τὸν As’,* 6 δ᾽ ὀκτακις Kl’ tov ais’. Kat 
ἔστιν ὁ μὲν ς΄ τέλειος, ἴσος ὧν τοῖς ἑαυτοῦ μέρεσι, 
καὶ γάμος καλεῖται διὰ τὴν τοῦ ἀρτίου καὶ περιτ- 
τοῦ σύμμιξιν. ἔτι δὲ συνέστηκεν ἔκ τε τῆς ἀρχῆς 
καὶ τοῦ {πρώτου " ἀρτίου καὶ τοῦ πρώτου περιτ- 
τοῦ. ὁ δὲ As’ πρῶτός ἐστι τετράγωνος ἅμα καὶ 
τρίγωνος, τετράγωνος μὲν ἀπὸ τῆς ἑξάδος τρίγωνος 
δ᾽ ἀπὸ τῆς oydoddos: καὶ γέγονε πολλαπλασιασμῷ 
μὲν τετραγώνων δυεῖν, τοῦ τέσσαρα τὸν ἐννέα 
1 Diibner (ὅσαις λέγεται ἡμέραις -Nylander); ὅσαις (.. . 
vac. ὦ... -Ε : no lacuna -B) μοίραις λέγεται -E, Bs ὅσαις 
ἀν -e, Escor. 72 [ἐν ὅσαις in margin] ; se -U3 ὅσεσι 
-Aldine) λέγεται μοίραις -c, ἃ, f, m,'r,; Esecor; 72, 


2 Xylander : ἐφ᾽ -Mss. 3 ποιοῦσιν -e, u, Escor. 72. 
4 FE, B, ἢ, m, r3 τριάκοντα καὶ ἕξ -e, U3 τριακονταέξ 
-Fscor. 79] 


5 «πρώτου» -added in margin of Aldine from codex of 
Donatus Polus and implied by Amyot’ 8 version : ; misplaced 
by Nylander before the a ἀρτίου of διὰ τὴν τοῦ ἀρτίου just above. 

δ᾽ καὶ τοῦ πρώτου ἀρτίου καὶ περιττοῦ -Wyttenbach : καὶ τοῦ 
ἀρτίου καὶ τοῦ περιττοῦ πρώτου -B. Miiller (1873). 


¢ Cf. lamblichus, Theolog. Arith., p. 51, 16-19 and p. 64, 
5-13 (De Falco); Censorinus, De Die Natali xi, 5 (pp. 19, 
28-20, 2 [Hultsch}); Macrobius, Jn Somnium Scipionis 1, 
vi, 15-16; Proclus, In Platonis Rem Publicam ii, pp. 34, 
28-35, 23 (Kroll). 

> i.e. the pairs of numbers in the triangle of Crantor 
(1017 © supra [chap. 11 sub finem]), which in the preceding 
chapter gave the sums 5, 13, and 35, now by multiplication 
yield the products 6, 6?, and 63, 

¢ See Quaest. Conviv. 738 ¥ and Lycurgus v, 13 (42 F) 
and cf. Euclid, Elements vii, Def. 22; Nicomachus, Arith- 


278 





ie Soe a 


GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1018 


the number of days in which it is said seven months’ 
babes are born fully formed.* 

13. And again making a fresh start, by multipli- 
cation: twice three makes six, four times nine thirty- 
six, and eight times twenty-seven 216.2 Now, six is a 
perfect number, being equal to the sum of its 
factors, and is called marriage by reason of the 
commixture of the even and odd?; and furthermore 
it consists of the principle and the first) even and 
the first odd number.’ Thirty-six is the first number 
at once square and triangular, square from six and 
triangular from eight’; and it is the result of the 
multiplication of two squares, nine multiplied by 


metica Introductio 1, xvi, 2-3 (pp. 39, 14-40, 22 [Hoche]) ; 
Theon Smyrnaeus, p. 45, 10-22 and p. 101, 6-9 (Hiller); 
Anatolius in Jamblichus, Theolog. Arith., p. 17, 12-13 and 
Ρ. 42, 19-20 (De Falco). 

4 Cf. Philo Jud., Quaestiones in Genesin ili, 38 (p. 206 
[Aucher]=pp. 224-225 [L.C.L.]) with Joannes Lydus, De 
Mensibus ii, 11 (p. 32, 4-14 [Wuensch]); Clement of 
Alexandria, Stromata vi, xvi, 139, 3; Anatolius in lam- 
blichus, Theolog. Arith., p. 43, 3-9 (De Falco). 

¢ For two as the first even number and three as the first 
odd number see Quaest. Romanae 264 a, De H 388 a, De 
Defectu Orac. 429 8; and for unity or the monad as ἀρχὴ 
ἀριθμοῦ see De Defectu Orac. 415 © (ἔκ τε τῆς ἀρχῆς καὶ τῶν 
πρώτων . . .) and 1017 p supra with note c there (cf. also 
Bers ates, Arithmetica Introductio τ, viii, 2-3 =p. 14, 18-19 
{Hoche]; Iamblichus, Theolog. Arith., p. 1, 4 [De Falco] ; 
and Macrobius, In Somnium Scipionis 1, vi, 7), but for one 
treated as the first odd number see 1027 F supra with note 
d there. 

7 For triangular numbers see the references in note Ο on 
n(n +1) 
2 
satisfied for 36 by n=8, and none of the preceding triangular 
numbers (with the exception of 1) is a square (cf. Theon 

Smyrnaeus, p. 33, 16-17 [Hiller]). 


Plat. Quaest. 1003 r supra. ‘The expression is 





279 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1018) πολλαπλασιάσαντος, συνθέσει δὲ τριῶν κύβων, τὸ 
γὰρ ἕν καὶ τὰ ὀκτὼ καὶ τὰ εἰκοσιεπτὰ συντεθέντα 


α κ β 





παραμέση 


δ 


a τέσσα )ρὼν 


= 
«Ὁ 


ὃ v r 


ποιεῖ TOV προγεγραμμένον ἀριθμόν. ἔτι δὲ ἕτερο- 
D μήκης ἀπὸ δυεῖν πλευρῶν, τῶν μὲν δώδεκα τρὶς 


6 For 1 as a cubic number see Quaest. Conviv. 744. B with 
Jamblichus, Theolog. Arith., p. 77, 9 (De Faico), and cf. 
Nicomachus, Arithmetica Introductio τι, xv, 3 and xx, 5 


280 





GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1018 


four, and of the addition of three cubic numbers, for 
one® and eight and twenty-seven added together 


a K B 


6 9 





Hypaté Paramesé 


δ v Y 


produce the aforesaid number. Moreover, it is an 
oblong number from two sides, from twelve multi- 


(pp. 106, 6-7 and 119, 12-15 [Hoche]); Plutarch himself, 
however, calls eight the first cubic number (1017 pb supra, 
1020 pv infra, and Quaest. Conviv. 738 F), for which ef. 
Jamblichus, Theolog. Arith., p. 72, 2 (De Falco): πρῶτον 
ἐνεργείᾳ κύβον. 


281 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


, 1 A ee re. 7, a δι τὸν 
(1018) γιγνομένων' τῶν δ᾽ ἐννέα τετράκις. ἂν οὖν ἐκτε- 
ἴω € ~ / / “- 
θῶσιν" αἱ τῶν σχημάτων πλευραΐ, τοῦ τετραγώνου 
\ a \ } 
τὰ ς΄ καὶ τοῦ τριγώνου τὰ ὀκτὼ καὶ παραλληλο- 
/ los \ fee: x 2 / A \ e 
γράμμων τοῦ μὲν ἑτέρου τὰ ἐννέα τοῦ δὲ ἑτέρου 
τὰ ιβ΄, τοὺς" τῶν συμφωνιῶν ποιήσουσι λόγους. 
v Ἃ \ / \ cA dat δι / \ / 
ἔσται γὰρ τὰ δώδεκα πρὸς μὲν τὰ ἐννέα διὰ τεσσά- 
ρων ὡς νήτη πρὸς παραμέσην, πρὸς δὲ τὰ ὀκτὼ 
διὰ πέντε ὡς νήτη πρὸς μέσην, πρὸς δὲ τὰ ς΄ διὰ 
- ῃ , \ pg ε \ “4 , 
πασῶν ὡς νήτη πρὸς ὑπάτην. ὁ de ais” κύβος 
ἐστὶν ἀπὸ ἑξάδος ἴσος τῇ ἑαυτοῦ περιμέτρῳ. 
14. Τοιαύτας δὲ δυνάμεις τῶν ἐκκειμένων ἀρι- 
“ > / 3 “a / , “A 
θμῶν ἐχόντων ἴδιον τῷ τελευταίῳ συμβέβηκε, τῷ 
f A “A A ? ~ 7 δ» εὶ 
E xl’, τὸ τοῖς πρὸ αὐτοῦ συντιθεμένοις" ἴσον εἶναι 
πᾶσιν. ἔστι δὲ καὶ περιοδικὸς σελήνης. καὶ τῶν 


ty... vac. 3... ὁμένων -F. 

2 ἐντεθῶσιν -r. The figure supra set into text -E; in 
margin -B; in margin (right angled parallelogram divided 
into four equal parts with letters and numbers only) -e, u, 
Escor. 72; figure omitted by f, m, r. 

3 Between ιβ΄ and τοὺς f, m, r, and Aldine repeat καὶ τοῦ 
τριγώνου . . . παραλληλογράμμων supra; and Escor. 72 repeats 
(but brackets) καὶ τοῦ τριγώνου . . . τοῦ μὲν €. 

4 f, m, r, Escor. 72, Aldine (cf. 6 μὲν ς΄ and ὁ δὲ ds’ in 
1018 c supra); ὁ δὲ τῶν ais’ -E, B, e, u (τῶν of’). 


ν 
5 Maurommates ; συντιθέμενον -MSS. (συντιθέμενος -Τ). 


¢ Number of this kind is προμήκης and only that of the 
type πίη 1) is ἑτερομήκης according to Nicomachus, 
Arithmetica Introductio τι, xvii, 1 and xviii, 2 (pp. 108, 8- 
109, 11 and 113, 6-18 [Hoche]) and Theon Smyrnaeus, 
pp. 30, 8-31, 8 (Hiller). Theon himself at least once, how- 
ever, uses ἑτερομήκης for any oblong number (p. 36, 13-20 
[Hiller]), just as Plutarch does here (see also De Iside 367 F, 


282 














GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1018 


plied by three and from nine multiplied by four.4 
Now, if the sides of the figures be set out, six the 
side of the square and eight of the triangular number 
and of the parallelogrammic numbers? nine the side 
of one and twelve of the other, they will produce the 
ratios of the consonances, for twelve to nine will be a 
fourth as nété to paramesé, to eight a fifth as nété 
to mesé, and to six an octave as nété to hypaté.¢ 
The number 216 is a cube from six equal to its own 
perimeter. 

14. Of the numbers set out,’ which possess such 
properties, the last, twenty-seven, has the peculiar 
characteristic of being equal to the sum of all those 
before 10.959 It is also the periodic number of the 


where eighteen [7.e. 6 x3 or 9 x2] is called ἑτερομήκης), as 
Euclid is supposed by Iamblichus to have done (Jn Nico- 
machi <Arithmeticam Introductionem, pp. 74, 23-75, 4 
{Pistelli]), and as Aristotle apparently did (Anal. Post. 
73 a 40-b 1 with Philoponus, Anal. Post., Ὁ. 62, 15-20). 
Plato in Theaetetus 148 a 1-8 2 used both προμήκης and 
ἑτερομήκης indifferently of all oblong numbers. 

> i.e. the oblongs, 12 x3 and 9x4, supra. Cf. Theon 
Smyrnaeus (pp. 27, 23-28, 2 [Hiller]), who uses the term 
for those numbers that in his sense are προμήκεις but not 
ἑτερομήκεις, 1.6. those of the type n(n +m) where m is not 
less than 2. 

¢ Cf. [Plutarch], De Musica 1138 e—1139 B and 1140 a; 
Nicomachus, Harmonices Man. 6 and Excerpta 7 (Musici 
Scriptores Graeci, pp. 247, 7-26 and 248, 18-26; p. 279, 
8-15 [Jan]). For the meaning of nété and hypaté see note 
6 on Plat. Quaest. 1007 © supra; the paramesé is one tone 
higher in pitch than the mesé (cf. Nicomachus in Musici 
Scriptores Graeci, Ὁ. 248, 21-22 [Jan}). 

4 2,9, 216=63=the sum of the six bounding planes, each 
of which is 6?. 

¢ 2,6. τῶν ὑπὸ ἸΠλάτωνος ἐκκειμένων ἀριθμῶν (1017 D supra). 

f See page 251, note a supra. 

9 Cf. Theon Smyrnaeus, Ὁ. 96, 5-8 (Hiller). 


283 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


> ] A / ς \ ἃ 
(1018) ἐμμελῶν διαστημάτων οἱ Πυθαγορικοὶ τὸν τόνον 
3 A ~ U \ 
ἐν τούτῳ TH ἀριθμῷ τάττουσι" διὸ Kal’ τὰ τριακαί- 
a A > 7 \ / “A 
dexa λεῖμμα καλοῦσιν, ἀπολείπει γὰρ μονάδι τοῦ 
ες; σ΄ et) αἱ 3 \ \ α x 
ἡμίσεος. ὅτι δὲ OTOL Kal τοὺς τῶν συμφωνιῶν 
λόγους περιέχουσι padiov καταμαθεῖν. καὶ γὰρ 
διπλάσιος λόγος ἐστὶν 6 τῶν δύο πρὸς τὸ ἕν ἐν ᾧ 
A A ~ \ ς / e \ \ 7 ~ 
τὸ διὰ πασῶν, καὶ ἡμιόλιος ὃ πρὸς Ta δύο τῶν 
τριῶν ἐν ᾧ τὸ διὰ πέντε, καὶ ἐπίτριτος ὁ πρὸ ὰ 
τρία τῶν τεσσάρων ἐν ᾧ τὸ διὰ τεσσάρων, καὶ 
, e A 4 / ~ > / > e \ x 
τριπλάσιος ὁ πρὸς τὰ τρία τῶν ἐννέα ἐν @ TO διὰ 
F πασῶν καὶ διὰ πέντε, καὶ τετραπλάσιος ὁ πρὸς τὰ 
, mai Ws 9/9 (Oe a ees \ A_4.” \ \ 
δύο τῶν ὀκτὼ ἐν @ TO δὶς" διὰ πασῶν"" ἔνεστι δὲ καὶ 


1 καὶ -omitted by r. 
2 οὗτοι -omitted by r. 
8 δὶς -omitted by ἃ. 
* δὶς διὰ πασῶν καὶ διὰ πέντε -Ὑ. 


* Cf. Aulus Gellius, 1, xx, 6; Favonius Eulogius, De 
Somnio Scipionis, Ὁ. 12, 2-4 (Holder); and Chalcidius, 
_ Platonis Timaeus, Ὁ. 180, 20-21 (Wrobel)=p. 160, 9-10 
(Waszink). The period of 274 days, also mentioned by 
Chalcidius (p. 137, 17-20 [Wrobel] = p. 117, 11-13 [Waszink]), 
is the approximate tropical month: cf. Geminus, Elementa 
Astronomiae i, 30 (p. 12, 24-27 [Manitius]); Pliny, ΝΗ. ii, 
44; Theon Smyrnaeus, Ὁ. 136, 1-3 (Hiller); Macrobius, 
In Somnium Scipionis 1, vi, 50. 
> See τὰ μελῳδούμενα . . . διαστήματα in 1019 a infra with 
note f there; and for τὰ ἐμμελῆ διαστήματα cf. Dionysius 
Musicus in Porphyry, In Ptolemaei Harmonica, Ὁ. 37, 19-20 
(Diiring) and Gaudentius, Harmonica Introductio 3 (Musici 
Scriptores Graect, p. 330, 11-16 [Jan]). 
¢ Cf. Boethius, De Institutione Musica 11, v (pp. 276, 
15-277, 1 and p. 277, 16-18 [Friedlein])=Philolaus, frag. 
A 26 (I, p. 405, 8-15 and 27-28 [D.-K.]). In fact, if the fifth, 


284. 














GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1018 


moon; and of the melodious intervals” the tone is 
assigned to this number by the Pythagoreans,° which 
is also why they call thirteen “ leimma,’’? for it falls 
short of the half by a unit.¢ And it is easy to see 
that these numbers also comprise the ratios of the 
consonances.f For the ratio of two to one is duple, 
in which the octave consists, and that of three to two 
is sesquialteran, in which the fifth consists, and that 
of four to three is sesquitertian, in which the fourth 
consists, and that of nine to three is triple, in which 
consists the octave plus a fifth, and that of eight to 
two is quadruple, in which the double octave consists ; 


fourth, and tone be raised to their least common denominator, 
the numerator of the tone is 27. 

@ See 1017 F supra (page 273, notec). The “ leimma ”’ is 
the ratio 256-243 but was then identified with the difference 
between these two numbers, as is stated in 1022 a infra 
(τὸ μεταξὺ τῶν opy’ Kai τῶν avs’. . .) and Boethius, De 
Institutione Musica 111, v (p. 277, 5-7 [Friedlein]) — Philolaus, 
frag. A 26 (I, p. 405, 19-20 [D. -K.]), a mistake of which 
Theon Smyrnaeus was aware despite his tendency to fall into 
it himself (p. 67, 13-16 and p. 69, 3-14 [Hiller]). 

¢ The same explanation of the term “ leimma,’’ though 
without the additional mistake of μονάδι (for not thirteen but 
that of which it is a half falls short of twenty-seven by a unit), 
is given in 1020 F infra (. . . ὅτι τοῦ ἡμίσεος ἀπολείπει) and 
by Chalcidius (Platonis Timaeus, Ὁ. 112, 11-12 [Wrobel] = 
p. 94, 10-11 [Waszink]) and Gaudentius (Harmonica Intro- 
ductio 14= Musici Scriptores Graeci, p. 343, 6-10 [Jan]) ; 
but the correct explanation, i.e. that it means “the re- 
mainder’ after two tones have been measured off from a 
fourth (cf. Proclus, In Platonis Timaeum ii, p. 177, 10-13 
and pp. 182, 30-183, 2 [Diehl]; Theon Smyrnaeus, p. 70, 
3-6 [Hiller]), is given in 1022 a infra (... περίεστι... διὸ Kai 
λεῖμμα ὠνόμαζον). 

7 Cf. Theon Smyrnaeus, p. 95, 14-16 (Hiller); for what 
follows see De E 389 p and cf. Proclus, In Platonis Timaeum 
ii, p. 168, 2-8 (Diehl) and Macrobius, In Somnium Scipionis 
11, i, 15-20. 

285 


(1018) 


1019 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


ἐπόγδοος ὁ δ᾽ τῶν ἐννέα πρὸς τὰ ὀκτὼ" ἐν ᾧ τὸ το- 
νιαῖον. ἂν τοίνυν ἡ μονὰς ἐπίκοινος οὖσα καὶ τοῖς 
ἀρτίοις συναριθμῆται" καὶ τοῖς περιττοῖς, ὁ μὲν 
ἅπας ἀριθμὸς τὸ τῆς δεκάδος παρέχεται πλῆθος 
(ot γὰρ ἀπὸ μονάδος μέχρι τῶν δέκα συντιθέμενοι 
{πέντε καὶ πεντήκοντα ποιοῦσι) τούτου δὲ ὁ μὲν 
ἄρτιος)" πεντεκαίδεκα, τρίγωνον ἀπὸ πεντάδος, ὁ 
δὲ περιττὸς τὸν τεσσαράκοντα κατὰ σύνθεσιν μὲν 
ἐκ τῶν δεκατριῶν καὶ τῶν KC’ γεννώμενον, οἷς τὰ 
μελῳδούμενα μετροῦσιν εὐσήμως" οἱ μαθηματικοὶ 
διαστήματα τὸ μὲν δίεσιν τὸ δὲ τόνον καλοῦντες, 
κατὰ τὸν πολλαπλασιασμὸν δὲ τῇ τῆς τετρακτύος 
δυνάμει γιγνόμενον, τῶν γὰρ πρώτων τεσσάρων 
καθ᾽ αὑτὸν ἑκάστου τετράκις λαμβανομένου γίγνε- 
ὁ -E, B; omitted by all other mss. and Aldine. 

2 τῶν ἐννέα πρὸς τὰ ὀκτὼ -Bernardakis (πρὸς τὰ ὀκτὼ τῶν 
ἐννέα -Maurommates) ; τῶν ὀκτὼ (η΄ -B, f, m, r) πρὸς τὰ θ' 
(ἐννέα - 1) -Μ88. 


9 5 ΒΘ Uirst ¢ Over erasure), f, m; συναριθμεῖται -e, Al- 
aa συναρθμεῖται -¥ 3; συναρίμειται -U; συναριθεῖται -Escor. 


ou .> added by H. C. after Bernardakis (τὰ πέντε καὶ 
Reeves ποιοῦσι: τούτων δὲ πάλιν ὁ μὲν ἄρτιος τὰ) and 
similar supplements by Wyttenbach and B. Miiller (1873) ; 
συντιθέμενοι.. .. Vac. 50 -E; vac. 48-B... πεντεκαίδεκα -Ἐ,, 
Bs avr Weuebort πεντεκαΐδεκα -€, ἃ, Escor. 79 : : συντιθέμενοι 
te” Deira lacuna) -f, m, r, Aldine. 
> εὐρύθμως -B. 
¢ See De 588. a (... ἡ, μὲν «μονὰς Cp  ΟΣ ἐπίκοινός 
ἐστι τῇ δυνάμει) and 1027 © supra (page 269, note a); cf. 
Theon Smyrnaeus, p. 95, 8-9 (Hiller) and Chaleidius, 
Platonis Timaeus, p. 104, 16-25 (Wrobel)= pp. 87, 23-88, 
(Waszink). 
ὃ With what follows, i.e. 1+2+3...+10=55=(14+2+ 4 
+8 [=15])+(1+3+9+27 [=40]) cf. Anatolius in lam- 
blichus, Theolog. Arith., p. 86, 10-18 (De Falco). 


286 








GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1018-1019 


and among them also that of nine to eight is sesqui- 
octavan, in which the interval of the tone consists. If, 
then, the unit, which is common to the even numbers 
and the odd,* be counted along with both, the number 
taken all together ὃ gives the sum of the decad (for 
the numbers from one to ten added together (make 
fifty-five), and of this the even number gives) fifteen, 
a triangular number from five,° while the odd number 
gives forty, by addition produced from thirteen and 
twenty-seven, numbers which the mathematicians,? 
calling the former “ diesis ”’ and the latter “ tone,’ 
make distinct measures of the melodic intervals,f but 
by multiplication arising in virtue of the tetractys,’ 
for, when each of the first four by itself is multiplied 


feast) 
ae 


δλξιφ,),. 15— Cf. Theon Smyrnaeus, p. 38, 11-114 


(Hiller) and see note ¢ on Plat. Quaest. 1003 F supra. 

4 4.€. of Πυθαγορικοί of 1018 π supra. See 1020 E-F infra, 
where οἱ μὲν ἁρμονικοὶ. . . of δὲ Πυθαγορικοὶ -Ξ τοῖς μὲν ἅρμονι- 
κοῖς... τοῖς δὲ μαθηματικοῖς, and 1021 p infra (. .. ὀρθῶς ὑπὸ 
τῶν μαθηματικῶν λεῖμμα προσηγόρευται). 

4 See 1018 © supra with notes cand ὦ there. As to the use 
of ‘‘ diesis”’ here for what is there called “ leimma”’ cf. 
Theon Smyrnaeus, pp. 55, 13-15 and 56, 18—57, 1 (Hiller) ; 
Chalcidius, Platonis Timaeus, Ὁ. 112, 9-10 (Wrobel)=p. 9-4, 
8-9 (Waszink) ; Macrobius, Jn Somnium Scipionis uy, i, 23 : 
Boethius, De Institutione Musica 11, xxviii (p. 260, 21-25 
[Friedlein]) and m1, v (p. 277, 1-5 [Friedlein]=Philolaus, 
frag. A 26 [i, p. 405, 15-19, D.-K.]) with Philolaus, frag. B 6 
(i, p. 410, 2-8 [D.-K.]). 

. τῶν ἐμμελῶν διαστημάτων... τὸν τόνον... (1018 E 
supra) and διάστημα ἐν pedwdia . . . τῶν δὲ διαστημάτων. .. 
τόνος (1020 © infra). In De E 389 Ἐ-Ὲ and De Defectu Orac. 
430 a Plutarch counts five μελῳδούμενα διαστήματα. distin- 
guishing δίεσις as the quarter-tone from ἡμιτόνιον (cf. Theon 
Smyrnaeus, p. 55, 11-13 [Hiller]}). 

9 Not the Platonic “ tetractys ’’ but, as is clear from what 
follows, the quaternary of the first four numbers. 


287 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


’ \ , A A 
(1019) tor δ΄ καὶ η΄ καὶ ιβ΄ καὶ ις΄. ταῦτα Tov’ μ' συν- 
τίθησι περιέχοντα τοὺς τῶν συμφωνιῶν λόγους" τὰ 
μὲν γὰρ us’ ἐπίτριτα τῶν δεκαδύο ἐστὶν τῶν δ᾽ 
ὀκτὼ διπλάσια, τῶν δὲ τεσσάρων" τετραπλάσια, τὰ 
Β {δὲν ιβ΄’ τῶν ὀκτὼ ἡμιόλια τῶν δὲ τεσσάρων τρι- 
πλάσια. οὗτοι δὲ οἱ λόγοι τὸ διὰ τεσσάρων καὶ τὸ 
διὰ πέντε καὶ τὸ διὰ πασῶν καὶ τὸ δὶς διὰ πασῶν 
περιέχουσιν. ἴσος γε μήν ἐστιν ὁ τῶν τεσσαρά- 
κοντα δυσὶ" τετραγώνοις" καὶ δυσὶ κύβοις ὁμοῦ 
λαμβανομένοις" τὸ γὰρ ἕν καὶ τὰ τέσσαρα καὶ τὰ 
ὀκτὼ καὶ τὰ κζ' κύβοι καὶ τετράγωνοι {(μ'" yiy- 
νονται συντεθέντες .ἷ ὥστε πολὺ τῆς ΠΙυθαγορικῆς 
τὴν Τἰλατωνικὴν τετρακτὺν ποικιλωτέραν εἶναι τῇ 
διαθέσει καὶ τελειοτέραν. 
3 A aA 3 / / ~ e 
15. ᾿Αλλὰ ταῖς εἰσαγομέναις μεσότησι τῶν ὑπο- 
κειμένων ἀριθμῶν χώρας οὐ διδόντων, ἐδέησε μεί- 
ζονας ὅρους λαβεῖν ἐν τοῖς αὐτοῖς λόγοις. καὶ 
Ο λεκτέον τίνες εἰσὶν οὗτοι. πρότερον δὲ περὶ τῶν 
μεσοτήτων' ὧν τὴν μὲν ἴσῳ κατ᾽ ἀριθμὸν ὑπερ. 
1 ταῦτα δὲ τὸν -E, Β. 5. τῶν δ΄ -Ε, B, 
8. «δὲ» -added by Β. Miiller (1873). 
4 δυσὶ -Bernardakis; δυοῖν -E, B, f, τὴ, r; δυεῖν -e, u, 
Escor. 72. 
5 τετραγώνοιν -f (-γωνοῖν). m}, r. 
6 <¢u’> -added by Maurommates. 
7 Es; συντιθέντες -all other mss., Aldine. 


* The octave plus a fifth (12-4), though expressly included 
in 1018 ἘΠ supra as the ratio of nine to three, the triple 
ratio, is (inadvertently 3) omitted here, as it is by the mss. of 
Chalcidius, Platonis Timaeus, p. 101, 4-5 (Wrobel)=p. 84, 
22-23 (Waszink). 

ὃ Since eight and twenty-seven are cubic numbers, one 
and four must be the two square numbers (cf. De Defectu 
Orac. 429 E[. . . πρώτων δυεῖν τετραγώνων . . . τῆς TE μονάδος 


288 








GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1019 


by four, the result is four and eight and twelve and 
sixteen. These make up the number forty while 
comprising the ratios of the consonances, for sixteen 
is four thirds of twelve and twice as much as eight 
and four times as much as four, (and) twelve is half 
again as much as eight and three times as much as 
four ; and these ratios comprise the fourth and the 
fifth and the octave and the double octave.* Then, 
as to the number forty, it is equal to two square and 
two cubic numbers taken together, for one and four 
and eight and twenty-seven are cubic and square 
numbers? amounting to <forty) when they have been 
added together. Consequently the Platonic tetractys 
is much more intricate and consummate in organisa- 
tion than is the Pythagorean.°¢ 

15. Since, however, the numbers postulated do not 
provide room for the means that are being inserted, 
it was necessary to take higher terms in the same 
ratios.¢ So one must say what these are. Before 
that, however, about the means”: of these the one 


καὶ τῆς τετράδος) and De E 391 a), though one has just been 
treated as a cubic number (see 1018 c supra with note a 
on page 281). 

¢ See 1017 v, note ὃ supra. 

4 The ‘‘ numbers postulated’ are τῶν ὑπὸ Πλάτωνος ἐκκει- 
μένων ἀριθμῶν (1017 pv supra). See 1020 a infra, where 
after the digression on the means the substance of the 
present sentence is rephrased more clearly ; and cf. Chal- 
cidius, Platonis Timaeus, pp. 106, 24-107, 2 (Wrobel) = 
p. 89, 19-21 (Waszink). 

¢ With what follows cf. Nicomachus, Harmonices Man. 
8 (Musici Scriptores Graeci, pp. 250, 12-251, 3 and p. 251, 
10-13 [Jan]); Philo Jud., De Opificio Mundi 108-110 (i, 
pp. 38, 19-39, 11 [Cohn]); Chalcidius, Platonis Timaeus, 
p. 107, 2-20 (Wrobel)=pp. 89, 22-90, 12 (Waszink) ; 
Martianus Capella, vii, 737. 


289 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1019) ἔχουσαν ἴσῳ δὲ ὑπερεχομένην ἀριθμητικὴν οἱ νῦν 
καλοῦσι τὴν δὲ ταὐτῷ μέρει τῶν ἄκρων αὐτῶν 
ὑπερέχουσαν καὶ ὑπερεχομένην ὑπεναντίαν. ὅροι 
δ᾽ εἰσὶ τῆς μὲν ἀριθμητικῆς ς΄ καὶ θ' καὶ ιβ’, τὰ 
γὰρ ἐννέα τῷ ἴσῳ κατ᾽ ἀριθμὸν τῶν ἕξ ὑπερέχει 
καὶ τῶν 1p’ λείπεται: τῆς δὲ ὑπεναντίας ς΄ η΄ up’, 
τὰ γὰρ ὀκτὼ δυσὶ μὲν τῶν s’ ὑπερέχει τέσσαρσι 
δὲ τῶν ιβ΄ λείπεται, ὧν τὰ μὲν δύο τῶν ἐξ τὰ δὲ 
τέσσαρα τῶν δώδεκα τριτημόριόν ἐστι. συμβέβη- 
κεν οὖν ἐν μὲν τῇ ἀριθμητικῇ ταὐτῷ" μέρει TO* 

D μέσον" ὑπερέχεσθαι καὶ ὑπερέχειν ἐν δὲ τῇ ὑπεν- 
αντίᾳ ταὐτῷ μέρει τῶν ἄκρων τοῦ μὲν ἀποδεῖν 
\6 Ὁ... / 9 A 4 \ A / . = 7 
τὸ" δὲ ὑπερβάλλειν, ἐκεῖ μὲν γὰρ τὰ τρία τοῦ μέσου 
’ $ ese , 7.5 ~ \ \ , \ \ , aA 
τρίτον ἐστὶ μέρος ἐνταῦθα δὲ τὰ δ΄ καὶ τὰ β΄ τῶν 
ἄκρων ἑκάτερον ἑκατέρου: ὅθεν ὑπεναντία κέκλη- 
1 F, B; dvo -all other mss., Aldine. 2 3. 

8 τῷ ἄκρω “U3 τῷ αὐτῷ -all other mss. 
, μέρει τῶν ἄκρων τὸ -B, Β. 
5 μέσον -correction in margin -f!, m?!, r!, Leonicus ; ἴσον 
(or ἶσον) -Mss. 


6 +6 -Turnebus; τοῦ -r; τὸν -all other mss., Aldine. 

7 μέσον (with final ν remade to s) -u. 

α ἢ. exceeds one extreme and falls short of the other. 
This is clear in Timaeus 36 a 4-5 (quoted in 1027 B-c supra) 
because this clause is preceded by that which defines the 
harmonic mean and which contains τῶν ἄκρων. 

> Though Plutarch here says that ὑπεναντία is the term 
used for the harmonic mean by his contemporaries and so 
uses it in paraphrasing Eudorus (1019 & infra), lamblichus 
says (In Nicomachi Arithmeticam Introductionem, pp. 100, 
29-101, Sand p. 113, 16-22 [Pistelli]) that what was originally 
called ὑπεναντία was renamed ἁρμονική by the circle of 
Archytas and Hippasus (ef. Archytas, frag. B 2 [D.-K.]= 
Porphyry, Jn Ptolemaei Harmonica, Ὁ. 93, 7 and 13-17 
(Diiring]) and that afterwards the name ὑπεναντία was 
applied to a new, fourth mean, thought to be contrary to the 


290 





i 


GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1019 


that exceeds and falls short ὁ by amounts numerically 
equal men today call arithmetical, and the one that 
exceeds and falls short of the extremes by the same 
fraction of them they call subcontrary.o Of the 
arithmetical six and nine and twelve are terms, for 
nine exceeds six and falls short of twelve by numerical 
equality ; and of the subcontrary six, eight, twelve 
are terms, for eight exceeds six by two and falls 
short of twelve by four, and of these two is a third 
of six and four a third of twelve. So it is characteristic 
in the arithmetical for the middle to exceed and fall 
short by the same fraction ὁ and in the subcontrary 
for it to be inferior to one of the extremes and to 
surpass the other by the identical fraction of them, 
for in the former case three is a third of the middle 
and in the latter four and two are thirds, one of one 
extreme and the other of the other, for which reason 
it has been called subcontrary.¢ And to this they 
harmonic (cf. Nicomachus, Arithmetica Introductio τι, 
xxvili, 3=p. 141, 4-16 [Hoche] and Theon Smyrnaeus, 
p. 115, 9-11 [Hiller]). 

ὁ 6. by the same fraction of itself. Cf. Nicomachus, 
Arithmetica Introductio τι, xxv, 3 (p. 132, 18-20 [Hoche] 
and for the whole of Plutarch’s sentence ibid., pp. 132, 
18-133, 2); Iamblichus, In Nicomachi Arithmeticam Intro- 
ductionem, p. 114, 5-8 (Pistelli). 

4 Cf. Iamblichus, In Nicomachi Arithmeticam Intro- 
ductionem, Ὁ. 110, 17-23 with pp. 100, 25-101, 1 (Pistelli) 
and Nicomachus, Arithmetica Introductio 11, xxv, 3 (p. 132, 
21-22 [Hoche]). The contrariety is identified with another 
characteristic by Iamblichus, op. cit., p. 111, 18-26 and 
Boethius, De Institutione Arithmetica τι, xlvii (p. 152, 27-31 
[Friedlein|) ; ef. Nicomachus, op. cit. τι, xxiii, 6 and xxv, 
2 (pp. 126, 1-6 and 132, 11-15 [Hoche]). E. de Strycker 
(Antiquité Classique, xxi [1952], p. 531, n. 1) defended the 
latter explanation; Burkert (Weisheit und Wissenschaft, 
p. 418, n. 98) proposed still another. 


20) 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1019; ται. ταύτην dé’ a nV ὀνομαζ Ἵ i 
i ται. nv ρμονικὴν ὀνομάζουσιν ὅτι τοῖς 
¢ \ wn , 4 ζω 
ὅροις τὰ πρῶτα σύμφωνα παρέχεται, τῷ μὲν με- 


ὅροι τῆς ἀριθμητικῆς ? 


θ ιβ 
ἡ λεῖψις 


τοῦ ἐννέα 
τρία 









t 
ἢ ὑπεροχὴ 
τοῦ ἐννέα 
τρίᾳ 

















« » / 
ὁ ἐννέα 
σις # 3 > ‘ 
τῷ tow κατ᾽ ἀριθμὸν. 
~ ap’ ie ’ - 
τῶν ἕξ ὑπερέχει καὶ τῶν 

’ 
δώδεκα λείπεται 


΄- ε n ΄- ¢ - 
ὅροι τῆς ὑπεναντίας ἢ τῆς αρμονικὴς 


η ιβ 













~ > \ 
ἡ ὑπεροχὴ τῶν ὀκτὼ 
vo 
, 
τριτημόριον 





ε μ᾿ 1 - 
ἡ ἔνδεια αὐτῶν 
/ 
τέσσαρα 


τριτημόριον 













€ > \ 

ὁ ὀκτὼ 

τῷ αὐτῷ μέρε: 

τὸν €€ ὑπερβάλλει καὶ 
“A ΄ ,ὔ 

τοῦ δώδεκα λείπεται 


1 τὴν αὐτὴν δὲ -Β. Miiller (1873) ; ταύτην δὲ «καὶ» -Hubert. 
2 The two figures as here -E (lower margin) ; 
ο θ Τ n 
δ᾽ δὰ and ς β ὃ ιβ -e, Escor. 72 (both 
in side margin); figures omitted by all other mss. 
202 





GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1019 


give the name harmonic because by its terms it 
exhibits the primary concords,* by the greatest in 


Terms of the arithmetical 
9 









Three, 
the excess of nine 





Three; 
the deficiency of nine 






Nine exceeds six and falls short of 
twelve by numerical equality 


Terms of the subcontrary or harmonic 


8 















Two, Four, 
the excess of eight, the inferiority of it, 
a third a third 






Eight surpasses six and fails short of 
twelve by the same fraction 





¢ Cf. lamblichus, In Nicomachi Arithmeticam Introduc- 
tionem, p. 100, 23-25 (Pistelli) and Nicomachus, Arithmetica 
Introductio τι, xxvi, 2 (pp. 135, 10-136, 11 [Hoche]); for 
τὰ πρῶτα σύμφωνα See page 275, note ἃ supra. 


293 


(1019) 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


/ \ \ δὰ 7 \ \ “- a \ 
γίστῳ πρὸς τὸν ἐλάχιστον τὸ διὰ πασῶν τῷ δὲ 
μεγίστῳ" “πρὸς τὸν" μέσον τὸ διὰ πέντε τῷ δὲ 
μέσῳ πρὸς TOV" ἐλάχιστον τὸ διὰ τεσσάρων, OTL 
τοῦ μεγίστου τῶν ὅρων κατὰ νήτην τιθεμένου τοῦ 
δ᾽ ἐλαχίστου καθ᾽ ὑπάτην ὁ μέσος γίγνεται o° 
κατὰ μέσην πρὸς μὲν" τὸν μέγιστον τὸ" διὰ πέντε 
ποιοῦσαν πρὸς δὲ τὸν ἐλάχιστον" TO” διὰ τεσσάρων" 
ὥστε γίγνεσθαι τὰ ὀκτὼ κατὰ τὴν μέσην τὰ δὲ 
δώδεκα κατὰ νήτην"" τὰ δὲ ἕξ καθ᾽ ὑπάτην. 

16. Τὸν δὲ τρόπον ᾧ λαμβάνουσι τὰς εἰρημένας 
μεσότητας ἁπλῶς καὶ σαφῶς Εὔδωρος ἀποδείκ- 
νυσι. σκόπει δὲ πρότερον ἐπὶ τῆς ἀριθμητικῆς. 
ἂν γὰρ ἐκθεὶς τοὺς ἄκρους λάβῃς ἑκατέρου" τὸ 
ἥμισυ μέρος καὶ συνθῆς, ὃ συντεθεὶς ἔσται μέσος ἔν 
τε τοῖς" διπλασίοις καὶ τοῖς τριπλασίοις ὁμοίως. 
ἐπὶ δὲ τῆς ὑπεναντίας, ἐν μὲν τοῖς διπλασίοις ἂν 
τοὺς ἄκρους ἐκθεὶς᾽" τοῦ μὲν ἐλάττονος τὸ τρίτον 
τοῦ δὲ μείζονος τὸ ἥμισυ λάβῃς, ὁ συντεθεὶς" 
γίγνεται μέσος" ἐν δὲ τοῖς τριπλασίοις" ἀνάπαλιν 
τοῦ μὲν ἐλάττονος ἥμισυ δεῖ λαβεῖν τοῦ δὲ μεί- 
ζονος τρίτον, ὁ γὰρ συντεθεὶς οὕτω γίγνεται μέσος. 
ἔστω γὰρ ἐν τριπλασίῳ λόγῳ τὰ ς΄ ἐλάχιστος ὅρος 


1 πρὸς τὸν ἐλάχιστον τὸ διὰ πασῶν τῷ δὲ μεγίστῳ -omitted 
by f. 

2 τὸν -E (ν superscript -E!), B; τὸ -all other mss., Aldine. 

3 


τὸ -Y. 
* ὅθεν -B. Miller (1873); ἔτι -Hubert (who also suggests 
wee ὅτι. .. τὰ δὲ ἐξ καθ᾽ ὑπάτην AS a Marginal note). 


ὁ -deleted by Β. Miiller (1873). 
ὃ μὲν -omitted by Zs 
Η πρὸς μὲν τὴν νήτην -Β. Miiller (1873). 8 τὸν -Τίο, Aldine. 
Ἂ τὸ ἐλάχιστον -Ὑ : τὴν ὑπάτην -Β. Miller (1873). 
τ πὸ , Β, τ: omitted by all other uss. and Aldine. 


κατὰ THY νήτην -f, mM, ©. 12 ἑκάτερον -F. 








GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1019 


relation to the least the octave and by the greatest in 
relation to the middle term the fifth and by the middle 
term in relation to the least the fourth, because, the 
greatest of the terms being placed at nété and the 
least at hypaté, the middle term turns out to be that 
at mesé, mesé in relation to the greatest making the 
fifth and in relation to the least the fourth, so that 
eight turns out to be at the mesé and twelve at nété 
and six at hypaté. 

16. The way the aforesaid means are found is set 
forth simply and clearly by Eudorus.¢ Of the two 
consider first the arithmetical. If you set out the 
extreme terms and take the half of each and add the 
two halves together, the resulting sum will be the 
middle term in the case of the double numbers and 
of the triple alike.’ In the case of the subcontrary,° 
however, if in the double numbers you set out the 
extreme terms and take the third of the lesser and 
the half of the greater, their sum turns out to be the 
middle term ; but in the triple numbers contrariwise 
you must take half of the lesser and a third of the 
greater, for the sum of this addition turns out to be 
the middle term. For let six be least term and 

* See note 6 on 1013 B supra. 

> Cf. Plutarch, Quaest. Conviv. 738 Ὁ (. . . συντεθέντα δ᾽ 
ἀλλήλοις διπλασιάζει τὸν μέσον): Nicomachus, Arithmetica 
Introductio 11, xxvii, 7 (pp. 139, 23-140, 2 [Hoche]) ; Theon 
Smyrnaeus, p. 113, 29-25 and p. 116, 11-13 and 20-2. 
(Hiller). 

¢ See note 6 on 1019 c supra. 


13 τοῖς -omitted by ἢ, m, r. 
14 ἂν θεὶς -τ. 

18 συντιθεὶς -Υ΄. 

16 ἐν δὲ τοῖς τριπλασίοις . . . οὕτω γίγνεται μέσος -omitted 


by u. 


295 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


Ἷ A \ ’ ’ \ > “. 
(1019) τὰ δὲ ιη΄ μέγιστος" ἂν οὖν τῶν ς΄ τὸ ἥμισυ λαβὼν 
A “ \ ~ > \ 4 A 
τὰ τρία Kal τῶν ὀκτὼ καὶ δέκα TO τρίτον τὰ ς΄ 
An A. ‘ A’? 2 A , A » ε 
συνθῇς," ἕξεις τὰ θ΄" ταὐτῷ μέρει τῶν ἄκρων ὑπερ- 
/ \ 
EXOVTA καὶ ὑπερεχόμενα. οὕτως μὲν al μεσότητες 
1020 λαμβάνονται. δεῖ δ᾽ αὐτὰς ἐκεῖ παρεντάξαι" καὶ 
9 ~ A 
ἀναπληρῶσαι τὰ διπλάσια καὶ τριπλάσια διαστή- 
~ > “~ 
ματα. τῶν δ᾽ ἐκκειμένων ἀριθμῶν ot μὲν οὐδὲ 
ὅλως μεταξὺ χώραν ἔχουσιν οἱ δ᾽ οὐχ ἱκανήν" 
» Ss ~ ~ 
αὔξοντες οὖν αὐτούς, τῶν αὐτῶν λόγων διαμενόν- 
των, ὑποδοχὰς ποιοῦσιν ἀρκούσας ταῖς εἰρημέναις 
μεσότησι. καὶ πρῶτον μὲν ἐλάχιστον ἀντὶ" τοῦ 
ἑνὸς τὰ ἕξ θέντες, ἐπεὶ πρῶτος ἥμισύ τε καὶ τρίτον 
ἔχει μέρος, ἅπαντας ἑξαπλασίους τοὺς ὑποτεταγ- 
μένους ἐποίησαν, ὡς ὑπογέγραπται," δεχομένους 
τὰς μεσότητας ἀμφοτέρας καὶ τοῖς διπλασίοις δια- 
στήμασι καὶ τοῖς τριπλασίοις. εἰρηκότος δὲ τοῦ 
1 E, B, εθοτσ. (¢ added over cancellation), ἃ ; συνθῆ -f, m, 
ἔς Escor. 79. 
2 τὰ 0’ -e, u, f, πὶ, r, Escor. 72, Aldine; τὸν ἐννέα -E; 
θ΄ -Β. 

e, u, f, m, r, Escor. 72, Aldine : ὑπερεχόμενον -E, B. 
παρεντέξαι -€, ἃ, Escor. 72}. 
αὐτοὺς -omitted by B! (added superscript -B?2). 

f,m,r; ὄντι -all other mss., Aldine. 

ἐποίησεν -E, B. 

The figure (p. 298) -E (lower margin); the figure with 
numbers but without words -e, u, f, m, Escor. 72 (all in side 
margins) ;. figure omitted by B, r. 

9. καὶ τοῖς τριπλασίοις -f, m (added in margin by m?), r; 
omitted by all other mss. 


\ 
TO 


on aon ἢ wh 


¢ The general method of finding the harmonic mean (m), 


(c - α) 


αἱ ἐν α 
where of the extremes 61» α, is given as nie ee +a by Nico- 


ς 
206 








GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1019-1020 


eighteen greatest in a triple ratio : then, if of six you 
take the half, three, and of eighteen the third, six, 
and add them together, you will have nine, which 
exceeds and falls short of the extremes by the same 
fraction of them.* This is the way the means are 
found ; but one must insert them in that designated 
position and fill up the double and triple intervals.” 
Of the numbers set out,° however, some do not have 
any room at all between them and others do not have 
enough ; so by increasing them with the same ratios 
preserved people produce sufficient accommodations 
for the aforesaid means.? First, for one they sub- 
stituted as the smallest number six, since it is the 
first that has both a half and a third; and all those 
ranged underneath, as drawn below, they made six 
times as large with room to admit both the means to 
the double intervals and the triple too.¢ Plato has 
machus (Arithmetica Introductio τι, xxvii, T=p. 140, 8-13 
[Hoche]), Theon Smyrnaeus (p. 119, 3-16 [Hiller]), and 


Proclus (Jn Platonis Timaeum ii, Ὁ. 172, 11-18 and pp. 172, 
21-173, 4 [Diehl]). None of them gives the simpler formula- 


tion, m= ἐπ, although this is implicit in the statement that 


the sum of the extremes multiplied by the mean equals twice 
the product of the extremes, 7.e. m(a+c)=2ac, made both 
by Nicomachus (op. cit. τι, xxv, 4=p. 133, 5-8 [Hoche]} and 
Harmonices Man. 8= Musici Scriptores Graeci, p. 251, 3-10 
[Jan]) and by ‘Theon Smyrnaeus (pp. 114, 25-115, 4 
[ Hiller]). 

> Cf. Timaeus 35 c 2—36 a 5 quoted at 1027 B-c supra. 

¢ See 1019 B swpra (chap. 15 init.) with note d there. 

4 Cf. 1027 pv supra (chap. 30 init.): .. . ἀριθμοῖς . . . χώρας 
ἔχουσι δεκτικὰς μεταξὺ τῶν εἰρημένων ἀναλογιῶν... .. 

¢ Cf. Proclus, In Platonis Timaeum ii, pp. 175, 22--ΤἸ76, 
27 (Diehl); Iamblichus, Theolog. Arith., p. 51, 8-15 and 
pp. 51, 25-52, 5 (De Falco); Chalcidius, Platonis Timaeus, 
pp. 106, 24-110, 2 (Wrobel)=pp. 89, 19-92, 5 (Waszink). 


407 


(1020) 


B 


C 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 





, (ee , \ oj 9 , 
Πλάτωνος “ ἡμιολίων δὲ διαστάσεων καὶ ἐπιτρίτων 
καὶ ἐπογδόων γενομένων ex’ τούτων τῶν δεσμῶν 
ἐν ταῖς πρόσθεν διαστάσεσι, τῷ" τοῦ ἐπογδόου δια- 
στήματι τὰ ἐπίτριτα πάντα συνεπληροῦτο λείπων" 
αὐτῶν ἑκάστου" μόριον, τῆς τοῦ" μορίου ταύτης 
διαστάσεως λειφθείσης" ἀριθμοῦ πρὸς ἀριθμὸν ἐ ἐχού- 
σης τοὺς ὅρους σ΄ καὶ ν΄ καὶ σ΄ πρὸς γ΄" καὶ μ'" 
καὶ σ΄," διὰ ταύτην τὴν λέξιν ἠναγκάζοντο πάλιν 
τοὺς ἀριθμοὺς ἐπανάγειν καὶ μείζονας ποιεῖν. ἔδει 

\ \ > Cond > ’ / 4 ~ \ 
μὲν yap ἐφεξῆς ἐπόγδοα γίγνεσθαι δύο: τῆς δὲ 


e , wi? 3 / > ’ 9 [4 » ’ 
ἑξάδος οὔτ᾽ αὐτόθεν ἐπόγδοον ἐχούσης, εἴ τε τέμ- 


> 
YOLTO, κερματιζομένων εἰς μόρια τῶν μονάδων, 


δυσθεωρήτου τῆς μαθήσεως ἐσομένης, αὐτὸ" τὸ 
πρᾶγμα τὸν πολλαπλασιασμὸν᾽" ὑπηγόρευσεν, ὥσ- 


1 K, B, f, τὰ, r; εἰς -e, u, Escor. 72, Aldine. 

2 διαστάσαισι τὸ -U. 

> f, m, Τὶ : συνεπλήρου τὸ λεῖπον -all other ass. 

4 ἢ, τὴ, Υ : ἑκάστῳ -all other mss. 

5 τῆς δὲ τοῦ -ἔ, m, r. 

; ληφθείσης -E, B. 

7 ἕξ καὶ πεντήκοντα καὶ διακόσια -E, B; ... διακοσίων -1027 σα 
supra and Timaeus 36 B 4. 

4 πρὸς τρία πρὸς τρία -ἘΠῚ (first two words cancelled). 

9 


πρὸς τρία μ-ὺ. 


10 πρὸς τρία καὶ τεσσαράκοντα καὶ διακόσια -Ἐὶ, B. 








GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1020 





\ 162 


said,* however, “‘ since as a result of these links in 
the previous intervals there came to be intervals of 
three to two and of four to three and of nine to 
eight, he filled in all the intervals of four to three 
with the interval of nine to eight leaving a fraction 
of each of them, this remaining interval of the 
fraction having the terms of the numerical ratio 256 
to 243’; and because of this passage they were 
compelled again to raise the numbers and make them 
larger. For next in succession there had to come two 
sesquioctavans ὃ ; but, as six of itself does not have a 
sesquioctavan and, if it should be divided with the 
units broken up into fractions,“ understanding the 
subject would be an obscure matter,? the situation 
itself prescribed the multiplication, just as in har- 

* Timaeus 36 a 6—B 5 quoted at 1027 c supra. 

> Cf. Proclus, In Platonis Timaeum ii, pp. 176, 27-177, 3 
(Diehl) ; Theon Smyrnaeus, p. 67, 16-21 (Hiller); Chal- 
cidius, Platonis Timaeus, pp. 115, 6-116, 8 (Wrobel)=p. 97, 
3-24 (Waszink). 

ο Of. Proclus, In Platonis Timaeum ii, p. 177, 21 (Diehl) : 

εν τοῖς ἄτμητον THY μονάδα φυλάττειν ἀεὶ βουλομένοις. 

4 Cf. 1027 & supra: ... ἀμυδρὰν ποιεῖ τὴν μάθησιν... .. 


11 αὐτῶ -u. 


12 βγη, Γ: πολυπλασιασμὸν -all other mss. 


299 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1020) περ ἐν ἁρμονικῇ μεταβολῇ τοῦ διαγράμματος. ὅλου 
συνεπιτεινομένου τῷ πρώτῳ τῶν ἀριθμῶν. ὁ “μὲν 
οὖν Εὔδωρος ἐπακολουθήσας Kpavropt πρῶτον 
3) \ ,ὔ Δ ὔ a a pe | \ } 
ἔλαβε τὸν τπὸ΄, ὃς γίγνεται τοῦ ἐξ ἐπὶ τὰ ξδ΄ πολ- 
λαπλασιασθέντος" ἐπηγάγετο δ᾽ αὐτοὺς ὁ τῶν ξδ΄ 
3 θ τ. ΠΝ 4 ὃ δ A f'-3 “-" δὲ ς \ “ 
ἀριθμὸς᾿ ἐπόγδοον ἔχων τὸν οβ΄. τοῖς δὲ ὑπὸ τοῦ 
Πλάτωνος λεγομένοις συμφωνότερόν ἐστιν ὑπο- 
θέσθαι τὸ ἥμισυ τούτου: τὸ yap® λεῖμμα τὸ τῶν 
3 ’ Ὁ , ? 3 A Δ ς / 
ἐπογδόων ἕξει λόγον ἐν ἀριθμοῖς ovs ὁ HAatwv 
εἴρηκεν ς΄ καὶ v’ καὶ σ' πρὸς y’ καὶ μ' καὶ σ΄, τῶν 

D 9) ’ ’ θ / nv“ ὃ A ξς ’ ὃ λ “i 
p?p’ πρώτων τιθεμένων. av δὲ ὁ τούτου διπλά 
σιος τεθῇ" πρῶτος, ἔσται τὸ λεῖμμα λόγον μὲν ἔχον 

A 3 \ 3 \ \ A , Δ ” \ f 
τὸν αὐτὸν ἀριθμὸν δὲ τὸν διπλάσιον, ὃν ἔχει τὰ φιβ 
πρὸς υὑπο'"" γίγνεται γὰρ ἐπίτριτα τῶν μὲν pPB” 


; anaes τι. 
τὸν οβ΄ -Β ; τὸν on πρὸς τὸν of -Ἐ (τὸν on πρὸς Can- 

ase 3 τὸν 7 καὶ ο (ὁ -f, m, r) πρὸς τὸν of -all other MSS. 

3 τούτου, τὸ yap -f, m, 3 τούτου (τρίτου -B) yap τὸ -all 
other mss. 

* τὸ -Maurommates ; τὸν -Mss. 

5 707 -r. 

6 EK, B, e, u, Escor. 72 (with ὃ superscript over s); vod’ 
-f, ΠΣ ὃ vie -Aldine. 

7 psp’ -u. 


¢ Cf. Ptolemy, Harmonica, pp. 54, 13-55, 1 and p. 55, 
4-5 and 7-9 (Diiring). 

Ὁ Crantor, frag. 5 (Kayser)=frag. 5 (Mullach, Frag. 
Philos. Graec. iii, pp. 141-148). Plutarch’s expression sug- 
gests that his immediate source was Eudorus (see note @ on 
1019 ε supra). 

¢ Cf. ‘ Timaeus Locrus”’ 96 8; Theon Smyrnaeus, 
pp. 68, 12~69, 3 (Hiller); Proclus, In Platonis Timaeum ii, 
p. 178, 2-11 (Diehl). The integer 384 is mentioned by 
Chalcidius too (Platonis Timaeus, pp. 116, 19-117, 1 
[Wrobel]=p. 98, 9-11 [Waszink]) but only in passing as 


300 


GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1020 


monic transposition the whole scale is raised in pitch 
along with the first of the numbers.* Eudorus, then, 
following Crantor ὃ took as the first of the numbers 
384,° which is the product of six multiplied by 64; 
and they were attracted by the number 64 because 
it has 72 as sesquioctavan.? It is more in accord with 
Plato’s words, however, to assume the half of this 
number, for the “leimma’”’ that is left after the 
sesquioctavans are taken?’ will have its ratio ex- 
pressed in the numbers that Plato has given, 256 to 
243, if 192 is made the first number.’ If the double 
of this be made the first number, the “‘ leimma ”’ will 
be the same in ratio, to be sure, but double in number, 
being as 512 is to 486, for four thirds of 192 come to 


another possibility. Severus adopted 768, twice 384, in 
order to make the whole scale end with a ‘“ leimma” 
(Proclus, op. cit., ii, pp. 191, 1-192, 12 [Diehl)). 

ἃ Contrast Theon Smyrnaeus, pp. 68, 13-69, 1 (Hiller) 
and Proclus, In Platonis Timaeum ii, p. 177, 3-7 (Diehl). 

¢ Cf. 1022 a mfra (ἀφαιρουμένου δὲ τούτου [scil. διτόνου] 
περίεστι τοῦ ὅλου . . .) and Proclus, In Platonis Timaeum ii, 
p. 177, 10-13 (Diehl). 

f So it was by Theon Smyrnaeus (pp. 67, 21-68, 12 and 
86, 15-87, 3 [Hiller], with which cf. Porphyry, /n Ptolemaer 
Harmonica, p. 130, 9-16 [Diiring]), by Chalcidius (Platonis 
Timaeus, pp. 116, 12-118, 3 [Wrobel]=pp. 98, 3-99, 9 
[Waszink]), and by Aristides Quintilianus (De Musica iii, 1 
[p. 96, 25-28, Winnington-Ingram]). Plutarch’s argument 
for 192 (see 1021 r—1022 a infra, and cf. Theon Smyrnaeus, 
p. 69, 3-6 [Hiller]) is invalid, however, first because Plato 
speaks only of ratios (¢f. Theon Smyrnaeus, p. 69, 7-9 
[Hiller], and see note ὦ on 1018 £ supra) and furthermore 
because 192 would not serve the purpose of clearing fractions 
after the first fourth but in the second would give 288, 324, 
3644 (cf. Proclus, In Platonis Timaeum ii, p. 177, 8-30 
{Diehl}), as Chalcidius himself duly records without re- 
cognizing the implication of it (loc. cat., pp. 117, 18-118, 3 
[Wrobel]=p. 99, 6-9 [Waszink]). 

301 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1020) τὰ avs’ τῶν' δὲ τπδ' τὰ φιβ΄. καὶ οὐκ ἄλογος ἡ 
ἐπὶ τοῦτον ἀναγωγὴ τὸν ἀριθμὸν" ἀλλὰ καὶ τοῖς 
περὶ τὸν Kpavtopa παρασχοῦσα τὸ" εὔλογον" τὰ 
yap ξδ' καὶ κύβος ἐστὶν ἀπὸ πρώτου τετραγώνου 
καὶ τετράγωνος ἀπὸ πρώτου κύβου γενόμενος δ᾽ 
ἐπὶ τὸν γ΄," πρῶτον ὄντα περιττὸν" καὶ πρῶτον τρί- 
γωνον καὶ πρῶτον τέλειον ovTa καὶ ἡμιόλιον, ρΘβ' 

E πεποίηκεν, ἔχοντα καὶ αὐτὸν ἐπόγδοον, ὡς δεί- 
ἕξομεν. 

17. ἹΙρότερον δὲ τί τὸ λεῖμμά ἐστι καὶ τίς ἡ 
διάνοια τοῦ ἰλάτωνος μᾶλλον κατόψεσθε τῶν εἰω- 
θότων ἐν ταῖς [[υθαγορικαῖς σχολαῖς λέγεσθαι 
βραχέως ὑπομνησθέντες. ἔστι γὰρ διάστημα ἐν 
μελῳδίᾳ πᾶν τὸ περιεχόμενον ὑπὸ δυεῖν φθόγγων 
ἀνομοίων τῇ τάσει" τῶν δὲ διαστημάτων ἕν ὁ κα- 

1 FE, B, f, m,r; τὰ -e, τι, Escor. 72, Aldine. 


oO ο 


3 ~ > “~ 4 τ 
2 τούτων ἀναγωγία τῶν ἀριθμῶν -r3 τούτων ἀναγωγὴ τῶν 


ο 
ἀριθμῶν -f, m. 5 χὸν -Ἰ}. 4 τὸν τρία -E, Ὁ. 
5 περιττὸν καὶ πρῶτον... .. τέλειον ὄντα -omitted by r. 


@ 2,6. 192 (not Crantor’s 384). Plutarch contends in what 
follows that the use of 64 as multiplier, by which 192 is 
originally reached, is what made Crantor’s procedure appear 
to be reasonable. In the procedure as given by Proclus 
(In Platonis Timaewm ii, Ὁ. 177, 3-26 [Diehl]) 64 is first 
taken (lines 3-4; cf. Theon Smyrnaeus, pp. 67, 21-68, 1 
{Hiller]) and is then multiplied by three to give 192 (line 8 ; 
cf. Plutarch infra and Theon Smyrnaeus, p. 68, 3-4 [Hiller]), 
and finally 192 is doubled to give 384 (lines 22-26). 

> 2,6, 64=48=8*%. Cf. Philo Jud., De Opificio Mundi 93 
and 106 (i, p. 32, 1-4 and p. 38, 2-6 [Cohn]); Anatolius, 
p. 35, 14-16 (Heiberg)=Iamblichus, Theolog. Arith., Ὁ. 54, 
13-15 (De Falco). For eight as the first cubic number see 
note a on page 281 supra. 

¢ See note 6 on page 279 supra. 


302 





GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1020 


256 but of 384 to 512. Raising it to this number @ is 
not unreasonable either but even for Crantor and his 
followers is the source of what is reasonable in their 
procedure, for 64 is both a cubic number from the 
first square number and a square number from the 
first cubic number ὃ and, multiplied by three, which 
is the first odd ὁ and first triangular number ¢ and 
the first perfect ὁ and first sesquialteran number,f 
makes 192, which itself has a sesquioctavan also, as 
we shall show. 9 

17. What the “leimma”’ is and what is Plato’s 
meaning you will perceive more clearly, however, 
after having first been reminded briefly of the 
customary statements in the Pythagorean treatises. 
Tor an interval in music is all that is encompassed by 
two sounds dissimilar in pitch” ; and of the intervals 


ἃ See note ¢ on Plat. Quaest. 1003 F supra. 

e Cf. Quaest. Romanae 288 νυ, De Iside 374 a, Fabius 
Maximus iv, 7 (176 pv), and Quaest. Conviv. 738 τ and 744 B 
for the different senses in which three and six is each the 
‘first perfect number”; cf. also Anatolius, p. 31, 7-9 
(Heiberg)=Iamblichus, Theolog. Arith., Ὁ. 17, 4-5 (De 
Falco) and for six see note ¢ on 1018 ὁ supra. 

f Cf. Nicomachus, Avrithmetica Introductio 1, xix, 2-3 
(p. 49, 10-19 [Hoche]); Theon Smyrnaeus, p. 81, 1-2 
(Hiller); Macrobius, In Somnium Scipionis τ, vi, 43 (“primus 
hemiolius tria ...’’). 

9 See 1021 F wnfra. 

» This is not the same as the definition given in 1026 a 
supra (page 253, note a) and is not the “ Pythagorean ”’ de- 
finition but is that of Aristoxenus (lementa Harmonica i, 15, 
25-32) and his followers, as Porphyry says (Jn Ptolemaez 
Harmonica, p. 91, 1-3; p. 93, 19-28; p. 125, 16-24; p. 128, 
5-6 [Diiring]). Cf. Cleonides and Gaudentius in Musici 
Scriptores Graeci, p. 179, 11-12 and pp. 329, 23-330, 4 (Jan) ; 
and Aristides Quintilianus, De Musica i, 7 (p. 10, 18-19 
[Winnington-Ingram]). 

305 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1020) λούμενος τόνος, @ τὸ διὰ πέντε μεῖζόν ἐστι τοῦ διὰ 
τεσσάρων. τοῦτον οἱ μὲν ἁρμονικοὶ δίχα τεμνό- 
μενον οἴονται δύο διαστήματα ποιεῖν, ὧν ἑκάτερον 
ἡμιτόνιον καλοῦσιν" οἱ δὲ Πυθαγορικοὶ τὴν μὲν εἰς 
ἴσα τομὴν ἀπέγνωσαν αὐτοῦ τῶν δὲ τμημάτων ἀν- 

F ίσων ὄντων λεῖμμα τὸ ἔλαττον ὀνομάζουσιν, ὅτι τοῦ 
ἡμίσεος' ἀπολείπει. διὸ Kal τῶν συμφωνιῶν τὴν 
διὰ τεσσάρων οἱ μὲν δυεῖν τόνων καὶ ἡμιτονίου 
ποιοῦσιν ot δὲ δυεῖν καὶ λείμματος. μαρτυρεῖν δὲ 
δοκεῖ τοῖς μὲν ἁρμονικοῖς ἡ αἴσθησις τοῖς δὲ μαθη- 
per τοις 7 proce, Ἢ ἧς τοιοῦτος ὁ τρόπος ἐστίν" 

1 ἡμίσεως -e, ἃ, τη (corrected), Escor. 721 (corrected). 


* This definition also is not ‘‘ Pythagorean ”’ but is that of 
Aristoxenus (Hlementa Harmonica i, 21, 20-24 and ii, 46, 1-2), 
sharply criticized by Ptolemy (Harmonica, pp. 20, 13-21, 
20 [Diiring]; cf. Porphyry, Jn Ptolemaei Harmonica, Ὁ. 126, 
7-19 [Diiring]); cf. Bacchius and Gaudentius (Musici 
Scriptores Graeci, Ὁ. 293, 6-7 and p. 338, 11-12 [Jan]) and 
Theon Smyrnaeus, p. 53, 5-8 (Hiller). 

> Aristoxenus, Hlementa Harmonica ii, 46, 3 and 57, 
11-12; ef. Theon Smyrnaeus, p. 53, 8-10 (Hiller) and 
Boethius, De Institutione Musica 111, i (p. 268, 21-25 [Fried- 
lein]). By of ἁρμονικοί here Plutarch means neither theorists 

_ earlier than Aristoxenus (Elementa Harmonica i, 2, 8-11 and 
ii, 40, 25-26) nor “‘ dilettanti ’’ (Maria Timpanaro Cardini, 
Pitagorici : Testimonianze e Frammenti, Fasc. ii [ Firenze, 
1962], p. 213 note) but Aristoxenus and his followers, as is 
confirmed by of μὲν δυεῖν τόνων Kat ἡμιτονίου ποιοῦσιν infra. 

¢ See 1017 F supra (. .. τὴν εἰς ἴσα τοῦ τόνου διανομὴν 
ἀπογιγνώσκοντες) and ς΄. Porphyry, In Ptolemaei Harmonica, 
p. 67, 3-8 (Diiring); Euclid, Sectio Canonis 16; ‘Theon 
Smyrnaeus, p. 53, 13-15 (Hiller) ; Boethius, De Institutione 
ae ul, i and xi (pp. 269, 32-270, 1 and pp. 285, 9-286, 

4 [Friedlein] = Archytas, frag. A 19 [D.-K.]). 

4 See 1018 £ supra (page 285, note 6). 

e Aristoxenus, Llementa Harwouiea i, 24, 9-11 and ii, 
46, 2 and 56, 14-58, 5. Cf. Ptolemy, Harmonica, p. 91, 
21-22 and Theon Smyrnaeus, p. 67, 10-12 (Hiller). 


304 











GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1020 


one is what is called the tone, that by which the fifth 
is greater than the fourth. The harmonists think 
that this, when divided in two, makes two intervals, 
each of which they call a semitone®; but the 
Pythagoreans denied that it is divisible into equal 
parts ὁ and, as the segments are unequal, name the 
lesser of them “ leimma ”’ because it falls short of the 
half.¢ This is also why among the consonances the 
fourth is by the former made to consist of two tones 
and a semitone ὁ and by the latter of two and a 
“leimma.’’* Sense-perception seems to testify in 
favour of the harmonists but in favour of the mathe- 
maticians 7 demonstration,” the manner of which is 


* Cf. Philolaus, frag. B 6 (i, p. 410, 3-8 [D.-K.] with 
note e on 1019 a supra); Ptolemy, Harmonica, pp. 22, 
17-23, 3 (Diiring) ; Proclus, In Platonis Timaeum ii, Ὁ. 183, 
20-21 and 23-25 (Diehl). 

9 i.e. the Pythagoreans just mentioned ; see 1021 p infra 
(ὀρθῶς ὑπὸ τῶν μαθηματικῶν λεῖμμα προσηγόρευται) and note ὦ 
on 1019 a supra. 

» Cf. Ptolemy, Harmonica, pp. 21, 25-22, 1 (Diiring); 
and Theon Smyrnaeus, pp. 69, 17-70, 1 (Hiller), where of 
μὴ λόγῳ ἀλλὰ τῇ ἀκοῇ ταῦτα κρίνοντες is the conventional 
characterization of the Aristoxenians (cf. Proclus, Jn Platonis 
Timaeum ii, p. 170, 7-10 [Diehl] ; Boethius, De Institutione 
Musica τι, xxxi and ul, i=p. 267, 4-5 and p. 268, 21-22 
[Friedlein]) in contrast to the Pythagoreans, who made 
reason, i.e. mathematical demonstration, the criterion of 
musical science (cf. [ Plutarch], De Musica, 1144 Fr; Aristides 
Quintilianus, De Musica iii, 2=p. 97, 3-7 [Winnington- 
Ingram]; Ptolemy, Harmonica, Ὁ. 6, 1-13 [Diiring]; 
Ptolemais of Cyrene in Porphyry, Jn Ptolemaei Harmonica, 
pp. 25, 9-26, 4 [Diiring]). For the attitude of Aristoxenus 
himself cf. his Hlementa Harmonica ii, 32, 10-33, 2. Theo- 
phrastus spoke of τῶν ἁρμονικῶν καὶ αἰσθήσει κρινόντων in con- 
trast to those who made numerical ratio the criterion (Por- 
phyry, In Ptolemaei Harmonica, p. 62, 2-3 { Diiring|=Theo- 
phrastus, frag. 89, 2 [Wimmer)]). 


305 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1020) ἐλήφθη διὰ τῶν ὀργάνων θεωρηθὲν᾽ ὅτι τὸ μὲν διὰ 
πασῶν τὸν διπλάσιον λόγον ἔχει τὸ δὲ διὰ πέντε τὸν 
ἡμιόλιον τὸ δὲ διὰ τεσσάρων τὸν ἐπίτριτον ὁ δὲ 

102] τόνος τὸν ἐπόγδοον. ἔξεστιν δὲ καὶ νῦν βασανίσαι 
τἀληθὲς 1 7° βάρη δυεῖν ἄνισα χορδῶν ἐξαρτήσαντας 
ἢ δυεῖν ἰσοκοίλων αὐ ῶν τὸν ἕτερον μήκει διπλά- 
σιον. τοῦ" ἑτέρου ποιήσαντας" τῶν μὲν γὰρ αὐλῶν ὁ 
μείζων βαρύτερον φθέγξεται" ὡς ὑπάτη πρὸς 
νήτην," τῶν δὲ “χορδῶν ἡ ἡ τῷ. διπλασίῳ κατατεινο- 


μένη βάρει τῆς ἑτέρας ὀξύτερον. ὡς νήτη πρὸς 
ὑπάτην. τοῦτο δ᾽ ἐστὶ διὰ πασῶν ὃ ὁμοίως δὲ 
καὶ τρία πρὸς δύο ληφθέντα μήκη καὶ βάρη τὸ διὰ 
πέντε ποιήσει καὶ “τέσσαρα πρὸς τρία τὸ διὰ τεσσά- 
ρων, ὧν τοῦτο μὲν ἐπίτριτον ἔχει λόγον ἐκεῖνο δὲ 
ἡμιόλιον. ἐὰν δὲ ὡς ἐννέα πρὸς ὀκτὼ γένηται τῶν 

1 ληφθὲν -r} (corrected in margin). 

2 ἔστι -f, τὰ, Escor. 723 ἔσται -r? (ει, superscript over αἱ 
-r*), 

8. εἶ Tt. τ τοῦ -omitted by τ. 

5 φθέγγεται -B. § νήτην -omitted by r. 

᾿ βάρη -e, u, Escor. 721 (corrected). 

8 ἐστὶ «τὸ» διὰ πασῶν -Hubert; but cf. 1018 ν be ie 
(πρὸς δὲ τὰ ς΄ διὰ πασῶν ὡς νήτη πρὸς ὑπάτην). 

ΒΒ epi -e, u, Escor. 72, Aldine; γίνηται -f, m, r 

4 The following two experiments are ascribed to “* various 
Pythagoreans’”’ by Porphyry (Jn Ptolemaei Harmonica, 
pp. 119, 13-120, 7 [Diiring]) and to Pythagoras himself by 
Censorinus (De Die Natali x, 8-12=pp. 17, 19-19, 2 
{Hultsch]). Introduced by the story of the blacksmith’s 
hammers, they are among those ascribed to Pythagoras by 
Nicomachus (Harmonices Man. 6= Musici Scriptores Graeci, 
pp. 246, 5-248, 26 [Jan]), whose account was copied by 
Iamblichus (Vita Pyth. 115-119). Versions similar to this 
are given by Gaudentius (Musici Scriptores Graeci, pp. 540, 
4— 341, 25 [Jan]), Macrobius (Jn Somnium Scipionis τι, i, 
9-14), and Boethius (De Institutione Musica τ, x-xi). The 


306 





GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1020-1021 


as follows. It has been found by observation with 
instruments that the octave has the duple ratio and 
the fifth the sesquialteran and the fourth the ses- 
quitertian and the tone the sesquioctavan. It is 
possible even now to test the truth of this ¢ either by 
suspending unequal weights from two strings or by 
making one of two pipes with equal cavities double 
the length of the other, for of the two pipes the 
larger will sound lower as hypaté to nété and of the 
strings the one stretched by the double weight will 
sound higher than the other as nété to hypaté. This 
is an octave.? Similarly too, when lengths and 
weights of three to two are taken, they will produce 
the fifth and of four to three the fourth, the latter of 
which has sesquitertian ratio and the former ses- 
quialteran. If the inequality of the weights or the 


longest account of such experiments but without the story 
of the hammers is given—in part from Adrastus—by Theon 
Smyrnaeus (pp. 57, 1-61, 11; pp. 65, 10-66, 11; p. 66, 
20-23 [Hiller]), whereas of them all Chalcidius (Platonis 
Timaeus, p. 112, 16-19 [Wrobel]=p. 94, 14-16 [Waszink]) 
mentions—and ascribes to Pythagoras—only that with the 
suspended weights (cf. Aristides Quintilianus, De Musica 
iii, 1=pp. 94, 11-95, 7 [Winnington-Ingram]). The experi- 
ments were dismissed as “* inexact ”’ by Ptolemy (Harmonica, 
pp. 16, 32-17, 20 (Diiring]) but without mention and pre- 
sumably without knowledge of the physical laws that make 
their professed results erroneous (οὐ, Burkert, Weisheit und 
Wissenschaft, pp. 354-357). 

> The double weight would not produce an octave, for the 
frequency of vibration and hence the pitch varies with the 
square root of the weight stretching the string. lor the 
opposite effect of increasing the length of the pipe and the 
weight suspended from the string cf. Nicomachus, Har- 
monices Man. 4 (Musici Scriptores Graeci, pp. 243, 10-244, 
9 [Jan]) and Censorinus, De Die Natali x, 12 (pp. 18, 94-- 
19, 2 [Hultsch]). 


307 


(1021) 


C 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


Β βαρῶν 7 ἢ τῶν μηκῶν ἡ ἀνισότης, ποιήσει διάστημα 
τονιαῖον οὐ σύμφωνον ἀλλ᾽ ἐμμελές, ὡς εἰπεῖν ἔμ- 
βραχυ, τῷ" τοὺς φθόγγους, ἂν ἀνὰ μέρος κρου- 

~ 4 e ~ 
σθῶσι, παρέχειν ἡδὺ φωνοῦντας Kal προσηνές, ἂν 
δὲ ὁμοῦ, τραχὺ" καὶ λυπηρόν" ἐν δὲ ταῖς συμφω- 
νίαις, κἂν ὁμοῦ κρούωνται κἂν ἐναλλάξ, ἡδέως προσ- 
ίεται τὴν συνήχησιν" ἡ αἴσθησις. οὐ μὴν ἀλλὰ 
καὶ διὰ λόγου τοῦτο δεικνύουσιν. ἐν μὲν γὰρ ἄρ- 
μονίᾳ τὸ διὰ πασῶν ἔκ τε τοῦ διὰ πέντε σύγκειται 
καὶ τοῦ διὰ τεσσάρων, ἐν δ᾽ ἀριθμοῖς τὸ διπλάσιον 

ay ee / “- 

ἔκ τε τοῦ ἡμιολίου καὶ τοῦ ἐπιτρίτου" τὰ γὰρ ip" 
TOV μὲν θ’ ἐστὶν ἐπίτριτα τῶν δ᾽ 7’ ἡμιόλια τῶν 
δὲ s” διπλάσια. σύνθετος οὖν ὁ τοῦ διπλασίου" 
λόγος ἐστὶν ἐκ τοῦ ἡμιολίου καὶ τοῦ ἐπιτρίτου 
καθάπερ ὁ τοῦ διὰ πασῶν ἐκ᾽ τοῦ διὰ πέντε καὶ 

- \ / 9 2 > ~ A \ / “A 
τοῦ διὰ τεσσάρων, ἀλλὰ κἀκεῖ TO διὰ πέντε τοῦ 
διὰ τεσσάρων τόνῳ κἀνταῦθα τὸ ἡμιόλιον τοῦ ἐπι- 

“A / A / 
τρίτου τῷ ἐπογδόῳ μεῖζόν ἐστι. φαίνεται τοίνυν 
“A / ᾽ὔ 
ὅτι τὸ διὰ πασῶν τὸν διπλάσιον λόγον ἔχει καὶ τὸ 
διὰ πέντε τὸν ἡμιόλιον καὶ τὸ διὰ τεσσάρων τὸν 
> 
ἐπίτριτον καὶ ὁ τόνος TOV ἐπόγδοον. 
3 “- 

18. ᾿Αποδεδειγμένου δὲ τούτου, σκοπῶμεν εἰ 
δίχα τέμνεσθαι πέφυκε τὸ ἐπόγδοον᾽" εἰ γὰρ μὴ 
1 τὸ -€, uy, Yr, Escor. 12, Aldine. 

2 παχὺ -f, m, τ, Aldine. 
3 συνήθειαν -B 3 σύγχυσιν τ. 
4 καὶ -omitted by u. 
: 5 διπλάσιον -u. 
6 εἰς -e, τι, Escor. 72! (corrected in margin).° 
7 ἀποδεδειγμένου . . . TO ἐπόγδοον -omitted by f. 


α Cf. Nicomachus, Harmonices Man. 6 (Musici Scriptores 
Graeci, Ὁ. 246, 11-14 [Jan]) ; Ptolemy, Harmonica, p. 15, 10- 
17 and p. 16, 14-16 and 25-28 (Diiring) ; Theon Smyrnaeus, 
p. 49, 4-5 and p. 75, 15-17 (Hiller). 


308 





GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1021 


lengths be made as nine to eight, however, it will 
produce an interval, that of the tone, not concordant 
but tuneful ¢ because, to put it briefly, the notes it 
gives, if they are struck successively, sound sweet and 
agreeable but, if struck together, harsh and painful, 
whereas in the case of consonances, whether they be 
struck together or alternately, the sense accepts with 
pleasure the combination of sound.” What is more, 
they give a rational demonstration of this too.° The 
reason is that in a musical scale the octave is com- 
posed of the fifth and the fourth and arithmetically 
the duple is composed of the sesquialter and the 
sesquiterce, for twelve is four thirds of nine and half 
again as much as eight and twice as much as six. 
Therefore the ratio of the duple is composite of the 
sesquialter and the sesquiterce just as that of the 
octave is of the fifth and the fourth, but in that case 
the fifth is greater than the fourth by a tone and in 
this the sesquialter greater than the sesquiterce by a 
sesquioctave.? It is apparent, then, that the octave 
has the duple ratio and the fifth the sesquialteran and 
the fourth the sesquitertian and the tone the ses- 
quioctavan. 

18. Now that this has been demonstrated, let us 
see whether the sesquioctave is susceptible of being 


» Cf. Adrastus in Theon Smyrnaeus, pp. 50, 22-51, 4 
(Hiller) and Porphyry, Jn Ptolemaet Harmonica, p. 96, 1-6 
(Diiring); Nicomachus, Harmonices Man. 12 (Musici Serip- 
tores Graeci, p. 262, 1-5 [Jan]}). 

¢ Cf. Adrastus in Theon Smyrnaeus, p. 61, 20-23 and 
with the following demonstration Theon Smyrnaeus, pp. 62, 
1-63, 2 (Hiller); Chalcidius, Platonis Timaeus, p. 113, 1-20 
(Wrobel)=p. 95, 1-15 (Waszink); Ptolemy, Harmonica, 
pp. 11, 24-12, 1 (Diiring). 

4 Cf. Euclid, Sectio Canonis 13. 


309 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1021) πέφυκεν, ovde ὁ τόνος. ἐπειδὴ πρῶτοι" τὸν ἐπόγ- 
D Soov λόγον ὁ ὁ θ' καὶ 6 η΄ ποιοῦντες οὐδὲν διάστημα 


μέσον ἔχουσι διπλασιασθέντων δ᾽ ἀμφοτέρων ὁ 
παρεμπίπτων μεταξὺ δύο ποιεῖ διαστήματα, δῆλον 
ὅτι τούτων μὲν ἴ ἴσων ὄντων δίχα τέμνεται τὸ ἐπόγ- 
δοον. ἀλλὰ μὴν διπλάσια γίγνεται τῶν μὲν θ' 
τὰ ιη΄ τῶν δ᾽ η΄ τὰ ις΄, δέχονται δὲ οὗτοι μεταξὺ 
τὰ ιζ' καὶ γίγνεται τῶν διαστημάτων τὸ μὲν μεῖζον 
τὸ δ᾽ ἔλαττον" ἔ ἔστι γὰρ TO μὲν πρότερον ἐφεπτα- 
καιδέκατον τὸ δὲ δεύτερον ἐφεξκαιδέκατον. εἰς 
ἄνισα τοίνυν τέμνεται τὸ ἐπόγδοον᾽ εἰ δὲ τοῦτο, καὶ 
ὁ τόνος. οὐδέτερον ἄρα γίγνεται διαιρεθέντος 
αὐτοῦ τῶν τμημάτων ἡμιτόνιον, ἀλλ᾽ ὀρθῶς ὑπὸ 
τῶν μαθηματικῶν λεῖμμα" προσηγόρευται. καὶ 
τοῦτ᾽ ἐστὶν ὃ φησιν ὁ Πλάτων τὰ ἐπίτριτα" τοῖς 
ἐπογδόοις συμπληροῦντα τὸν θεὸν λείπειν ἑκάστου 
μόριον αὐτῶν, οὗ λόγος ἐστὶν ὃν ἔχει τὰ ς΄ καὶ ν' 
καὶ o πρὸς τὰ γ΄ καὶ μ' καὶ σ΄. εἰλήφθω γὰρ τὸ 
διὰ τεσσάρων ἐν ἀριθμοῖς δυσὶ τὸν ἐπίτριτον λόγον 

᾿ ἐπεὶ δὲ -Stephanus. 

5 πρῶτον -τ, Aldine. 


᾿ λεῖμμα «τὸ ἔλαττονΣ -Maurommiates. 
4 f,m,r; τὰ ἡρίτα -E, B, e, u, Escor. 72, Aldine. 


4 With the following demonstration cf. Anon. ij Platonis 
Theaetetum (Pap. Berl. 9782), cols. 34, 47-35, 12 (p. 23 
[Diels-Schubart]) ; Aristides Quintilianus, De Musica iii, 1 
(pp. 95, 19-96, 4 [Winnington-Ingram]); Boethius, De 
Institutione Musica ur, 1 (p. 270, 4-18 [Friedlein}); and 
Proclus, In Platenis Timaeum ii, Ὁ. 179, 18-25 (Diehl). 

® This is inconsistent with the statement that between 
nine and eight there is no interval. The authors cited in the 
last preceding note speak of numbers and ratios rather than 
intervals, whereas Theon Smyrnaeus (p. 70, 1-3 and 15-16 
(tiller|) asserts that the sesquioctave is indivisible because 
the interval of nine to eight, i.e. the unit, is indivisible. 


310 








GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1021 


divided in half, for, if it is not, neither is the tone.¢ 
Since nine and eight, the first numbers producing the 
sesquioctavan ratio, have no intermediate interval 
but between them when both are doubled the inter- 
vening number produces two intervals, it is clear 
that, if these intervals are equal, the sesquioctave is 
divided in half. But now twice nine is eighteen and 
twice eight sixteen; and between them these 
numbers contain seventeen, and one of the intervals 
turns out to be larger and the other smaller, for the 
former is eighteen seventeenths and the second is 
seventeen sixteenths. It is into unequal parts, then, 
that the sesquioctave is divided ; and, if this is, the 
tone is also. Neither of its segments, therefore, 
when it is divided, turns out to be a semitone ; but 
it ὁ has rightly been called by the mathematicians 
“leimma.’’ ὦ This is just what Plato says @ god in 
filling in the sesquiterces with the sesquioctaves 
leaves a fraction of each of them, the ratio of which 
is 256 to 243. For let the fourth be taken as ex- 
pressed by two numbers comprising the sesquitertian 


ὁ i.e. what is commonly called the semitone, for λέγεται 
κοινῶς μὲν ἡμιτόνιον ἰδίως δὲ λεῖμμα (Gaudentius in Musici 
Scriptores Graeci, p. 342, 7-11 [Jan]; ef. zbid., p. 344, 5-6 
and Theon Smyrnaeus, p. 53, 8-13 [Hiller] with Porphyry, 
In Ptolemaei Harmonica, p. 67, 5-8 [Diiring]}). 

@ See supra 1020 Ἐ-Ὲ and 1019 a, notes ὦ and ὁ. 

¢ This sentence is a paraphrase of Timaeus 36 5 1-5, 
quoted supra 1027 c and 1020 8. 

7 With what follows in the rest of this chapter cf. especially 
Nicomachus, Lxcerpta 2 (Musici Scriptores Graeci, pp. 267, 
2-268, 2 {[Jan]). Cf. also Chalcidius, Platonis Timaeus, 
pp. 117, 1-11 and 118, 4-16 (Wrobel) =pp. 98, 11-99, 1 and 
99, 10-19 (Waszink); Boethius, De Institutione Musica 
1, ii (pp. 272, 11-273, 14 [Friedlein]) ; and most succinctly 
Proclus, In Platonis Timaeum ii, p. 177, 8-13 (Diehl). 


311 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


/ a , \ A e ¢ A 
(1021) περιέχουσι, τοῖς avs’ καὶ τοῖς p9P’, ὧν ὁ μὲν 
ἐλ / A oO f ’ θ \ \ / 1 
ἐλάττων, τὰ p°B’, κείσθω κατὰ τὸν βαρύτατον 
“- ’ ,ὔ 2 e \ ’ \ , 
τοῦ τετραχόρδου φθόγγον" ὁ de μείζων, τὰ avs’, 
\ \ 39“ 2 3 / ¢ is 
κατὰ τὸν ὀξύτατον. ἀποδεικτέον OTL, τούτου συμ- 
πληρουμένου δυσὶν ἐπογδόοις, λείπεται διάστημα 
τηλικοῦτον ἡλίκον ὡς ἐν ἀριθμοῖς τὰ ς΄ καὶ v’ καὶ 
o’ πρὸς τὰ y’ καὶ μ' καὶ σ΄. τοῦ γὰρ βαρυτέρου 
Ἐ' τόνον' émitabévtos,® ὅπερ ἐστὶν ἐπόγδοον, γίγνεται 
6 , (A / ” ΠΣ ᾽ ,ὔ 
σις΄. τούτου πάλιν τόνον ἄλλον ἐπιταθέντος, γίγ- 
νεται σμγ΄. ταῦτα μὲν γὰρ ὑπερέχει τῶν σις" τοῖς 
KC’ τὰ δὲ σις" τῶν ρΟβ’ τοῖς Kd’, ὧν τὰ μὲν KC’ 
τῶν as’ oydod® ἐστι τὰ δὲ Kd’ τῶν ρΟβ΄. διὸ 
γίγνεται τῶν τριῶν τούτων ἀριθμῶν ὅ τε μέγιστος 
ἐπόγδοος τοῦ μέσου καὶ ὁ μέσος τοῦ ἐλαχίστου" τὸ 
δ᾽ ἀπὸ τοῦ ἐλαχίστου" διάστημα μέχρι τοῦ peyt- 
στου, τουτέστι τὸ ἀπὸ τῶν pPP’ μέχρι τῶν opy’,” 
1022 δίτονον᾽ ἡ ἐκ δυεῖν συμπληρούμενον" ἐπογδόων. ἀφ- 
αἱιρουμένου δὲ τούτου, περίεστι τοῦ ὅλου διά- 
στημα λοιπὸν τὸ μεταξὺ τῶν σμγ΄ καὶ τῶν OVS’, τὰ 
vy’: διὸ καὶ λεῖμμα τοῦτον τὸν ἀριθμὸν ὠνόμαζον. 
1 τὸν βαρύτατον -f; τὸ βαρύτατον -m, Υ ; τὸν βαρύτερον -E, 
B, ec, τὶ ; τὸν βαρύτονον -Escor. 72, Aldine. 
2 φθόγγου -u. 
8 πρὸς τὰ γ΄ καὶ μ΄ καὶ σ΄ -f, m, Tr (ἔχει πρὸς ... σ΄’ -Turne- 
bus); omitted by E, B, e, u, Escor. 72, Aldine. 
4 τόνον -Benseler (De Hiatu, p. 528); τόνῳ -Mss. 
5 ἐπιθέντος -f. , 
6 ois’ -E, B, e, Escor. 72; σιβ' -ἃ : τὰ σις" -f, m, r. 
7 KE, B, e, Escor. 72; τόνῳ ἄλλῳ -f, m, r3 τόνον ἄλλως -U, 
Aldine. 
8. KE, B, ἢ, m, rs τὰ δὲ ws’ -e, Escor. 72, Aldine; ra δὲ ιβ΄ 
=U. 
® Xylander ; ἐπόγδοα -Mss. 
9. τὸ δὲ ἐλαχίστου τὸ -U. 


312 


1 





GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1021-1022 


ratio, 256 and 192; and of these let the smaller, 192, 
be placed at the lowest note of the tetrachord and 
the larger, 256, at the highest.2 It is to be proved 
that, when this is filled in with two sesquioctaves, 
there is left an interval of the size that numerically 
expressed is 256 to 243. This is so, for, when the 
lower note has been raised a tone, which is a ses- 
quioctave, it amounts to 216; and, when this has 
been raised again another tone, it amounts to 243, 
for the latter exceeds 216 by 27 and 216 exceeds 192 
by 24, and of these 27 is an eighth of 216 and 24 an 
eighth of 192. Consequently, of these three numbers 
the largest turns out to be sesquioctavan of the 
intermediate and the intermediate sesquioctavan of 
the smallest ; and the interval from the smallest to 
the largest, z.e. that from 192 to 243, amounts to an 
interval of two tones filled in with two sesquioctaves. 
When this is subtracted, however, there remains of 
the whole as an interval left over what is between 
243 and 256, that is thirteen; and this is the very 
reason why they named this number “ leimma.” ὃ 

* For the assignment of the larger numbers to the higher 
notes see 1018 pb supra with note ¢ there, and especially 
[Plutarch], De Musica 1138 Ἐ--, 1139 c, 1140 a and Nico- 
machus, Harmonices Man. 6 and Excerpta 7 (Musici 
Scriptores Graeci, Ὁ. 248, 18-23 and p. 279, 12-14 [Jan]). 
For advocacy of the opposite procedure cf. Adrastus in 
Theon Smyrnaeus, pp. 65, 10-66, 11 (Hiller). On the two 
procedures cf. Burkert, Weisheit und Wissenschaft, p. 359, 


n. 54. 
> See 1018 & supra with notes d and ὁ there. 


11 τουτέστι. . . μέχρι τῶν apy’ -deleted as a scholium by 
Papabasileios (Athena, x [1898], p. 226). 
12 διάτονον -F. 
18 Maurommates ; συμπληροῦμεν -Μ88. 
313 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


3 \ > 3 / - » | 4 
(1022) ἐγὼ μὲν οὖν εὐσημότατα δηλοῦσθαι τὴν ]λάτωνος 
/ ’ / A 3 A 
οἶμαι γνώμην ἐν τούτοις τοῖς ἀριθμοῖς. 
: Ξ ; / 

19. Ἕτεροι δὲ τοῦ" διὰ τεσσάρων ὅρους θέμενοι 
τὸν μὲν ὀξὺν ἐν {τοῖς Σ" on τὸν δὲ βαρὺν ἐ ἐν τοῖς 
σις" ἀναλόγως ἤδη" τοὺς" ἑξῆς περαίνουσιν, πλὴν 
ὅτι τὸ λεῖμμα τῶν δυεῖν τόνων ἢ μεταξὺ λαμβάνουσι. 
τοῦ γὰρ βαρυτέρου τόνον" ἐπιταθέντος γίγνεται 
σμγ΄, τοῦ δ᾽ ὀξυτέρου τόνον' ἀνεθέντος" γίγνεται 
σνς΄" ἔστι γὰρ ἐπόγδοα τὰ μὲν opy’ τῶν ows’ τὰ δὲ 

Bonn’ τῶν σνς᾽ ὥστε τονιαῖον εἶναι τῶν διαστη- 
μάτων ἑκάτερον λείπεσθαι δὲ τὸδ μεταξὺ τῶν 
σμγ΄ καὶ τῶν avs’, ὅπερ οὐκ ἔστιν ἡμιτόνιον ἀλλ᾽ 
ἔλαττον: τὰ μὲν γὰρ σπη΄ τῶν avs’ ὑπερέχει τοῖς 

? \ \ 7 ~ 8 ᾽ὔ 10 a / \ \ 
Ap’ τὰ δὲ opy’ τῶν ats’ ὑπερέχει τοῖς Kl’ τὰ δὲ 
ovs’ τῶν σμγ΄ ὑπερέχει τοῖς wy’: ταῦτα δ᾽ ἀμφο- 

’, 11 ΄ ς “. > 4 See ’ Ἄν. 3 \ 
τέρων" τῶν ὑπεροχῶν ἐλάττω" ἢ ἡμίσεά ἐστι. διὸ 
δυεῖν τόνων καὶ λείμματος, οὐ δυεῖν καὶ ἡμίσεος, 
εὕρηται τὸ διὰ τεσσάρων. καὶ ταῦτα μὲν ἔχει τοι- 

4 > , > A > > / \ > 
avtny ἀπόδειξιν. ἐκεῖνο δ᾽ οὐ πάνυ χαλεπὸν ἐκ 


1 τοῦ -Maurommates (p. 42 in note ad p. 29, 20), B. Miiller 
(1818): : τοὺς -MSS. 2 «τοῖς» -added by Stephanus. 

ἤδη -E, B, e, u, Escor. 79 : τοίνυν -f, m, r, Aldine. 

4 ποὺς ΤΕ C. (scil. ὅρους) : τοῖς -MSS.; τὰ -B. Miiller 
(A873), cf... religua ’: in the versions of Turnebus and 
Ay ΔΉΔΕτι 

5 Maurommates after the version of Xylander; τὸ 
λεῖμμα τῶν δυοῖν τῶν -Stephanus; τῶν λειμμάτων δυεῖν (or 
δυοῖν) τῶν -mss. (with cross in margin Ἢ 7044 τ ΝΣ 
margin -Ε) ; τὸ λεῖμμα δυοῖν τόνοιν -f?, and τηΐ in margin ; 
TO λεῖμμα δυοῖν -r? in margin. 

ὃ τόνον -Benseler (De Hiatu, Ὁ. 528) ; τόνῳ -Mss. 

7 τόνον -e, ἃ, f, m, Escor. 72, Aldine; τόνου -r (with 
three dots above ov); τόνῳ -E, B. 

8 Stephanus; ἀναταθέντος Ἔ (τος superscript over θεν 
erased and replaced by τὸς on the line), B, ἃ (ἀνα over 


314 


GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1022 


So I, for my part, think that Plato’s intention is most 
clearly explained by these numbers.¢ 

19. As terms of the fourth, however, others ὃ put 
the high note at 288 and the low at 216 and then 
determine proportionally those that come next, except 
that they take the “ leimma ”’ to be between the two 
tones. For, when the lower note has been raised a 
tone, the result is 243 and, when the higher has been 
lowered a tone, it is 256, for 243 is nine eighths of 216 
and 288 nine eighths of 256, so that each of the two 
intervals is that of a tone and there is left what is 
between 243 and 256; and this is not a semitone but 
is less, for 288 exceeds 256 by 32 and 243 exceeds 216 
by 27 but 256 exceeds 243 by thirteen, which is less 
than half of both the excesses 32 and 27.° Con- 
sequently it turns out that the fourth consists of two 
tones and a “ leimma,’’ not of two tones and a half. 
Such, then, is the demonstration of this point. As 
to the following point, from what has been said 


@ See 1020 c-p supra with note f on page 301. 

® The alternative procedure described in the following 
lines is given by Nicomachus, Hacerpta 2 (Musici Scriptores 
Graeci, pp. 269, 8-270, 6 [Jan]). 

¢ This is not proof that the leimma is less than half of the 
tone, but the same mistake of substituting for the ratios 
the differences between their terms is committed by Nico- 
machus in Ewcerpta 2 (Musici Scriptores Graeci, p. 270, 4-6 
and 6-12 [Jan]; ef. also ibid., pp. 267, 15-268, 2). 


erasure), f, m, Escor. 72; ἀναθέντος -e' (τα superscript 
between a and @ -e*); ἀνατεθέντος -r. 


ων 
® Maurommates; τὸ -Εἰ ; τῶν -Β, us τὸν -all other mss., 
Aldine. 
10 πρῖς λβ΄. . . τῶν ows’ ὑπερέχει -omitted by f, m, r. 
1 Turnebus : ; ἀμφότερα -e, u, f, m, r, Escor. 72, Aldine; 
ἀμφότερα after ὑπεροχῶν - 
ἐλάττων -f, r (with three dots above w). 
$15 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1022) τῶν προειρημένων συνιδεῖν," τί δήποτε φήσας ὁ 
’ 

ἅτων ἡμιολίους καὶ ἐπιτρίτους καὶ ἐπογδόους 

C γίγνεσθαι διαστάσεις ἐν τῷ συμπληροῦσθαι τὰς 

ἐπιτρίτους" ταῖς ἐπογδόοις οὐκ ἐμνήσθη τῶν ἡμι- 

τ 3 \ / t \ ἐ / = 
ολίων ἀλλὰ παρέλιπε. τὸ yap ἡμιόλιον τοῦ 
ἐπιτρίτου τῷ ἐπογδόῳ (μεῖζόν ἐστι, ὥστε τοῦ 
ἐπογδόουν" τῷ ἐπιτρίτῳ προστιθεμένου συμπλη- 
ροῦσθαι καὶ τὸ ἡμιόλιον. 

20. ᾿ἹἹποδεδειγμένων δὲ τούτων, τὸ μὲν συμ- 
πληροῦν τὰ διαστήματα καὶ παρεντάττειν τὰς 
μεσότητας, | εἰ καὶ μηδεὶς ἐ ἐτύγχανε πεποιηκὼς πρό- 
τερον, ὑμῖν" ἂν αὐτοῖς ἕνεκα" γυμνασίας παρῆκα" 
νῦν δὲ πολλοῖς κἀγαθοῖς ἀνδράσιν ἐξειργασμένου 
TOUTOU μάλιστα δὲ Kpavrope | καὶ Κλεάρχῳ, καὶ 
Θεοδώρῳ tots’ Σολεῦσι, μικρὰ περὶ τῆς τούτων 
διαφορᾶς εἰπεῖν οὐκ ἀχρηστόν ἐστιν. ὁ γὰρ Θεό- 

> ΤΑΣ τς Eee , , 8 A 5. 3.5. Ὃ 

D δωρος, οὐχ ὡς ἐκεῖνοι δύο στίχους" ποιῶν ἀλλ᾽ ἐπὶ 
μιᾶς εὐθείας ἐφεξῆς τούς τε διπλασίους ἐκτάττων 
καὶ τοὺς τριπλασίους, πρῶτον μὲν ἰσχυρίζεται τῇ 

1 συνειδεῖν -u, f, πη}. 

2 τὰς διαστάσεις -F. 

8 ¢. . .> -added by Leonicus ; τῷ ἐπογδόῳ τῷ -EH, e, u, f, 

δ. ν sa 7123 τῷ ἐπογδόῳ καὶ τῷ -B. 
προστιθεμένῳ -f, m, τ. 
Be ἡμῖν -all other mss., Aldine. 
αὐνοῖς evexay -Β. 
‘rots -omitted by f. 
8 στοίχους -f, m, r (cf. 1027 τ supra [chap. 29 ad finem] : 


> A ’, 
ἐν δυσὶ στίχοις). 


1 σι ᾿. 





α 2,6. in Timaeus 36 a 6- 1 (see 1090 B supra), where in 
B 1 Plato says τῷ τοῦ ἐπογδόου διαστήματι τὰ ἐπίτριτα πάντα 
συνεπληροῦτο. In paraphrasing this Nicomachus explicitly 
included the ἡμιόλια (Harmonices Man. 8= Musici Scriptores 
Graeci, p. 250, 10-11 [Jan]), and the filling in of the ἡμιόλια 
also was taken for granted by Proclus (Jn Platonis Timaewm 


316 








GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1022 


before it is not very difficult either to see why, after 
Plato had said that there came to be intervals of 
three to two and of four to three and of nine to eight, 
when saying that those of four to three are filled in 
with those of nine to eight he did not mention those 
of three to two but omitted them.* The reason is 
that the sesquialter (is greater than) the sesquiterce 
by the sesquioctave {80 that with the sesquioctave's) 
addition to the sesquiterce the sesquialter is filled in 
as well.? 

20. After the exposition of these matters the task 
of filling in the intervals and inserting the means ¢ 1 
should still have left to you for an exercise to do your- 
selves though no one at all had happened to have 
done it before ; but now that this has been worked 
out by many excellent men and especially by Crantor 
and Clearchus and Theodorus, all of Soli,? it is not 
unprofitable to say a few words about the way in 
which they disagree. For Theodorus unlike those 
others does not make two rows but sets out the 
double and the triple numbers one after another in a 
single straight line,¢ relying for this in the first place 


ii, p. 170, 25-26 and p. 175, 3-5 with p. 179, 3-6 and p. 185, 
5-6 and 13-16 [Diehl]); cf. B. Kytzler, Hermes, ἸΧΧΧΥ 
(1959), pp. 401-402. 

> Cf. Chalcidius, Platonis Timaeus, p. 115, 11-15 (Wrobel) 
=p. 97, 7-10 (Waszink). 

¢ See 1020 a supra with note 6 there. 

¢ Crantor, frag. 6 (Kayser)=frag. 6 (Mullach, Frag. 
Philos. Graec. iii, pp. 143-145) and Clearchus, frag. 4 
(Wehrli) ; see 1027 pv supra (chap. 29 sub finem) with notes 
d and ὁ there. 

4 So later Severus, Porphyry, and Proclus himself 
(Proclus, In Platonis Timaeum ii, p. 171, 4-9; p. 175, 17- 
21; and p. 192, 24-27 [Diehl]), who does not mention the 
priority of Theodorus of Soli. 

317 


(1022) 


K 


1027 F 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


λεγομένῃ κατὰ μῆκος σχίσει' τῆς οὐσίας δύο ποι- 
ovon μοίρας ὡς ἐκ μιᾶς, οὐ τέσσαρας ἐκ δυεῖν, 
ἔπειτά φησι τὰς τῶν μεσοτήτων παρεντάξεις οὕτω 
λαμβάνειν προσήκειν" χώραν: εἰ δὲ μή, ταραχὴν 
καὶ σύγχυσιν ἔσεσθαι καὶ μεταστάσεις εἰς" τὸ πρῶ- 
τον εὐθὺς τριπλάσιον ἐκ τοῦ πρώτου διπλασίου τῶν 
συμπληροῦν" ἑκάτερον ὀφειλόντων. τοῖς δὲ περὶ 
τὸν Kpdvropa βοηθοῦσιν αἵ τε θέσεις τῶν ἀριθμῶν, 
ἐπιπέδων ἐπιπέδοις καὶ τετραγώνων τετραγώνοις 
καὶ κύβων κύβοις ἀντιθέτως συζυγούντων, τῇ τε 
μὴ κατὰ τάξιν αὐτῶν λήψει ἀλλ᾽ ἐναλλὰξ ἀρτίων 
καὶ" (30 b.) περιττῶν" (αὐτὸς ὁ Πλάτων). τὴν γὰρ 


1 σχίσει -m (i Gver Original ἐ), ‘Turnebus ; σχέσει -all other 
mMss., Aldine. 

2 ποιοῦσι -u 3 ποιήσῃ -Aldine. 

3 f,m,1r3 προσήκει -E, B, e, u, Escor. 72. 

4 Emperius (Op. Philol., p. 340), cf. ‘‘ traiectiones ”’ 
-Xylander ; μεταστὰς εἰς -MSS. 

5 E, B ; συμπληρούντων -all other mss., Aldine. 

6 ἀρτίων καὶ 7... vac. 4-1/2 lines -E; vac. 2-1/2 lines 
-B ... κατὰ τὰ αὐτὰ (1022 © supra [chap. 21 init.]) -E, B; 


apriwy καὶ emi... vac. 14-f; vac. 1I3-m,r... κατὰ τὰ αὐτὰ 


-f,m, r3 ἀρτίων καὶ ἐπὶ κατὰ (κατὰ -Escor. 723 ἐπὶκατὰ -u) 
τὰ αὐτὰ -e, u, Escor. 72; see 1022 © supra (chap. 21 init.), 
apparatus criticus, note 2 on page 212. 

7 See 1017 c supra (chap. 30, page 268), apparatus criticus, 
note 9: δευτέρα περιττῶν -E, B; δευτέρα (δευτέρα δὲ -f) 
τῶν περιττῶν -f, τὰ, τ, Aldine; δευτεριττῶν -e, αν, Escor. 72 
(ρατῶνπε -Escor. 72 in margin with three dots after δευτε). 

ὃ <adros 6 Πλάτων» -added by Pohlenz; «Πλάτων -B. 
Miiller (Hermes, iv [1870], pp. 399-403 and v [1871], p. 
154). 





α Timaeus 36 5 6-7 (ταύτην οὖν τὴν σύστασιν πᾶσαν διπλῆν 
κατὰ μῆκος σχίσας .. .): ef. Proclus (Jn Platonis Timaeum 
ii, p. 237, 15-27 [Diehl] and Jn Platonis Rem Publicam ii, 


318 





GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1022, 1027 


upon what is stated to be the cleavage of the sub- 
stance lengthwise that makes two parts presumably 
out of one,? not four out of two, and in the second 
place saying that it is suitable for the insertions of 
the means to be arranged in this sequence, as other- 
wise there will be disorder and confusion and trans- 
positions to the very first triple from the first double 
of the terms that ought to fill in each of the two.? 
Crantor and his followers,° however, are supported 
by the position of the numbers, paired off with plane 
numbers over against plane and square over against 
square and cubic over against cubic numbers,? and 
in their being taken not in order but alternately even 


and (30 b.) odd by <Plato himself>.¢ For after 


p. 143, 20-21 [Kroll]), who also takes this to show that the 
numbers were meant to be arranged in a single row. 

> 'The harmonic and arithmetical means of the first triple 
(3 and 2) are already given by the first double and its means 
(1, $ ξ, 2); of. the objection to the lambda of Adrastus 
made by Proclus, Jn Platonis Timaeum ii, pp. 187, 28-188, 
1 and p. 192, 27-29 (Diehl). 

¢ Among them Clearchus, who was mentioned with 
Crantor just above, and Plutarch himself. The arrange- 
ment in the form of a lambda is assumed later by Theon 
Smyrnaeus (pp. 94, 11-96, 5 [Hiller]) and Macrobius (/n 
Somnium Scipionis 1, vi, 46); of those who adopted it 
earlier Proclus names only Adrastus, who elaborated a triple 
form of it (Proclus, In Platonis Timaeum ii, pp. 170, 26- 
171, 4; p. 187, 17-26; and p. 192, 24-26 [Diehl]), which is 
represented by the three successive diagrams of Chalcidius 
(Platonis Timaeus, pp. 98, 13-118, 3 [Wrobel]=pp. 82, 20- 
99, 9 [Waszink]). 

@ See 1017 v-E supra (chap. 11), pages 271, note d-273, 
note a. 

¢ In Timaeus 35 B 4- 2 the order is 2, 3, 4, 9, 8, 27, 1.6. 
alternately even and odd (cf. Macrobius, Jn Somnium 
Scipionis τι, ii, 17), whereas the natural order (. . . 4, 8, 9, 27) 
would be... even, even, odd, odd. 


319 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1027) μονάδα κοινὴν οὖσαν ἀμφοῖν προτάξας λαμβάνει 

τὰ ui καὶ ἐφεξῆς τὰ KO, μονονουχὶ" δεικνύων ἡ ἡμῖν 

1028 ἣ ἣν ἑκατέρῳ γένει “χώραν ἀποδίδωσι. ταῦτα μὲν 

οὖν ἑτέροις προσήκει μᾶλλον. ἐξακριβοῦν, τὸ δ᾽ 

ἀπολειπόμενον οἰκεῖόν ἐστι τῆς ὑποκειμένης ἡμῖν 
πραγματείας. 

F. 31. Οὐ yap ἐπίδειξιν ὁ Πλάτων θεωρίας μαθη- 

ματικῆς ποιούμενος εἰς φυσικὴν ὑπόθεσιν μὴ δεο- 

μένην μεσότητας ἀριθμητικὰς καὶ ἁρμονικὰς παρ- 

εἰσήγαγεν ἀλλὰ ὡς μάλιστα δὴ τῇ συστάσει τῆς 

ψυχῆς τοῦ λόγου τούτου" προσήκοντος. καίτοι 

τινὲς μὲν ἐν τοῖς τάχεσι τῶν πλανωμένων σφαι- 

ρῶν τινὲς δὲ μᾶλλον ἐ ἐν τοῖς ἀποστήμασιν ἔνιοι δ᾽ ἐν 

τοῖς μεγέθεσι τῶν ἀστέρων οἱ δ᾽ ἄγαν ἀκριβοῦν δο- 

Β κοῦντες ἐν ταῖς τῶν ἐπικύκλων διαμέτροις ζητοῦσι 

τὰς εἰρημένας ἀναλογίας, ὡς τὴν ψυχὴν ἕνεκα τού- 

των τοῦ δημιουργοῦ τοῖς οὐρανίοις ἐναρμόσαντος" 


1 E, B; μονονουχὶ οὖν -all other mss., Aldine. 
2 τοῦ λόγου τοῦ -U. 3 οὐρανοῖς ἐναρμώσαντες -U. 
4 See 1027 © supra with note a on page 269. 
> Plutarch may have in mind here not only the order 
9, 8, 27 to which he has just referred but also the omission 
of 16, the next power of two between 8 and 27 (cf. B. Kytzler, 
Hermes, \xxxvii [1959], pp. 404-405). 

¢ See 1017 © supra (chap. 11) with note f on page 271. 

@¢ With all that follows in this sentence cf. Proclus, Jn 
Platonis Timaeum ii, pp. 212, 12-213, 7 (Diehl). 

ε Plato in Timaeus 36 p 5-7 says that of the seven circles 
three move τάχει. .. ὁμοίως and four ἀλλήλοις καὶ τοῖς τρισὶν 
ἀνομοίως ἐν λόγῳ δέ and in Timaeus 39 p 4-5 speaks of 
ἁπασῶν τῶν ὀκτὼ περιόδων τὰ πρὸς ἄλληλα. .. τάχη (cf. Re- 
public 617 a 7-8 3). For the introduction of ‘ A edren? 
into the astronomy of the Timaeus see supra Plat. Quaest. 
1007 a with note ὦ there. 

t Cf. Chalcidius, Platonis Timaeus, p. 167, 8-17 (Wrobel) 


320 


<= Shee 





GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1027-1028 


putting at the head the unit, which is common to 
both,? he takes eight and next thereafter twenty- 
seven,” all but showing us° the position that he assigns 
to each of the two kinds. Now, to treat this with 
greater precision is a task that belongs to others ; 
but what remains is a proper part of our present 
disquisition. 

31. It is so because Plato did not as a display of 
mathematical learning drag arithmetical and har- 
monic means into a discourse on natural philosophy 
where they are not wanted but introduced them on 
the assumption that this calculation is especially 
appropriate to the composition of the soul. Yet 
certain people 2 look for the prescribed proportions 
in the velocities of the planetary spheres,’ certain 
others rather in their distances,’ some in the magni- 
tudes of the stars,’ and those with a reputation for 
exceedingly exact investigation in the diameters of 
the epicycles,” assuming these to be the ends for 
which the artificer fitted to the heavenly bodies the 


=p. 148, 12-19 (Waszink); Macrobius, In Somnium Sci- 
pionis τι, iii, 14-15 (= Porphyrii in Platonis Timaeum.. . 
Fragmenta, p. 63, 5-21 [Sodano]); Hippolytus, Refutatio 
iv, 10, 1-11, 5 (pp. 42, 17-44, 22 [Wendland]). These are all 
attempts to interpret Timaeus 36 pv 2-4, for which cf. Proclus, 
In Platonis Timaeum ii, p. 265, 8-29 (Diehl). 

σ Perhaps by interpretation of Republic 616 Ἑ 3-8: cf. 
Proclus, Jn Platonis Rem Publicam ii, Ὁ. 218, 2-28; p. 219, 
23-29 ; and pp. 221, 28-222, 2 (Kroll) with Theon Smyrnaeus, 
p. 143, 14-18 (Hiller) and Taylor, Commentary on Plato’s 
Timaeus, p. 161, n. 2. 

* Against the attempt to introduce epicycles into Plato’s 
astronomy (6.5. Theon Smyrnaeus, pp. 188, 25-189, 6 
{Hiller] ; Chalcidius, Platonis Timaeus, Ὁ. 176, 6-13 [Wrobel] 
=p. 156, 19-24 [Waszink]) cf. Proclus, In Platonis Timaeum 
ii, p. 264, 19-25 and iii, p. 96, 13-32 and p. 146, 14-28 (Diehl). 


321 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


> ε A , / 
(1028) εἰς ἑπτὰ μοίρας νενεμημένην. πολλοὶ δὲ καὶ τὰ 
\ a / > A a 
Πυθαγορικὰ δεῦρο μεταφέρουσιν, ἀπὸ τοῦ μέσου 
A ~ / ὃ 
τὰς τῶν σωμάτων ἀποστάσεις τριπλασιάζοντες. 
γίγνεται δὲ τοῦτο κατὰ μὲν τὸ πῦρ μονάδος τιθε- 
μένης κατὰ δ᾽ ἀντίχθονα τριῶν κατὰ δὲ γῆν ἐννέα 
καὶ κατὰ σελήνην εἰκοσιεπτὰ καὶ κατὰ τὸν “Ερμοῦ" 
~ ‘ > , \ \ / ~ x 
μιᾶς Kat ὀγδοήκοντα κατὰ δὲ Φωσφόρον τριῶν καὶ 
7 ᾿ f > Seen \ A ν ’ \ Lf \ , 
μ΄ καὶ σ΄ Kat αὐτὸν δὲ Tov ἡλιον θ΄ Kai κ΄ καὶ ψ', 
“ 4 ¢ , ΄, 4 , 4. \ \ 
ὅς γε ἅμα τετράγωνός Te καὶ κύβος ἐστί: διὸ Kat 
τὸν ἥλιον ἔστιν ὅτε τετράγωνον καὶ κύβον προσ- 


4 4 \ \ Ἁ ” 3. / 
C ayopevovow. οὕτως δὲ καὶ τοὺς ἄλλους ἐπανάγουσι 


1 ἀποστάσει -B. 


2 épunv -m, Yr, Escor. 72°F (ἣν superscript over οὔ), 
Aldine. 
8 ὅς γ᾽ -Hubert; ὅτι -F, B, e, u, Aldine; ὅτε -f, m, r, 
Escor. 72; ὅστις -Stephanus (** qui numerus”’ -Turnebus). 


PGF; Plutarch, Numa xl, 1-2 (67 p): . . . τοῦ σύμπαντος 
κόσμου, οὗ μέσον οἱ Πυθαγορι κοὶ τὸ πῦρ ἱδρῦσθαι νομίζουσι καὶ 
τοῦθ᾽ Ἑστίαν καλοῦσι καὶ μονάδα... 

> Central fire and counter-earth identify this as the 

_ Pythagorean system referred to by Aristotle (De Caelo 293 
a 20-27 and Metaphysics 986 a 10-13) and elsewhere ascribed 
to Philolaus (frags. A 16 and 17 [D.-K.]); but in that 
system the orbit of the sun was located immediately above 
that of the moon (Philolaus, frag. A 16 [D.-K.]; Alexander, 
Metaph., pp. 38, 20-39, 3 and p. 40, 3-6) as it was by Plato 
and Aristotle too (cf. Proclus, In Platonis Timaeum iii, 
pp. 60, 31-61, 2 and p. 62, 3-6 [Diehl] and Jn Platonis Rem 
Publicam li, p. 220, 1-21 [Kroll]). The Pythagoreanizing 
interpretation of the Timaeus reported by Plutarch in the 
present passage is a contamination of the Philolaic system 
and the planetary order widely though not universally 
adopted later (cf. Heath, Aristarchus of Samos, pp. 106-107 ; 
Burkert, Weisheit und Wissenschaft, pp. 297-299, especially 


322 





GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1028 


soul that had been distributed into seven parts. 
Many carry over into this context Pythagorean 
notions too, multiplying by three the distances of the 
bodies from the middle. This is brought about by 
placing the unit at the central fire, three at the 
counter-earth, nine at the earth and 27 at the moon 
and 81 at Mercury, 243 at Venus and at the sun 
itself 729, which is at the same time a square and 
a cubic number ὃ ; and this is the reason why they 
sometimes call the sun too a square and a cube.? In 
this way these people increase the other numbers 


notes 121, 122, and 129, to which add Plutarch, De Facie 
925 a), an order which, if the purpose of it was to make the 
sun midmost of the planets (cf. Theon Smyrnaeus, p. 138, 
16-18 [Hiller]; Chalcidius, Platonis Timaeus, p. 140, 8-9 
[Wrobel]=p. 119, 16-18 [Waszink]; Philo Jud., Quis 
Rerum Div. Heres 222-224=iii, p. 50, 9-19 [Wendland] ; 
Proclus, Jn Platonis Timaewim iii, Ὁ. 62, 7-9 and 18-22 
[Diehl]), is incompatible with a system in which the earth 
and the counter-earth are planets. 

¢ 729 =277=—93, See the next note im/ra. 

4 Not the Pythagoreans to whom the original Philolaic 
system is ascribed (see the note next but one supra). They 
are said to have assigned the number seven to the sun as 
being the seventh of the moving bodies counted inwards from 
the fixed stars (Alexander, Metaph., pp. 38, 20-39, 3; 
Asclepius, Metaph., Ὁ. 36, 5-11; A. Delatte, Btudes sur la 
littérature pythagoricienne, p. 169 [Anecdota Arith. A 1, 
lines 20-22]) ; and, had they applied the triplication from the 
central fire as the unit that Plutarch here reports, they would 
have had to associate the number 81 with the sun. The later 
order with Mercury and Venus located between the moon 
and the sun, however, makes the sun seventh from the 
central fire; and in such triplication or multiplication by 
any given ratio the seventh number is always both a square 
and a cube (Philo Jud., De Opificio Mundi 92-94=i, pp. 31, 
22-32, 12 [Cohn]; Anatolius, p. 35, 14-21 [Heiberg] and 
partially in Iamblichus, Theolog. Arith., pp. 54, 13-55, 1 
[De Falco} ; cf. Theon Smyrnaeus, pp. 34, 16-35, 17 [Hiller]). 


323 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1028) τοῖς τριπλασιασμοῖς,᾿ πολὺ τοῦ κατὰ λόγον οὗτοί 
γε παραπαίοντες, εἴ TU τῶν γεωμετρικῶν ὄφελός 
ἐστιν ἀποδείξεων, καὶ μακρῷ πιθανωτέρους παρα- 
βαλεῖν" αὐτοῖς ἀποδεικνύοντες τοὺς ὁρμωμένους 
ἐκεῖθεν, οὐδ᾽ αὐτοὺς παντάπασιν ἐξακριβοῦντας" 
ἀλλὰ ὡς ἔγγιστα λέγοντας" ὅτι τῆς μὲν ἡλίου δια- 
μέτρου πρὸς τὴν διάμετρον τῆς γῆς λόγος ἐστὶ 
δωδεκαπλάσιος τῆς δὲ γῆς αὖ" πάλιν διαμέτρου 
πρὸς τὴν σελήνης διάμετρον τριπλάσιος ὁ δὲ φαι- 
νόμενος ἐλάχιστος τῶν ἀπλανῶν ἀστέρων οὐκ ἐλάτ- 
τονα τῆς διαμέτρου τῆς γῆς ἢ τριτημόριον ἔχει 

D τὴν διάμετρον τῇ δὲ ὅλῃ σφαίρᾳ τῆς γῆς πρὸς τὴν 
ὅλην σφαῖραν τῆς σελήνης ὡς ἑπτὰ καὶ εἴκοσι πρὸς 
(ἕν) ἐστι͵, ἷ Φωσφόρου δὲ καὶ γῆς αἱ μὲν διάμετροι 
τὸν διπλάσιον at δὲ σφαῖραι τὸν ὀκταπλάσιονΣ" 

1 τριπλασμοῖς -e, u, Escor. 72, Aldine. 
2 εἴ re -e, u, f, m, r, Escor. 72, Aldine. 
Ney ee τιν (παραβάλλειν -u), m, Escor. 72; παραλαβεῖν 
-f, r; παραλαβεῖν αὐτοὶ -Wyttenbach; «ὡς» παραβαλεῖν 


-B. Miiller (1873) : but cf. Lucian, Demosthenis Encomium 
32 (iii, p. 376, 23-24 [J acobitz}) : «ον παιδιὰ παραβάλλειν τῷ 
τούτου κρότῳ. ee 

aT, Ὑ: ΕΞ δ Mteh. -E, B, e, u, Escor. 72, Aldine. 

δε superscript over a -E1; λέγοντας -all other Mss. 

6 EK, Bs; τῆς γῆς δ᾽ ad -all other mss., Aldine. 

«ἕν -added by Wyttenbach ; πρόσεστι -Μ88. ; πρὸς (ἕν 
λόγος» ἐστί -Β. Miiller (1873). 

αἱ δὲ σφαῖραι τὸν ὀκταπλάσιον -omitted by r. 


¢ They would be Mars: 2187, Jupiter: 6561, Saturn: 
19,683, fixed stars: 59,049. 

> These are approximately the figures of Pee ei (the 
diameters of earth, moon, and sun are as 1:4: 124); ef. 
Heath, Aristarchus of Samos, pp. 342 and 350 

¢ That is to say not less than the diameter assigned to the 
moon by Hipparchus (¢f. Boll, R.-H. vi [1909], col. 2411, 
6-11). Contrary to the contention that all the fixed stars are 


324 











GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1028 


also by triplications, going far astray of what is 
reasonable, if there is any use in geometrical demon- 
strations, and proving that in comparison with them- 
selves those who proceed from such demonstrations 
are far more credible, though these are themselves 
speaking not with absolute precision either but in 
close approximations when they say that the ratio of 
the sun’s diameter to the diameter of the earth is 
twelve to one and of the earth’s diameter on the 
other hand to the moon’s diameter is three to one ὃ 
and that what appears to be the smallest of the 
fixed stars has a diameter not less than a third part 
of the diameter of the earth ὁ and that for the whole 
sphere of the earth to the whole sphere of the moon 
the ratio is as twenty-seven to (one) ὁ and that the 
diameters of Venus and of the earth have the ratio 
of two to one ὁ and their spheres the ratio of eight to 


larger than the earth (e.g. Cleomedes, De Motu Circulari 1, 
xi, 58 and τι, iii, 97 =pp. 106, 2-8 and 176, 11-24 [Ziegler] ; 
Proclus, Jn Platonis Rem Publicam ii, p. 218, 5-13 [Kroll]) 
Philoponus (Meteor., Ὁ. 15, 18-23) in support of Aristotle 
(Meteorology 339 Ὁ 7-9; cf. Areius Didymus, Hpitomes 
Frag. Phys. 8 [Dox. Graeci, Ὁ. 450, 10-11]) cites unnamed 
astronomers (possibly from Arrian, cf. zbid., p. 15, 13) to 
the effect that the earth is not smaller than all the fixed stars. 

tae. 2: 15 (ef. Euclid, Elements xii, Prop.’18).. “850 
Hipparchus as reported by Theon Smyrnaeus, p. 197, 9-12 
(Hiller) and Chalcidius, Platonis Timaeus, p. 161, 18-22 
(Wrobel) =p. 143, 5-8 (Waszink). 

¢ According to Cleomedes, De Motu Circulari τι, iii, 96 
(p. 174, 25-27 [Ziegler]) the diameter of Venus is one-sixth 
that of the sun; it would then be to the earth’s diameter as 
two to one if, as Plutarch has just said (1028 c supra), the 
sun’s diameter is to the earth’s as twelve to one. According 
to Ptolemy Hipparchus said- that the apparent diameter of 
Venus is about a tenth that of the sun (B. R. Goldstein, “ἡ The 
Arabic Version of Ptolemy’s Planetary Hypotheses,” Trans- 


325 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1028) ἔ ἔχουσι λόγον, τὸ δὲ διάστημα τῆς ἐκλειπτικῆς 
σκιᾶς τῆς" διαμέτρου τῆς σελήνης τριπλάσιον, ὃ ὃ δ᾽ 
ἐκτρέπεται πλάτος ἡ σελήνη τοῦ διὰ μέσου" τῶν 
ζῳδίων" ἐφ᾽ ἑκάτερα δωδεκάμοιρον. αἱ δὲ πρὸς 
ἥλιον" σχέσεις αὐτῆς ἐν τριγώνοις καὶ τετραγώνοις 
ἀποστήμασι διχοτόμους καὶ ἀμφικύρτους σχημα- 
τισμοὺς λαμβάνουσιν' ἐξ δὲ ζῴδια διελθοῦσα τὴν" 
πανσέληνον ὥσπερ τινὰ συμφωνίαν ἐν ἑξατόνῳ" 

EK διὰ πασῶν ἀποδίδωσι. τοῦ δὲ ἡλίου περὶ τὰς 
τροπὰς ἐλάχιστα καὶ μέγιστα περὶ τὴν ἰσημερίανΣ" 
ἔχοντος κινήματα, δι᾿ ὧν ἀφαιρεῖ τῆς ἡμέρας καὶ 


1 τοῦ -f. 

2 rot διὰ μέσου (or διὰ μέσων) ~Turnebus ; τῆς διαμέτρου 
-Ει, Β ; τοῦ διαμέτρου -all other mss., Aldine. 

3 ζῳδίων -E, B, e, us ζώων -f, m, r, Escor. 72, Aldine. 

‘EB; SSG ἀμ -all other atss. ιἐ Aldine. 

5 ἥλιον “Bs ἡλίου (with ον superscript over ov and acute 
accent superscript over ἡ) -Εἰ : ἡλίου -all other mss., Aldine. 

6 τὸν -U. 

7 K,m,r; ἐξατόνῳ -B, f; ἀξατόνῳ -e, u, Escor. 72 (with 
€ superscript over a). 

8 Kk, Β ; περὶ τῆς ἰσημερίας -all other mss., Aldine. 


actions of the American Philos. Soc., N.S. lvii, 4 satiny 
p. 8, col. 1 sub finenr). 

α re 25 tae. 

> Cf. Plutarch, De Facie 923 B and my note ad loc. 
(L.C.L. xii, Ὁ. 57, note d). 

ο Cf. Theon Smyrnaeus, p. 194, 8-13 and p. 135, 14-15 
(Hiller) with Chalcidius, Platonis Timaeus, p. 157, 14-15 
(Wrobel)=p. 117, 8-9 (Waszink); Geminus, Mlementa 
Astronomiae xii, 21 with v, 53 (pp. 142, 25-144, 1 and p. 62, 
8-9 [Manitius]) ; Martianus Capella, viii, 867. The devia- 
tion to either side of the ecliptic is given as five degrees by 
Ptolemy, Syntawis v, 12 (i, p. 401, 10-15 [Heiberg )) and as 
five and a half degrees by Proclus, Hypot yposis iv, 2 (pp. 86, 
24-88, 1 {Manitius]). For ὁ διὰ μέσου (instead of the more 


326 








GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1028 


one 4 and that the extent of the shadow eclipsing the 
moon is triple her diameter ? but that the breadth of 
the moon’s deviation to one side or the other of the 
circle through the middle of the zodiacal signs is 
twelve degrees of latitude.* Her positions relative 
to the sun in trine and quartile aspects assume the 
configurations of half and gibbous?; and, when she 
has traversed six signs of the zodiac,’ she exhibits the 
plenilune as it were a consonance consisting of the 
six tones of an octave.f As the sun has his minimal 
movement at the solstices and his maximal move- 
ment at the equinox,’ of these movements by which 


common ὁ διὰ μέσων) τῶν ζῳδίων cf. ‘Theon Smyrnaeus, p. 
133, 21 and p. 135, 18 (Hiller) and Simplicius, De Caelo, 
p. 494, 27-28. 

ὦ Cf. Pliny, .V.Z/. ii, 80 (“ itague in quadrato solis dividua 
est, in triquetro scminani ambitur orbe, inpletur autem: in 
adverso ...’’) and Proclus, In Platonis Rem Publicam ii, 
p. 44, 18-22 (Kroll). For the terminology cf. Geminus, 
Elementa Asironomiae ii, 1-19 (pp. 18, 16-26, 2 [ Manitius]) ; 
Ptolemy, J'etrabiblos 1, xiv, 1 (pp. 35, 20-36, 4 [ Boll-Boer]) ; 
and A. Bouché-Leclercq, L’astrologie grecque (Paris, 1899), 
pp. 165-172. 

¢ i.e. when she is in opposition, ὅταν κατὰ διάμετρον γένηται 
τῷ ἡλίῳ... (Geminus, op. cit., ix, 9=p. 126, 24-26 [Mani- 
tius Ji 

f "" . Censorinus, De Die Natali xiii, 5 (p. 24, 2-4 
{[Hultsch]): “*. . . tonos esse sex, in quibus sit dia pason 
symphonia,”’ where the six tones are not as here, however, 
the six signs of the zodiac through which the moon passes 
from conjunction to opposition. For this correlation of the 
plenilune with the octave cf. rather Ptolemy, Harmonica, 
p. 108, 13-18 and p. 109, 4-6 (Diiring) and A. Boeckh, 
Gesammelte Kleine Schriften iii (Leipzig, 1866), p. 173, n. 3. 

g ΟἿ, Cleomedes, De Motu Circulari 1, vi, 28 and 31-32 
(p. 52, 13-20; pp. 56, 27-58, 1; and p. 58, 13-15 [Ziegler}). 
On this and the other errors in this sentence of Plutarch’s 
cf. O. Neugebauer, A.J.P., Ixiii (1942), pp. 458-459. 


327 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1028) τῇ νυκτὶ προστίθησιν ἢ τοὐναντίον, οὗτος ὁ λόγος 
ἐστίν: ἐν ταῖς, πρώταις ἡμέραις A’ μετὰ τὰς" χει- 
μερινὰς, τροπὰς τῇ ἡμέρᾳ προστίθησι τὸ ἕκτον τῆς 
ὑπεροχῆς ἣν ἡ μεγίστη νὺξ πρὸς τὴν βραχυτάτην 
ἡμέραν" ἐποίει" ταῖς" δ᾽ ἐφεξῆς Nn’ τὸ τρίτον τὸ δὲ 
ἥμισυ ταῖς λοιπαῖς ἄχρι τῆς ἰσημερίας, ἐν ἐξαπλα- 
σίοις καὶ τριπλασίοις διαστήμασι τοῦ χρόνου τὴν 
ἀνωμαλίαν ἐπανισῶν. Χαλδαῖοι δὲ λέγουσι τὸ ἔαρ 

F ἐν τῷ διὰ τεσσάρων γίγνεσθαι πρὸς τὸ μετόπωρον 
ἐν δὲ τῷ διὰ πέντε πρὸς τὸν χειμῶνα πρὸς δὲ τὸ 
θέρος ἐν τῷ διὰ πασῶν. εἰ δ᾽ ὀρθῶς ὁ ὁ ᾿ὐριπίδης 
διορίζεται θέρους τέσσαρας μῆνας καὶ χειμῶνος 


ἴσους 
/ 3 >? , 2 ’ὔ “ ’ 9» 
φίλης T ὀπώρας διπτύχους Hpos T ἴσους 
1 ἐν <yap> ταῖς -Wyttenbach. 
2 τὰς -Stephanus; yap-Mss. 3 ἡμέραν -omitted by B. 
4 éproet -B. ἘΞ, rais'-f, m, &; τὰς -all other mss., Aldine. 
6 B. Miiller (1873); ἐπανισοῦντος -Mss. 
« A sixth, a third, and a half of the excess of the longest 
night over the shortest day if added to the shortest day = 
the longest day, 1.6. the day at the summer solstice and not 
that at the equinox. Plutarch’s fractions should have been 
a twelfth, a sixth, and a fourth as in Cleomedes, De Motu 
Circulari 1, vi, 27-28 (pp. 50, 15-52, 2 [Ziegler]) and 
Martianus Capella, viii, 878. 

δ 2,6. the total increment of the second thirty days ($+ 3) 
is threefold and the total increment of the third (3+ 3 3+ 4) is 
sixfold the first (ὁ ). For the expression compare τὴν τῆς 
τύχης ἀνωμαλίαν ἐπανισοῦν (De Fraterno Amore 484. Ὁ). 

¢ So also Aristides Quintilianus, De Afuwsica iii, 19, who 
says (p. 119, 15-18 [Winnington-Ingram]), however, that 
these ratios of the seasons were ascribed to Pythagoras and 
that (ibid., p. 119, 10-15) they follow from assignment of the 
numbers eight (that of air) to spring, four (that of fire) to 
summer, six (that of earth) to autumn, and twelve (that of 
water) to winter. The correlation of these numbers with the 


328 























GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1028 


he subtracts from the day and adds to the night or 
contrariwise this is the ratio: in the first thirty days 
after the winter solstice he adds to the day a sixth of 
the difference by which the longest night exceeded 
the shortest day and in the next thirty a third and 
in the rest until the equinox a half,* thus equalizing 
the disparity of the time in sixfold and threefold 
intervals.2 The Chaldaeans assert that spring turns 
out to be related to autumn in the ratio of the fourth 
and to winter in that of the fifth and to summer in 
that of the octave.* If Euripides is right. however, 
in distinguishing four months of summer and an equal 
number of winter 


And of dear autumn twain and twain of spring,?@ 


seasons, however, depends upon the correlation in the 
Timaeus of the four regular solids with air, fire, earth, and 
water (ibid., pp. 118, 29-119, 9); and it results, moreover, 
in making three to two, the fifth, the ratio of winter to spring 
rather than that of spring to winter as professed and re- 
quired. According to O. Neugebauer (4.J.P., Ixiii [1942], 
pp. 455-458) the ratios were derived from twelve, nine, eight, 
and six, taken to be the number of days by which spring, 
summer, winter, and autumn respectively exceed a common 
measure (really eleven, nine, seven, and six respectively ac- 
cording to Callippus in the Eudoxt Ars Astronomica, col. 
xxlii=p. 25 [Blass]), so that originally the ratios of these 
increments or deviations were: spring to autumn (not to 
summer) as twelve to six (the octave), to summer as twelve 
to nine (the fourth), and to winter as twelve to eight (the 
fifth). This is rejected by Burkert (Weisheit und Wissen- 
schaft, p. 333, ἢ. 110), who seems to think that the parallel 
passage in Aristides Quintilianus makes it wrong to seek the 
origin of the ratios in any astronomical calculations and that 
the speculation was obviously meant to show in the numbers 
the opposition of summer and winter, though in fact neither 
the ratios nor the numbers in Aristides Quintilianus do this. 
4 Euripides, frag. 990 (Nauck, Trag. Graec. Frag.’, 

p. 679). 
329 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1028) ἐν τῷ διὰ πασῶν at ὧραι μεταβάλλουσιν. ἔνιοι δὲ 
a \ ~ 

γῇ μὲν τὴν' TOO προσλαμβανομένου" χώραν ἀποδι- 
) Vive \ \ ap ee \ \ 
ὄντες σελήνῃ de τὴν ὑπάτην Στίλβωνα δὲ Kat 
1029 Φωσφόρον ἐν diatovois* {παρυπάταις)" καὶ λιχα- 
νοῖς κινοῦντες αὐτὸν τὸν ἥλιον ὡς μέσην συνέχειν 
τὸ διὰ πασῶν ἀξιοῦσιν ἀπέχοντα τῆς μὲν γῆς τὸ 

διὰ πέντε τῆς δὲ τῶν ἀπλανῶν τὸ διὰ τεσσάρων. 

3 3 a ᾽ὔ \ \ “ 7 

82. ᾿Αλλ᾽ οὔτε τούτων τὸ κομψὸν ἅπτεταί τι- 

3 7 a5 2. ἝΞ a / ἌΣ ἊΝ aA 
vos ἀληθείας οὔτ᾽ ἐκεῖνοι παντάπασι τοῦ ἀκριβοῦς 


1 γῇ μὲν ἐν τῇ - (three dots superscript over ἐν and ὃν 
superscript over τῇ -1i1), e, u, ἢν m, r, Escor. 723 γῆν μὲν 
τὴν -B. 

2 Krom λαμβανομένου (f. 226 recto) to the end of the 
essay a new hand in e. 

3 σελήνην -Y. 

4 ἐν rots διατόνοις (διαγόνοις -1} -f, m, r. 

5 «παρυπάταις»Σ -B. Mitiler (1873) after Maurcmmates, 
who wished to substitute it either for λιχανοῖς or for διατόνοις. 


¢ With what follows cf. especially Macerpta Neapolitana 
Q4 (Musici Scriptores Graeci, pp. 418, 14-419, 7 [Jan})= 
Inscriptio Canobi (Ptolemaei Opera ii, p. 154, 1-10 [Hei- 
berg]) but with the better alignment of Halma, Hypothéses et 
Epoques des Planétes de Οὐ. Ptolémée ... (Paris, 1820), pp. 
61-62; also Alexander of Ephesus in Theon Sinyrnaeus, 
pp. 140, 5-141, 4 (Hiller) and Censorinus, De Die Natali 
xiii, 3-5 (pp. 23, 129-24, 6 [Hultsch]) with W. Burkert, 
Philologus, cv (1961), pp. 32-43 and B. L. van der Waerden, 
R.-#. Supplement x (1965), cols. 857, 65-859, 35. 

» The note added to the scale below the hypaté (the top- 
most string that gives the lowest tone: see supra note e on 
Plat. Quaest. 1007 x), as Plutarch himself says in 1029 5 
infra (see page 335, note ὁ). 

¢ For the variation in the oblique cases of Στίλβων as of 
Φαίνων (1029 B infra) see De Facie 925 a and 941 c with my 
note ad loc. (L.C.L. xii, p. 184, note a). 

4 Cf. [Plutarch], De Musica 1134 τ (. . . τὴν διάτονον 
mapuTarny ... τὴν διάτονον λιχανόν) and the note of Kinarson 
and De Lacy ad loc. (L.C.L. xiv, p. 375, n.d). W. Burkert 


330 








GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1028-1029 


it is in the ratio of an octave that the seasons change. 
Some people,* moreover, assigning to earth the 
position of the proslambanomenos ὃ and to the moon 
the hypaté and having Mercury ὁ and Venus move 
in the positions of the diatonic ¢parhypaté) and 
lichanos ὦ maintain that the sun himself as mesé 
holds the octave together,’ being at the remove of a 
fifth from the earth and of a fourth from the sphere 
of the fixed stars.f 

32. But the cleverness of these people is not con- 
cerned with any truth, and those others do not aim 
at accuracy at all.’ To those, however, who think 


(Philologus, ον [1961], p. 33, n. 2) thinks that the illogical 
ev διατόνοις καὶ λιχανοῖς was in Plutarch’s source. The ex- 
pression used for Mercury and Venus may be a reference 
to the fact that the parhypaté and the lichanos are ‘“ moy- 
able ’’ notes: contrast τοὺς ἑστῶτας (1029 B infra) and cf. 
Cleonides, Introductio 6 and Gaudentius, Harmonica Intro- 
ductio 17 (Musici Scriptores Graeci, pp. 189, 20-190, 5 and 
p. 345, 4-12 {[Jan]); Aristides Quintilianus, De Musica i, 6 
(p. 9, 25-26 [Winnington-Ingram]). 

¢ For the sun as midmost of the seven planets—and so the 
paradigm of the musical mesé (Nicomachus, Harmonices 
Man. 3= Musici Scriptores Graeci, Ὁ. 242, 2-7 [Jan])— 
συνάγοντα καὶ συνδέοντα τὰς ef ἑκάτερα αὐτοῦ τριάδας cf. 
Proclus, In Platonis Timaeum iii, p. 62, 7-9 (Diehl); and 
for the mesé itself as σύνδεσμος cf. [Aristotle], Problemata 
919 a 25-26. 

* Cf. Censorinus, De Die Natali xiii, 4-5 (p. 23, 18-20 and 
pp. 23, 27-24, 2 [Hultsch]) and Alexander of Ephesus in 
Theon Smyrnaeus, p. 140, 8 and 15 with Theon’s criticism 
ibid., p. 141, 16-19 (Hiller). 

5 Cf. οὐδ᾽ αὐτοὺς παντάπασιν ἐξακριβοῦντας (1028 c supra), 
which applies a fortiori to the preceding πολλοί who “ carry 
over into this context Pythagorean notions .. . going far 
astray of what is reasonable .. .”’ (1028 s—c). It is to these 
that the ἐκεῖνοι here refers and not, as Hubert supposes, to 
the “ Chaldaeans ”’ of 1028 Ἐ-Ὲ supra. 


331 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


» 4 9 > 9 a ~ a a 
(1029) ἔχονται. οἷς δ᾽ οὖν οὐ δοκεῖ ταῦτα τῆς τοῦ Πλά- 
3 “A /, 3 A a = 
Twvos ἀπηρτῆσθαι διανοίας ἐκεῖνα κομιδῇ φανεῖται 

-- ~ ’ / \ , 

τῶν μουσικῶν λόγων ἔχεσθαι, TO πέντε τετραχόρ- 
» ~ ’ Α / A 
δων᾽ ὄντων" τῶν ὑπάτων" Kal μέσων καὶ συνὴμ- 

’ 

μένων καὶ διεζευγμένων᾽ καὶ ὑπερβολαίων ἐν πέντε 

, / ° a 
διαστήμασι τετάχθαι τοὺς 'πλάνητας, ὧν TO μέν 
> i: 3 ‘ hg >s> ΦᾺ ‘ s ¢€ , 

Β ἐστι τὸ ἀπὸ σελήνης ἐφ᾽ ἥλιον καὶ τοὺς ὁμοδρόμους 
ey 7 , A / td aes: | \ 4 
ἡλίῳ, UTiABwva καὶ Φωσφόρον, ἕτερον TO ἀπὸ τού- 

ee, a a δ , , “Sar ‘ 
των ἐπὶ τὸν “Apeos® [[υρόεντα, τρίτον δὲ τὸ μεταξὺ 

, 6 \ / 22) ρα . Αἴ ι , 
τούτου" καὶ Φαέθοντος, εἶθ᾽ ἑξῆς τὸ ἐπὶ Daivwva, 
καὶ πέμπτον ἤδη τὸ ἀπὸ τούτου πρὸς τὴν ἀπλανῆ 
σφαῖραν: ὥστε τοὺς opilovtas φθόγγους τὰ τετρά- 
χορδα τὸν τῶν πλανωμένων λόγον ἔχειν ἀστέρων. 

1 EK, B, f, m, r, Escor. 72 (three dots over yo), Aldine; 
tetpad....vac. 1... py (@ and x erased) -e; vrerpa... vac. 2 

DO: a MOR a wae’, 

2 ὄντας -Β, 

3 τῶν ὑπάτων -Basil.; τοῦ ὑπατῶν -E (ὑπάτων -Ε)1), B; 
τοῦ ὑπόστων τα, Escor. 72 (with ὧν superscript over od) ; 
τοῦ ὑπόστον -U; τῶν ὑπόστων -f, τη, τ, Aldine. 

‘ , διαζευγμένων -r; διεξαγμένων -e, τι. 

5 B, f, m, r3 aépos -E, e, u, Escor. 72, Aldine. 


8 τούτων -F. 














¢ Of. De Defectu Orac. 430 a; Nicomachus, Harmonices 
Man. 11, 5-6 and Cleonides, Introductio 10 (Musici Scrip- 
tores Graeci, pp. 259, 13-260, 4 and p. 201, 8-13 [Jan]). 

> In De Defectu Orac. 430 a it is not the intervals of the 
planets that are said to be five but their ‘ periods ”’ (ef. 
[Plutarch], De Placitis 892 8= Dow. Graeci, p. 363 A 9-15). 

° So in De Defectu Orac. 430 a (.. . “HAiov καὶ Φωσφόρου 
καὶ Στίλβωνος ὁμοδρομούντων). In [Plato], Epinomis 987 B 4-5 
Mercury is said to be On08popos with the sun and Venus ; 
and ‘‘ Timaeus Locrus ”’ uses διὰ τὸ ὁμοδρομῆν adiw of Venus 
(97 a) just after (96 ©) having called Mercury and Venus 
ἰσόδρομοι ἀελίῳ (ef. [Plutarch], De Placitis 889 c and 892 B= 
Dox. Graeci, p. 346 a 4-6 and p. 363 a 11-13; [Aristotle], 


332 





GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1029 


these notions not remote from Plato's meaning the 
following will appear to be closely connected with 
the musical ratios, that, there being five tetrachords 
—those of the lowest and middle and conjunct and 
disjunct and highest—,? the planets have been 
arranged in five intervals,? of which one is that from 
moon to sun and those that keep pace with the sun, 
Mercury and Venus,¢ second that from these to the 
fiery planet of Mars,? and third that between this 
and Jupiter, and then next that extending to 
Saturn,? and finally fifth that from this to the sphere 
of fixed stars,’ so that the sounds bounding the 
tetrachords correspond to the planets.’ Further- 


De Mundo 399 a 8-9; Theon Smyrnaeus, p. 136, 20-21 
[Hiller]). Plato himself, however, in Timaeus 38 p 2-3 says 
that the revolution of Venus and of Mercury is τάχει icddpo- 
μον ἡλίῳ (cf. 36 D 5: τάχει τρεῖς μὲν ὁμοίως) : cf. ἰσοταχεῖς 
in Philo Jud., De Cherubim 22 (i, p. 175, 11-13 [Cohn]) and 
Philoponus, De Aeternitate Mundi vi, 24 (p. 199, 10-15 
[Rabe]). For the form Στίλβωνα page 330, note c supra. 

4 Cf. Plutarch, frag. ix, 5 (p. 46, 3 [Bernardakis])=frag. 
157, 80 (Sandbach); [Plutarch], De Placitis, 889 p= Doz. 
Graeci, pp. 344 a 20-345 a 1; Theon Smyrnaeus, p. 130, 
24 (Hiller). 

¢ For the form Φαίνωνα see page 330, note ὁ supra. 

t This reduction of the planetary intervals to five involves 
not only the mistake of making the orbits of the sun, Mer- 
cury, and Venus one and the same but also the inconsistency 
of counting the interval from Saturn to the fixed stars while 
at the same time omitting the interval from earth to moon 
(cf. Helmer, De An. Proc., p. 59). 

¢ The five tetrachords, not being all consecutive, are 
bounded by seven different notes (cf. Boethius, De Institu- 
tione Musica iv, xii=pp. 334, 23-335, 6 [Friedlein]) ; but in 
the preceding scheme the five consecutive intervals must be 
bounded by six terms, one of which, since three of the seven 
planets constitute a single boundary, cannot be a planet and 
is in fact the sphere of the fixed stars. 


333 


(1029) 


ap 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


” ἢ \ ee Δ δ. Ὁ 1 \ , 
ETL τοίνυν τοὺς παλαιοὺς ἰσμεν UTratas’ μὲν δύο 
ἬΝ: ΣΌΝ ἐσὺ δα τος «ΕΝ ; 
τρεῖς O€ νῆτας play’ ὃε μέσην καὶ μίαν παραμέσην 

/ a 3 a , ’ , 
τιθεμένους, ware? τοῖς πλάνησιν ἰσαρίθμους εἶναι 
A e a ¢ A ’ὔ ὃ ’ 
τοὺς ἑστῶτας. οἱ δὲ νεώτεροι τὸν προσλαμβανό- 
͵ , ee ed 5» Saas \ \ 
μενον, τόνῳ Stapepovta*® τῆς ὑπάτης, ἐπὶ τὸ βαρὺ 
΄ A \ Ὁ f \ \ an ? 
τάξαντες τὸ μὲν ὅλον σύστημα δὶς διὰ πασῶν ἐ- 
͵ ΄“΄ A ~ \ \ ’ >] 
ποίησαν τῶν δὲ συμφωνιῶν τὴν κατὰ φύσιν οὐκ 
> , , \ y \ 4 ‘4 , 
ἐτήρησαν τάξιν' τὸ γὰρ διὰ πέντε πρότερον γίγνε- 
~ 4 / Ἐπ τ \ A ~ e / 6 
ται τοῦ διὰ τεσσάρων, ἐπὶ τὸ βαρὺ τῇ ὑπάτῃ 
τόνου προσληφθέντος. ὁ δὲ !λάτων δῆλός ἐστιν 
ἐπὶ τὸ ὀξὺ προσλαμβάνων" λέγει γὰρ ἐν τῇ ΙΠολι- 
’ a > \ A ee , $978 
τείᾳ τῶν ὀκτὼ σφαιρῶν ἑκάστην περιφέρειν [εἶτ᾽] 
ἐπ᾿ αὐτῇ Σειρῆναδ βεβηκυῖαν, adew δὲ πάσας ἕνα 
ὑπάτους -Τ. 
νήτεις καὶ μίαν -Ὑ. 
ἐν δὲ -U. 
διαφέροντος -U. ' 
τῆς <émdtwv> ὑπάτης -Ἡ. Weil et Th. Reinach, P?u- 
tarque: De la musique (Paris, 1900), p. Ixix, n. 4. 
6 i, B, f, m, r3 ἀπάτῃ -e, u, Escor. 72, Aldine. 
7 Τὸ (τόνω -E} with ὦ remade to ov), B, e, τι, Escor. 72 ; 
τοῦ τόνου -f, τὰ, r, Aldine. 
8 Deleted by Hubert ; τὴν -Stephanus, 


9. FE, B; σειρῆναι -e, αὶ, Escor. 72, Aldine: σειρῆναν -f, in ; 
σειρῆνας -F. 


1 
2 
3 
4 


5 


« j.e., apart from the proslambanomenos, the seven fixed 
notes that bound the five tetrachords: cf. Boethius, De 
Institutione Musica 1, xiii (pp. 335, 8-337, 15 [Friedlein]) ; 
Cleonides, /utroductio 4 and Gaudentius, //armonica Intro- 
3384: 





GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1029 


more, we know that the ancients reckon two notes 
called hypaté and three nété but one mesé and one 
paramesé, so that the stable notes are equal in 
number with the planets. The moderns, however, 
by placing an additional note, the proslambano- 
menos, lower in the scale than the hypaté,® from 
which it differs by a tone, made the whole scale a 
double octave ὁ but did not preserve the natural 
order of the consonances, for the fifth turns out to be 
prior to the fourth when to the hypaté a tone has 
been added lower in the seale.¢ It is obvious, how- 
ever, that Plato makes the addition to the higher end 
of the scale, for in the Republic he says ¢ that each of 
the eight spheres’ carries around in its revolution a 
Siren standing on it and they all sing emitting a single 


ductio 17 (Musici Scriptores Graeci, p. 185, 16-25 and p. 345, 
1-4 [Jan]). 

δ That is the hypaté of the lowest tetrachord, as would 
be made explicit by the supplement of Weil-Reinach, τῆς 
ζὑπάτων» ὑπάτης : but τῇ ὑπάτῃ τόνου προσληφθέντος at the 
end of the sentence shows that Plutarch wrote simply τῆς 
ὑπάτης here just as Nicomachus wrote τὴν ὑπάτην for τὴν 
ὑπάτων ὑπάτην (cf. Musici Scriptores Graeci, p. 258, 2-3 

an 

¢ Cf. Nicomachus, Harmonices Man. 11, 4 (Musici 
Scriptores Graeci, p. 258, 2-11 (Jan]) and Bocthius, De 
Institutione Musica τ, xx (pp. 211, 21-212, 7 [Friedlein]}). 

@ i.¢e., the scale ought to begin with a tetrachord not in- 
creased to a fifth by the tone of the proslambanomenos, for 
the fourth is “‘ naturally prior’ to the fifth: cf. Nicomachus, 
Harmonices Man. 7, 9, and 12 (Musici Scriptores Graeci, 
p. 249, 2-19; p. 252, 4-15; and p. 262, 7-11 [Jan]) and 
Arithmetica Introductio τι, xxvi, 1 (p. 134, 5-15 [Hoche]) ; 
Theon Smyrnaeus, p. 66, 12-14 (Hiller). 

¢ Republic 617 B 4-7. 

f Plato said not “‘spheres”’ but ἐπὶ δὲ τῶν κύκλων. .. ἐφ᾽ 
ἑκάστου. See supra 1028 a with note e and Plat. Quaest. 
1007 a with note d there. 

335 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1029) τόνον' ἱείσας" ἐκ δὲ πασῶν κεράννυσθαι μίαν ἁρμο- 
νίαν. αὗται δ᾽ ἀνιέμεναι τὰ θεῖα εἴρουσι καὶ 
καταδουσιδ τῆς ἱερᾶς περιόδου" καὶ χορείας" ὀκτά- 
χορδον" ἐμμέλειαν: ὀκτὼ γὰρ ἦσαν καὶ οἵ πρῶτοι 

D τῶν διπλασίων καὶ τριπλασίων ὅροι λόγων, ἕκα- 
τέρᾳ προσαριθμουμένης μερίδι τῆς μονάδος. οἱ δὲ 
πρεσβύτεροι Μούσας παρέδωκαν καὶ ἡμῖν ἐννέα, 


1 ἕνα «ἑκάστην» τόνον ~Hubert. 


2 Ἐς; ἴσας -B; ἐείσας -all other μ88., Aldine. 
8 Stephanus ; εἴρουσαι καὶ κατάδουσαι -MSS. 
4 E, B; προόδου -all other mss., Aldine. 
5 E, B; ywpias re ἃ, Escor. 72, Aldine; χορίαις -f, m, r 
8 χὴν ὀκτάχορδον -f, m, r. 
7 MSS. (μούσαν -u); καὶ Μούσας παρέδωκαν ἡμῖν .-Pohlenz. 


-- 


¢ Each emits one tone (Republic 617 8B 6); but even 
Proclus, who elsewhere states this clearly (In Platonis Rem 
Publicam ii, pp. 236, 29-237, 1 and p. 238, 15 [Kroll}), says 
κινεῖ δὲ τὰς Σειρῆνας ἄδειν μίαν φωνὴν ἱείσας ἕνα τόνον... 
(ibid., i, p. 69, 10-12 [Kroll}). Hubert’s supplement, there- 
fore, ‘would be a case of improving rather than restoring 
what Plutarch wrote. 

> Plutarch must assume that the Siren of the moon emits 
hypaté of the lowest tetrachord and that of Saturn nété of 
the highest so that the additional eighth, that of the fixed 
stars, would be a tone higher in pitch than the latter. Plato 
does not say, however, what tone is emitted by which Siren 
and nothing that he does say would prevent the eighth tone 
from being understood as an addition to the lower end of the 
scale, whether the tone highest in pitch or lowest is as- 
sociated with the moon, for which two opposed theories cf. 
Nicomachus, Harmonices Man. 3 and Excerpta 3 (Musici 
Scriptores Graeci, pp. 241, 18-242, 11 and pp. 271, 18-273, 
24 [Jan]}). 

¢ 4.e. ‘‘ relaxed’ in the musical sense, referring to ΜΙ 
gentle sound of the harmony (of. De Genio Socratis 590 c-p 
.. . τὴν πραότητα τῆς φωνῆς ἐκείνης ἐκ πασῶν ἐῤμοβλ  ΑΥ ΤΑΣ 
and so differentiating the tones of these Sirens from the shrill 
song, Avyup?) ἀοιδή of Homer’s (Odyssey xii, 44 and 183; ο΄. 


336 











GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1029 


tone? and all are blended into a single concord. 
These Sirens free from strain ὁ entwining things 
divine ὁ chant a harmony of eight notes over the 
sacred circuit of the dance,’ for eight was also the 
number of the primary terms of the double and 
triple ratios, the unit being counted along with each 
of the two classes.f And we too have got from our 
elders the tradition that there are nine Muses,9 


Apollonius Rhodius, iv, 892-893 and 914), λιγυρή being 
ὀξεῖα and σύντονος, the opposite of ἀνιεμένη (cf. [Aristotle], 
De Audibilibus 804 a 21-29). Proclus is at pains to distinguish 
these two groups of Sirens and in fact maintains that ac- 
cording to Plato there are three different kinds (Jn Platonis 
Rem Publicam ii, pp. 238, 21-239, 8 [Kroll] and Jn Platonis 
Cratylum, Ὁ. 88, 14-26 [Pasquali]). 

4 Etymologizing Σειρήν, as is shown by Quaest. Conviv. 
745 F(... Σειρῆνας ὀνομάζειν, εἰρούσας τὰ θεῖα καὶ λεγούσας ἐν 
“Αἰιδου. . .), apparently as if from σεῖα (Laconian for θεῖα) 
cipew. Etym. Magnum 710, 19-20 (Gaisford) has παρὰ τὸ 
εἴρω, TO λέγω, εἰρήν: καὶ πλεονασμῷ τοῦ σ, σειρήν. ἢ παρὰ TO 
εἴρω τὸ συμπλέκω, the latter from Herodian Technicus, Reli- 
quiae ii, 1, p. 579, 13-14 (Lenz).. 

¢ Cf. Philo Jud., De Mutatione Nominum 72 (iii, p. 169, 
27-28 [Wendland]) and De Specialibus Legibus ii, 151 (v, 
p. 122, 13-15 [Cohn]); [Plato], Epinomis 982 § 4-6 from 
Plato, Timaeus 40 c 3-4. 

7 For the unit as common to both even numbers and odd 
being counted twice and so giving eight terms (1, 2, 4, 8 
and 1, 3, 9, 27) see supra 1018 r—1019 a with note 6 there, 
but for the same reason being taken only once and so giving 
seven terms (1, 2, 4, 8, 3, 9, 27) see 1027 © supra. With 
of πρῶτοι τῶν... ὅροι λόγων here cf. τῶν ὑποκειμένων ἀριθμῶν 

. . ἐδέησε μείζονας ὅρους λαβεῖν ἐν τοῖς αὐτοῖς λόγοις (1019 B 
supra with note d there). 

9 ** We too...,” for this was not the universal belief: 
cf. Quaest. Conviv. 744 c—745 B (where at the end Plutarch 
identifies the three Fates of Republic 617 c with the three 
Delphian Muses) and 7462; M. Mayer, R.-£. xvi/1 (1933), 
cols. 687, 50-691, 66. 


337 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1029) Tas μὲν ὀκτὼ καθάπερ ὁ Πλάτων περὶ τὰ οὐράνια 
τὴν δ᾽ ἐνάτην τὰ περίγεια κηλεῖν' ἀνακαλουμένην 
καὶ καθιστᾶσαν ἐ ἐκ πλάνης καὶ διαφορᾶς ἀνωμαλίαν 
καὶ ταραχὴν ἐχούσας." 

33. Σκοπεῖτε" δὲ μὴ τὸν μὲν οὐρανὸν ἄγει καὶ 
τὰ οὐράνια ταῖς περὶ αὑτὴν" ἐμμελείαις καὶ κινή- 
σεσιν ἡ ψυχὴ φρονιμωτάτη καὶ δικαιοτάτη γεγο- 
νυῖα, “γέγονε δὲ τοιαύτη τοῖς καθ᾽ ἁρμονίαν λόγοις, 

3 
ὧν εἰκόνες μὲν ὑπάρχουσιν εἰς τὰ σώματα ἐν τοῖς 
E ὁρατοῖς καὶ ὁρωμένοις μέρεσι. τοῦ κόσμου καὶ σώ- 
μασιν ἡ δὲ πρώτη καὶ κυριωτάτη δύναμις ἀοράτως" 
ἐγκέκραται τῇ ψυχῇ καὶ παρέχει σύμφωνον αὐτὴν 


1 καλεῖν -Τ΄ 
e, u, f, m, r, Escor. 72, Aldine; ἐχούσης -E, B. 
i, By ts σκοπεῖται -e, u, f, m, Escor. 79, 
Bernardakis ; αὐτὴν -Μμ858. 5 MSS.3 ἀσώματα -Stephanus. 
8 ἀοράτως -r, f (in margin), m (in margin); ὁρατοὺς -ut 
(ov remade to w) ; ὁρατῶς -all other Mss, 
7 Stephanus ; 3 ἑαυτὴν -MSS.; ἑαυτῇ -Hubert; <adri> 
αὐτὴν -A. E. Taylor (Commentary on Plato’s Timaeus, 
p. 157, n. 1). 


= ὦ t 


* This tacit identification of the Sirens of Republic 617 

B 4-7 with the Muses Ammonius in Quaest. Conviv. 745 F 
_ is made to assert explicitly after Plutarch in his own person 
had denied it (ἐδέα. 745 c). It is later denied by Proclus too 
(In Platonis Rem Publicam ii, p. 237, 16-25 with ii, p. 68, 
5-16 [Kroll]), who ascribes it to of παλαιοί (In Platonis 
Timaeum ii, p. 208, 9-14 and p. 210, 25-28 [Diehl]). It is 
explicit in Macrobius, Jn Somnium Scipionis uy, iii, 1-2 
(=Porphyrii in Platonis Timaeum . . . Fragmenta, pp. 59, 
11-60, 10. [Sodano]) and implicit in Porphyry, Περὶ ἀγαλ- 
μάτων, frag. 8 (J. Bidez, Vie de Porphyre, p. 12*, 14-15) 
= Eusebius, Praep. Evang. iii, 11, 24 (i, p. 139, 19-20 
[Mras]) and Vita Pythagorae 31 (pp. 33, 19-34, 2 [Nauck]) 
and in the citation of Amelius by Joannes Lydus, De 
Mensibus iv, 85 (p. 135, 3-7 [Wiinsch]). The Muses are 
not mentioned in the two interpretations of the Sirens given 


338 








GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1029 


eight of them, just as Plato says, being occupied with 
things celestial? and the ninth with those about the 
earth ὃ to cast a spell upon them recalling them from 
vagrancy and discord and settling their capricious- 
ness and confusion. 

33. Consider, however, whether the heavens and 
the heavenly bodies are not guided by the soul with 
her own harmonious motions ὁ when she has become 
most provident and most just and whether she has 
not become such by reason of the concordant ratios,4 
semblances of which are incorporated in the parts of 
the universe that are visible and seen, that is in 
bodies, but the primary and fundamental property of 
which has been invisibly blended in the soul ὁ and 


by Theon Smyrnaeus, pp. 146, 9-147, 6 (Hiller) or in that 
given by Chalcidius, Platonis Timaeus, p. 167, 1-7 (Wrobel) 
ΞΡ. 148, 6-11 (Waszink). 
’ So Ammonius i in Quaest. Conviv. 746 A (pia δὲ τὸν μεταξὺ 
γῆς καὶ σελήνης τόπον ἐπισκοποῦσα καὶ περιπολοῦσα .. .) ; Cf. 
τε ὑποσελήνιος σφαῖρα in Porphyry, Περὶ ἀγαλμάτων, frag. 8 
πὰ in the last note swpra). Others resolved the difficulty 
of identifying the nine Muses with Plato’s eight Sirens by 
making the ninth the concord produced by the other eight 
(Macrobius, Jn Somnium Scipionis τι, iii, 1-2). 

¢ Cf. Porphyry in Proclus, Jn Platonis Timaeum ii, p. 214, 
11 (=Porphyrii in Platonis Timaeum ... Fragmenta, Ὁ. 60, 
18-19 [Sodano]) and Proclus himself, 262d. ii, p. 268, 7-8 and 
p. 279, 10-12 (Diehl); and Simplicius, De Anima, p. 40, 
37-38. With the reasons given by Plutarch here for rejecting 
the astronomical interpretations considered in chaps. 31-32 
ἀκ ie cf. especially Proclus, ibid. ii, Ρ. 212, 28-31 (Diehl). 

* See Plat. Quaest. 1003 a: ἐπεὶ δὲ ἡ ψυχὴ νοῦ μετέλαβε καὶ 
ἁρμονίας καὶ γενομένη διὰ συμφωνίας ἔμφρων. .. 

“ See 1024 c supra (διαδιδοῦσαν ἐνταῦθα τὰς ἀκ δεν gas): 
cf. Porphyry in Proclus, ln Platonis Timaeum ii, p. 214, 15-16 
and pp. 214, 31-215, 8 (=Porphyrii in Platonis Timaeum 
. . . Fragmenta, Ὁ. 60, 22-23 and p. 61, 13-15 [Sodano}) 
and Proclus himself, ib¢d., p. 295, 2-9 (Diehl). 


339 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


\ θ , 2 an “~ / \ / 
(1029) kat πειθήνιον, ἀεὶ τῷ κρατίστῳ Kat θειοτάτῳ 
“ τ ¢ / 
μέρει τῶν ἄλλων ἁπάντων ὁμονοούντων. παραλα- 
βὼν γὰρ ὁ δημιουργὸς ἀταξίαν' καὶ πλημμέλειαν 
ἐν ταῖς κινήσεσι τῆς ἀναρμόστου καὶ ἀνοήτου ψυ- 
χῆς διαφερομένης πρὸς ἑαυτὴν τὰ μὲν διώρισε καὶ 
διέστησε τὰ δὲ συνήγαγε πρὸς ἄλληλα καὶ συν- 
ἔταξεν ἁ ἁρμονίαις καὶ ἀριθμοῖς χρησάμενος, οἷς καὶ 
τὰ κωφότατα" σώματα, λίθοι καὶ ξύλα καὶ φλοιοὶ 
φυτῶν καὶ θηρίων ὀστᾶ" καὶ πυτίαι, συγκεραν- 
Ε νύμενα καὶ συναρμοττόμενα θαυμαστὰς μὲν ἀγαλ- 
μάτων ὄψεις θαυμαστὰς δὲ παρέχει φαρμάκων καὶ 
ὀργάνων δυνάμεις. ἡἧ καὶ Ζήνων ὁ Κιτιεὺς ἐπὶ 
θέαν αὐλητῶν παρεκάλει τὰ μειράκια καταμανθά- 
νειν οἵαν" κέρατα καὶ ξύλα καὶ κάλαμοι καὶ ὀστᾶ,ἷ 
λόγου μετέχοντα καὶ συμφωνίας, φωνὴν ἀφίησι. 
τὸ μὲν γὰρ ἀριθμῷ πάντα ἐπεοικέναι" κατὰ τὴν 
ἢ υϑαγορικὴν ἀπόφανσιν"" λόγου δεῖται: τὸ δὲ πᾶσιν, 
1080 οἷς" ἐκ διαφορᾶς καὶ ἀνομοιότητος ἐγγέγονε κοι- 
νωνία τις πρὸς ἄλληλα καὶ συμφωνία, ταύτης 
αἰτίαν εἶναι μετριότητα καὶ τάξιν, ἀριθμοῦ καὶ 
1 Xylander; κατ᾽ ἀταξίαν -E, B, 6, τὶ ; κατ᾽ ἀξίαν (ἀξίαν 
corrected to ἀταξίαν in margin -f1, τα) -f, m, r, Escor. 72, 
Aldine. 
2 Wyttenbach ; κουφότατα -Μ88. 
3 φοιοὶ -f, m, r. 
4 Emperius (Op. Phalol., p. 340); εἰσὶ (εἰσὶν -e, ἃ) -Mss. 
> πιτύαι -F, B, ul ° 
§ οἷα -B. 
7 gaa (?}-e€3 ὅσα -u, Aldine. 
8 τὸ -E, B; τῷ -all other mss., Aldine. 
9 ἐπιοικέναι -e, u2, Escor. 72. 
10 EK, Β, f, m3; ἀπόφασιν -e, Ὁ, r, Escor. 72, Aldine. 
11 Xylander ; πᾶσι θεοῖς -Mss. 


« Cf. De Genio Socratis 592 B-c. 
340 











GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1029-1030 


renders her concordant and docile,“ all her other 
parts always agreeing with the part that is best and 
most divine.? For the artificer, having taken over ¢ 
a jangling disorder in the motions of the discordant 
and stupid soul which was at odds with herself,4 
distinguished and separated some parts and brought 
others together with one another and organized 
them, using concords and numbers ὁ by which when 
blended and fitted together even the most senseless 
bodies, stones and logs and the bark of plants and 
bones and beestings of animals, provide statuary of 
wonderful appearance and medicines and _ instru- 
ments of wonderful potency. Wherefore it was that 
Zeno of Citium 7 summoned the lads to a performance 
of pipers to observe what a sound is produced by bits 
of horn and wood and reed and bone when they par- 
take of ratio and consonance. For, while it requires 
reasoned argument to maintain with the Pythagorean 
assertion that all things are like unto number,’ the 
fact that for all things in which out of difference and 
dissimilitude there has come to be some union and 
consonance with one another the cause is regularity 
and order consequent upon their participation in 


>’ Cf. Plato, Republic 442 c 10-Ὁ 1 and 432 a 6-9. 

¢ See note f on 1014 ὁ supra. 

@ See supra 1014 8 (page 183, note c) and 1016 c with note f 
and the references there. 

¢ See supra page 175 note ¢ and 1015 & with note i. 

7 Cf. De Virtute Morali 443 a=S.V.F. i, frag. 299. 

¢ Cf. Sextus, Adv. Math. iv, 2 and vii, 94 and 109; 
Theon Smyrnaeus, p. 99, 16 (Hiller); Themistius, De Anz- 
ma, Ὁ. 11, 27 (Xenocrates, frag. 39 [Heinze]); A. Nauck, 
Tamblichi De Vita Pythagorica Liber, pp. 234-235, to 
which add Anatolius in [Hero Alexandrinus], Def. 138, 9 
(iv, p. 166, 16-18 [Heiberg]); Burkert, Weisheit und Wis- 
senschaft, pp. 64-65. 

341 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


ἔξ a 
(1030) ἁρμονίας μετασχοῦσιν, οὐδὲ τοὺς ποιητὰς λέληθεν 
\ \ ~ lo 
ἄρθμια μὲν τὰ φίλα καὶ προσηνῆ καλοῦντας avap- 
atous’ δὲ τοὺς ἐχθροὺς καὶ τοὺς πολεμίους," ὡς 
ἀναρμοστίαν τὴν διαφορὰν οὖσαν. ὁ δὲ τῷ Ilw- 
δάρῳ ποιήσας τὸ ἐπικήδειον 
» S ? SUPy [7 \ U > A 
ἄρμενος ἦν ξείνοισιν ἀνὴρ ὅδε καὶ φίλος ἀστοῖς 
᾽ , avs s A > yo" , e 
εὐαρμοστίαν δῆλός ἐστι THY ἀρετὴν" ἡγούμενος, ὥς 
που καὶ αὐτὸς ὁ [Πίνδαρος τοῦ θεοῦ φησιν ἐπα- 
a 4 ‘ the Re ee , Sagi δι , 
κοῦσαι" μουσικὰν ὀρθὰν" ἐπιδεικνυμένου" tov Καδ- 
[ἢ ᾽ὔ 7 ’ὔ ’ 
μον. οἵ τε πάλαι θεολόγοι, πρεσβύτατοι φιλοσόφων 
Β ὄντες, ὄργανα μουσικὰ θεῶν ἐνεχείριζον ἀγάλμα- 
σιν, οὐχ ὡς λύραν που <Kpovovary’ καὶ αὐλοῦσιν 
ἀλλ᾽" οὐδὲν ἔργον οἰόμενοι θεῶν οἷον ἁρμονίαν 


a 

1 Xylander ; ἀναρείους -K, e, u, Escor. 72: ἐναρείους -b ; 
ἀνάρθμια -f, m3; ἀνάρμιθμια τῇ. 

2 τὰ ἐχθρὰ καὶ τὰ πολέμια -f, Mm, Ὑ΄ 

3 ἁρμονίαν -Τ. 

4 B. Miiller (1873); ἐπακούοντος -Μ88. : ἐπακούοντα J. G. 
Schneider ; ἐπακούειν -Wyttenbach. 

5 μουσικὰν ὀρθὰν -Heyne (Pindari Carmina iii, pars i 
[Géttingen, 1798], pp. 51-52); οὐυκανορέαν -E 3 οὐκανορέαν 
(οὐκ dvopéav -u, f, m, r) -all other ass. 

6 Heyne (loc. cit.) : ἐπιδεικνύμενοι -E, B, e, u, Escor. 72 ; 
ἐπιδεικνύμενος -f, m, r, Aldine. 

ἕ «κρούουσι» -supplied by Mauroinmates ; ποὺ - - - vac. 

.. καὶ -E, B; που καὶ (without lacuna) -all other wuss. ἷ 
Aldine : ; λυρίζουσιν καὶ -Wyttenbach. 

8 αὐλὸν ow... Vac. 9 -f, τὰ : vac. 4-r... ἀλλὰ -f, τὰ, τ: 
αὐλὸν ἀλλὰ -Aldine. 


a a i - τ. 


Cf. Stobaeus, Hcl. i, Prooem., 2 (p. 16, 1-13 [Wachs- 
muth]) and Syrianus, Metaph., pp. 103, 29-104, 2. 

> Anth. Pal. vii, 35; cf. A. S. F. Gow and D. L. Page, The 
Greek Anthology : Hellenistic Epigrams ii(Cambridge, 1965), 
p. 395. 


342 











GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1030 


number and concord, this has not gone unnoticed 
even by the poets who call friendly and agreeable 
things befitting and enemies and foes unbefitting on 
the assumption that dissension is unfittingness.¢ He 
who composed the elegy for Pindar 


This was a man who was fitted for guests and friendly to 
townsmen ὃ 


is clearly of the belief that virtue is fittingness, as 
Pindar too says somewhere himself that Cadmus 
hearkened to the god displaying music fit.¢ The 
theologians of ancient times, who were the oldest of 
philosophers,? put musical instruments into the hands 
of the statues of the gods, with the thought, I pre- 
sume, not that they <do play) the lyre and the pipe 
but that no work is so like that of gods as concord 


ὁ Pindar, frag. 32 (Bergk, Schroeder, Snell) =22 (‘Turyn) 
=13 (Bowra); cf. De Pythiae Oraculis 397 a and Aelius 
Aristides, ii, p. 296, 4-5 (Jebb)=ii, p. 383 (Dindorf). The 
quotation is relevant to the present context only if Plutarch 
identified the ὀρθ- of ὀρθάν with the ἀρθ- of ἄρθμιον, which 
he could the more easily do since in Aeolic and his own 
Boeotian op and po often correspond to the ap and pa of 
common Greek (cf. R. Meister, Die griechischen Dialekte 
... i [Géttingen, 1882], p. 34, n. 2; pp. 48-49; p. 216 and 
I’. Bechtel, Die griechischen Dialekte i [Berlin, 1921], p. 25; 
p. 147; pp. 242-243); and I have therefore translated 
ὀρθάν by “ fit’? (ef. English “ fit”"=‘‘ a strain of music,” 
cognate with “ fit ’=** juncture ’’). 

4 Cf. De Iside 360 pv, where Plato, Pythagoras, Xenocrates, 
and Chrysippus are said to have followed τοῖς πάλαι θεολόγοις 
for their notion of δαίμονες, and 369 B, where 4 παμπάλαιος 
δόξα is said to have come down to poets and philosophers 
ex θεολόγων καὶ νομοθετῶν : in De Defectu Orac. 436 dD oi 
σφόδρα παλαιοὶ θεολόγοι Kai ποιηταί are contrasted to of νεώτεροι 
... καὶ φυσικοὶ προσαγορευόμενοι, and to the former is ascribed 
a line of Orpheus, frag. B 6 (D.-K.), for which see De Comm. 
Not. 1074 κε infra with note a there. 


343 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1030) εἶναι καὶ συμφωνίαν. ὥσπερ οὖν ὁ τοὺς ἐπιτρίτους 
καὶ ἡμιολίους καὶ διπλασίους λόγους ζητῶν ἐ ἐν τῷ 
ζυγῷ τῆς λύρας καὶ τῇ χελώνῃ καὶ τοῖς κολλάβοις 
γελοῖός ἐστι (δεῖ μὲν γὰρ ἀμέλει καὶ ταῦτα συμ- 
μέτρως γεγονέναι πρὸς ἄλληλα μήκεσι καὶ πάχεσι 
τὴν δὲ ἁρμονίαν ἐκείνην ἐπὶ τῶν φθόγγων θεωρεῖν) 
οὕτως εἰκὸς μέν ἐστι καὶ τὰ σώματα τῶν ἀστέρων 
καὶ τὰ διαστήματα τῶν κύκλων καὶ τὰ τάχη τῶν 

ἢ περιφορῶν ὥσπερ ὄργανα ἐν τεταγμένοις (λόγοις )* 
ἔχειν ἐμμέτρως πρὸς ἄλληλα καὶ πρὸς τὸ ὅλον, εἰ 
καὶ τὸ ποσὸν ἡμᾶς τοῦ μέτρου" διαπέφευγε, τῶν 
μέντοι λόγων ἐκείνων οἷς ὁ δημιουργὸς ἐχρήσατο 
καὶ τῶν ἀριθμῶν ἔργον ἡγεῖσθαι τὴν αὐτῆς τῆς 
ψυχῆς ἐμμέλειαν" καὶ ἁρμονίαν πρὸς αὑτήν," ὑφ᾽ 
ἧς" καὶ τὸν οὐρανὸν ἐγγενομένη μυρίων ἀγαθῶν ἐμ- 
TET ANKE καὶ τὰ περὶ γῆν ὥραις καὶ μεταβολαῖς 
μέτρον ἐχούσαις ἄριστα καὶ κάλλιστα" πρός τε 
γένεσιν καὶ σωτηρίαν τῶν γιγνομένων διακεκό- 
σμήκεν. 

1 <\dyous> -added by Wyttenbach. 
af in, Ps peri wall other Mss. 
3 ἐπιμέλειαν -f1, m1, r, Aldine. 
* E, B, Τρ τὴ αὐτὴν -e, U; +. E'scor. 72, Aldine. 


5 FE, Bs; ἐφ᾽ ols -all other MSS., Alditie: 
5 μάλιστα -U. 





α Cf. Cornutus, xiv and xxxii (p. 17, 11-16 and pp. 67, 
17-68, 5 [Lang]) and Sallustius, De Diis et Mundo vi (p. 12, 
8-12 [Nock]). Other such symbolic interpretations of the 
statues of gods and their attributes are given by Plutarch 
in De Iside 381 v-r, De Pythiae Oraculis 400 c and 402 a-s, 
An Seni Respublica Gerenda Sit 797 F; cf. Porphyry, 


344: 








GENERATION OF THE SOUL, 1030 


and consonance. Just as one is ridiculous, then, 
who looks for the sesquitertian and sesquialteran and 
duple ratios in the yoke and the shell and the pegs of 
the lyre (for, while of course these too must have 
been made proportionate to one another in length 
and thickness, yet it is in the sounds that that 
concord is to be observed), so is it reasonable to 
believe that, while the bodies of the stars and the 
intervals of the circles and the velocities of the 
revolutions are like instruments commensurate in 
fixed <ratios) with one another and with the whole 
though the quantity of the measurement has eluded 
us,? nevertheless the product of those ratios and 
numbers used by the artificer® is the soul’s own 
harmony and concord with herself,¢ whereby she has 
filled the heaven, into which she has come, with 
countless goods and has arrayed the terrestrial 
regions with seasons and measured changes in the 
best and fairest way for the generation and preserva- 
tion of things that come to be. 


Περὶ ἀγαλμάτων, frags. 3, 7, and 8 (J. Bidez, Vie de Porphyre, 
pp. G*, 4-1*, 4; p. 9*, 10-21; p.,12*, 5-11; and_p. 17*, 
10-18) and Macrobius, Sat. 1, xvii, 13 and xix, 2 and 8 
with R. Pfeiffer, Journal of the Warburg and Courtauld 
Institutes, XV (1952), pp. 20-32 on Callimachus, frag. 114 
(Pfeiffer). 

>’ So much and only so much, then, is conceded to those 
referred to in 1028 a-B supra, καίτοι τινὲς μὲν ἐν τοῖς τάχεσι 

. τινὲς δὲ μᾶλλον ἐν τοῖς ἀποστήμασιν ἔνιοι δ᾽ ἐν τοῖς μεγέ- 
σεσε.... 

¢ See page 341, note e and the references there. 

@ See 1028 a supra: ... ὡς μάλιστα δὴ τῇ συστάσει τῆς 
ψυχῆς τοῦ λόγου τούτου προσήκοντος. 


345 


κῷ 





5 δε 7 cop tnay 
py a a ἐπ « i } ᾿ 
ao ‘- Baie ἘΣ Ἰ ἶ bf 
Cee τς ΨΨ ἢ εὐ, ΘΑ ΝΣ ρον 
ιυ a } i. sie ἌΡ 
i 





‘ δ 5 . 
ὶ 7 ys a. ἢ tat be 
, B25)" t/t ae ee 0} 7 ie ΔΑ | af Ame 
- i a 4 εὐὐὔὐ ¢ uw? O08 et LA Γ > ds δὰ aly μεν 
Ags ἐν pe. ΕΙΣ ΕΟ ee Pee Ler IDEs: 
, " eee on γα. ee tte oe 3 νὰ tp 
¥ ae, ee a md ὙΦ ‘wry =) ᾿ ΤΑ͂Σ ὸ 
ν με » ᾿ e Ji ΓΙ." Ἴ 
roi Sy Sie ΚΗ ΒΙΌΣ 
ὦ Amd lie Sth ὙΠ ͵ a rd bi ‘> 
4 2 4 , 
κέ er τς pede δ alee 
ὖ > ωξ t {3 ἢ “Ὁ YER ΠΣ, 4 
ΠΠΛΑΦΧῪ Ἱ i “ει: ἢ 1 γ: 
“᾽ a " ἄν , 
COG ET. iis ἈΓΠΓ ΤΟΘΟΣΗ 
I f Ε Γ᾿ 
= “y ™) swe ΠΝ, ait are sve 
> ΔΝ AL “Se \ ere me fy 
ΥγῪ ΑΒ ὁ ᾿ “Ὁ yw OARS ἃ 
; hoe we ξ 
iat - , 
as 


_ 
‘oh g 
i 





Si) OF 5 


ae ee 
ν᾽ τ ‘ 


Vd 
» 
< 
= 


r * ΄ 
δ hea « 
a4 ' ὟΥ s a Fike a 
ΟΝ 7 4 
. a ¢ 
A vital 
4 “-- τὰ ΑΝ 
ἂν 
οἱ 
Ἵ ἐν Τὺ δὺ 
Ἢ ‘hoy Aad 1b if ces) Ὁ} 
> J 
4 a ‘ J 
¥ r ie. τὶ " 
*i Meda s ἴ Va wad 4 
᾿ = a Owe © 
} . : te SCYA ΤΟΥ 
ἧς 
᾿ Ν᾿ 
' 
i γ 
es A 
= 
ς , ν 
' 
a 
j 


; 
Ἢ 
Π v4 
eae 4 ia “ ΌΣ 
Ν 4 


wie: 







‘ed 
1 1 
οἱ ~~ 


Γ 


cy 








EPITOME OF THE 
REALISE, ΟΝ LAE 
GENERATION OF THE 

SOUL IN THE TIMAEUS” 


(COMPENDIUM LIBRI DE ANIMAE 
PROCREATIONE IN TIMAEO) 


INTRODUCTION 


Tus Epitome or ‘‘ Compendium,” which is No. 42 in 
the Planudean corpus, is not listed in the Catalogue 
of Lamprias. It is rather an excerpt than an epitome 
or compendium in the proper sense, for it is merely a 
copy of chaps. 22-25 (1023 B—1025 B) of the treatise 
with two short paragraphs by way of introduction. 
In these the “ epitomizer ”’ refers to the author of 
the treatise in the third person, though not by name, 
and in summarizing his doctrine ineptly ascribes to 
him a theory of evil that is vehemently rejected in the 
treatise. The excerpt itself shows in several places 
that the “ epitomizer”’ did not clearly understand 
what he was transcribing ; and, though he made one 
intelligent substitution in his text, he also introduced 
a supplement that reveals his misunderstanding of a 
Greek verbal form. 7 

It is practically certain that the ms. of the treatise 
from which the excerpt was taken was not one from 
which any of the extant mss. of the treatise was 
copied, for in five cases words absent from all the 
latter are present in all mss. of the Epitome. The 
text here printed is based upon a, A, f, y, Εἰ, B, and 


@ 1031 c (ἕκαστα), 1031 ἢ (πάλιν), 1031 E (καὶ), 1032 ἢ 
(πλανήτων), 1032 £ (τὴν). See besides these the correct forms 
in all the mss. of the Epitome: ἀεικίνητος (1031 a), ἄκρα τὸ 
(1032 £), τοῦ ταὐτοῦ (1032 F). 


348 








EPITOME OF GEN. OF SOUL 


n, all of which have been collated from photostats. 
Their readings are fully reported in the apparatus ; 
and so are those of Laurent. Conv. Soppr. 180, 
which was collated as a sample of the other mss. 
containing the Epitome (cf. Hubert-Drexler, Morala 
vi/1, pp. xviI-xvi1). For the few readings cited of 
Vat. Reg. 80 I have depended upon the Variae 
Lectiones of Cruser-Xylander and the reports of 
Hubert-Drexler and upon the latter for those of 
Marc. Append. IV, 1 and Urb. 100(t). There are 
few decisive indications in this work of the relation 
among the mss. collated ; but in several cases B and 
n are in agreement against all the others, and it is 
quite clear that the scribe of B did not copy the 
Epitome from E.4 


6 See 1030 κε (ἀναλογίας καὶ ; ἀναλογικὰς -B, n), 1031 a 
(περιλαμβάνων ; παραλαμβάνων -B, n), 1031 E (νοερὸν ἡ φύσις ; 
νοερὸν ὥσπερ ἡ φύσις -B, ἢ), 1032 a (πως omitted by B,n). In 
all these cases the Aldine is in disagreement with B and n. 


849 


10390 Ὁ 


Ὁ 


ENMITOMH TOY ΠΕΡῚ ΤῊΣ EN ΤΩΙ 
ΤΙΜΑΙΩΙ ΨΥΧΟΓΟΝΙΑΣ 


ς λ ~ > “~ ἣν / / > 
O περὶ τῆς ἐν τῷ Τιμαίῳ ψυχογονίας ém- 
’ ἣν “ 7 \ A 

γεγραμμένος λόγος ὅσα ]]λάτωνι καὶ τοῖς Π]λατω- 
νικοῖς πεφιλοτίμηται ἀπαγγέλλει εἰσάγει δὲ καὶ 
γεωμετρικάς τινας ἀναλογίας καὶ ὁμοιότητας" πρὸς 
τὴν τῆς ψυχῆς, ὡς οἴεται, θεωρίαν συντεινούσας 
αὐτῷ καὶ δὴ καὶ μουσικὰ καὶ ἀριθμητικὰ θεωρή- 
ματα. 

2, Λέγει δὲ τὴν ὕλην ᾿διαμορφωθῆναι ὑπὸ τῆς 
ψυχῆς καὶ δίδωσι μὲν τῷ παντὶ ψυχὴν δίδωσι δὲ 
καὶ ἑκάστῳ ζῴῳ τὴν διοικοῦσαν αὐτό," καὶ πῇ μὲν 
ἀγένητον" εἰσάγει ταύτην πῇ δὲ γενέσει δουλεύου- 

37 A 4 Ὁ \ e A “- ’ὔ \ ~ 
σαν ἀΐδιον δὲ τὴν ὕλην καὶ ὑπὸ τοῦ θείου διὰ τῆς 
ψυχῆς μορφωθῆναι καὶ τὴν κακίαν δὲ βλάστημα 
τῆς ὕλης γεγονέναι, ἵνα μή, φησί, τὸ θεῖον αἴτιον 


F τῶν κακῶν νομισθείη. 


Ὅτι οἱ περὶ τὸν ἸΪοσειδώνιον οὐ μακρὰν τῆς 


1 τοῦ περὶ -omitted by β. 
" ἀναλογικὰς ὁμοιότητας -L, 1). 
3 αὐτῷ -γ, Laurent. C. S. 180. 
4 a; ἀγέννητον -all other mss., Aldine. 


¢ The epitomizer passes without notice from the treatise 
to its author. 

> See supra 1016 ὁ and 1017 a-z. 

¢ See supra 1014 Β and in the final chapter 1029 p-» and 
1030 c, with which οὐ Plat. Quaest. 1003 a. 


350 


——— αφρὸν 











EPITOME OF THE TREATISE, 
“ON THE GENERATION OF THE 
SOUL IN THE TIMAEUS” 


1. THE treatise entitled On the Generation of the Soul 
in the Timaeus reports what all the contentions of 
Plato and the Platonists have been and also intro- 
duces certain geometrical proportions and similarities 
pertaining, as he thinks,“ to his theory of the soul 
and particularly musical and arithmetical specula- 
tions. 

2. He asserts, moreover, that matter was shaped 
by soul and ascribes a soul to the universe but 
ascribes to each living being also the one that 
manages it; and he represents this as being in one 
way ungenerated and in another subject to genera- 
tion ὃ but matter as everlasting and given shape by 
the divinity through the agency of the soul® and evil 
as being in origin an excrescence of matter,’ in 
order, he says, that the divinity might not be thought 
responsible for evil things. 

8. He says that Posidonius and his followers ὁ did 


¢ As B. Miller observed (Hermes, iv [1870], p. 396, n. 1) 
this is the very opposite to Plutarch’s contention in the 
treatise (see 1015 c-E supra). 

¢ =F 14] Ὁ (Edelstein-Kidd). Save for the differences in- 
dicated in the notes the rest of the Epitome is an exact copy 
of De An. Proc. in Timaeo 1023 »n —1025 B supra. 


351 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1030) ὕλης ἀπέστησαν τὴν ψυχὴν' ἀλλὰ δεξάμενοι τὴν 
τῶν περάτων οὐσίαν περὶ τὰ σώματα λέγεσθαι 
μεριστὴν καὶ ταῦτα τῷ νοητῷ μίξαντες ἀπεφή- 
ναντο τὴν ψυχὴν ἰδέαν εἶναι τοῦ πάντῃ διαστατοῦ 

1031 κατ᾽ ἀριθμὸν συνεστῶσαν ἁρμονίαν περιέχοντα: τά 
τε γὰρ μαθηματικὰ τῶν πρώτων νοητῶν μεταξὺ 
καὶ τῶν αἰσθητῶν τετάχθαι, τῆς τε ψυχῆς, τῷ 
νοητῷ" τὸ ἀΐδιον καὶ τῷ αἰσθητικῷ" τὸ παθητικὸν 
ἐχούσης, προσῆκον ἐν μέσῳ τὴν οὐσίαν ὑπάρχειν. 
ἔλαθε γὰρ καὶ τούτους ὁ θεὸς τοῖς τῶν σωμάτων 
πέρασιν ὕστερον, ἀ ἀπειργασμένης ἤδη τῆς ψυχῆς, 
χρώμενος ἐπὶ τὴν τῆς ὕλης διαμόρφωσιν,. τὸ σκεδα- 
στὸν αὐτῆς καὶ ἀσύνδετον ὁρίζων καὶ περιλαμ- 
βάνων" ταῖς ἐκ τῶν τριγώνων συναρμοττομένων 
ἐπιφανείαις. ἀτοπώτερον δὲ τὸ τὴν ψυχὴν ἰδέαν 
ποιεῖν" ἡ μὲν γὰρ ἀεικίνητος ἡ δ᾽ ἀκίνητος, καὶ ἡ 
μὲν ἀμιγὴς πρὸς τὸ αἰσθητὸν ἡ δὲ τῷ σώματι συν- 

Β ειργμένη ἢ πρὸς δὲ τούτοις ὃ θεὸς τῆς μὲν ἰδέας 
ὡς παραδείγματος γέγονε μιμητὴς τῆς δὲ ψυχῆς 
ὥσπερ ἀποτελέσματος δημιουργός. ὅτι δ᾽ οὐδ᾽ 


1 85. 2 τὴν ψυχὴν -omitted 1028 B supra. 
2 μαθητικὰ -a, A (with μα Superscript over yr), Aldine. 
$ MSS. ; τῶν νοητῶν -1023 B supra. 
4 Mss. ; τῶν αἰσθητῶν -1023 B-c supra (E, B; τῶν αἰσθη- 
τικῶν -4}} other mss.). 
5 παραλαμβάνων -B, n. 
6 διὰ -Laurent. C. S. 180. 


7 συνειργομένη -B, n, Laurent. C. 5. 180; συνηργμένη - Vat. 
Reg. 80. 


α The epitomizer misunderstood the second aorist ἀπέ- 
στησαν (1025. B supra) and, supposing it to be transitive, added 
the object, τὴν ψυχήν, that he thought was to be “ supplied.” 
The Bienak was correctly translated by Turnebus and 
Amyot; but Xylander misunderstood it just as the epito- 
mizer had done, and his mistake has been repeated by 


352 











EPITOME OF GEN. OF SOUL, 1030-1031 


not remove the soul far from matter but, having 
taken divisible in the case of bodies to mean the 
being of the limits and having mixed these with the 
intelligible, they declared the soul to be the idea of 
what is everyway extended, herself constituted 
according to number that embraces concord, for 
(they said) the mathematicals have been ranked 
between the primary intelligibles and the per- 
ceptibles and it is an appropriate thing for the soul 
likewise, possessing as she does everlastingness with 
the intelligible and passivity with the perceptive,® to 
have her being in the middle. In fact these people 
too failed to notice that only later, after the soul has 
already been produced, does god use the limits of the 
bodies for the shaping of matter by bounding and 
circumscribing its dispersiveness and incoherence 
with the surfaces made of the triangles fitted to- 
gether. What is more absurd, however, is to make 
the soul an idea, for the former is perpetually in 
motion but the latter is immobile and the latter 
cannot mix with the perceptible but the former has 
been coupled with body ; and, besides, god’s relation 
to the idea is that of imitator to pattern but his 
relation to the soul is that of artificer to finished 
product. As to number, however, it has been stated 


Helmer (De An. Proc., p. 16, n. 21), Thévenaz (L’ Ame du 
Monde, p. 26), Merlan (Platonism to Neoplatonism, p. 35), 
and Marie Laffranque (Poseidonios d’ Apamée [Paris, 1964], 
p. 431). 

> τῷ νοητῷ . . - τῷ αἰσθητικῷ is a mistake whether of the 
epitomizer’s own or of his original for τῶν νοητῶν. . . τῶν 
αἰσθητῶν (1023 B supra, where, however, all mss. except E 
oak have αἰσθητικῶν). It is uncertain what the epitomizer 
thought the text as he wrote it could mean—if indeed he 
thought about it at all. 


353 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


3 { ξ / 4 tn° Sf f a A 
(1031) ἀριθμὸν ὁ Πλάτων τὴν οὐσίαν τίθεται τῆς ψυχῆς 
ϑ \ , | taller ως. lo / 
ἀλλὰ ταττομένην ὑπ᾽ ἀριθμοῦ, προείρηται. 
\ 4. 9 , , 1 Fe ob ‘ 
4. Ipos δ᾽ ἀμφοτέροις τούτοις᾽ κοινόν ἐστι τὸ 
μήτε τοῖς πέρασι μήτε τοῖς ἀριθμοῖς μηδὲν ἴχνος 
> 4 > , “a 4 e \ > Ἁ ¢ 
ἐνυπάρχειν ἐκείνης τῆς δυνάμεως ἡ TO αἰσθητὸν ἡ 
ψυχὴ πέφυκε κρίνειν. νοῦν μὲν γὰρ αὐτῇ καὶ 
νοητὸν" ἡ τῆς νοητῆς μέθεξις ἀρχῆς ἐμπεποίηκε" 
, A \ , A A A \ 4 
δόξας δὲ καὶ πίστεις Kal TO φανταστικὸν καὶ TO 
tere § A \ \ A , ΔΊΑ 
παθητικὸν" ὑπὸ τῶν περὶ τὸ σῶμα ποιοτήτων [ὃ] 
> ” > ΄ OA a 5 S9Rmes 
οὐκ ἄν τις ἐκ μονάδων οὐδὲ γραμμῶν" οὐδ᾽ ἐπι- 
~ ς “κι / 9 , ‘\ \ 3 
C φανειῶν ἁπλῶς νοήσειεν ἐγγινόμενον. καὶ μὴν οὐ 
μόνον at τῶν θνητῶν ψυχαὶ γνωστικὴν τοῦ ai- 
Pare, ” 9 \ ΝΣ a , 6 
σθητοῦ δύναμιν ἔχουσιν, ἀλλὰ καὶ THY τοῦ κύκλου 
φησὶν ἀνακυκλουμένην αὐτὴν πρὸς ἑαυτήν, ὅταν 
ΕΝ) \ ” / 7 9 7 \ 
οὐσίαν σκεδαστὴν ἔχοντός Tivos’ ἐφάπτηται Kal 
“ ἜΧΕ: λ 4 8 , 5 ‘ , 9 ¢ 
ὅταν ἀμέριστον, λέγῃ" κινουμένην διὰ πάσης" éav- 


11 244 s νι «Ὁ 12 Ἃ e 
TAUVUTOV 7) και OTOU αν ETEPOV, 


A ef * 10 
TNS, OTW ἂν TL 
MSS. 3; ἀμφοτέρους τούτους -1023 D supra. 

mss. here and 1023 p supra; see the note there on καὶ 
«τὸ» νοητὸν. 

3 παθητὸν -a, B, n. 

4 [6] -omitted by t (Urb. 100) and deleted by Diibner ; 
see 1023 Ὁ supra: ποιοτήτων, τοῦτ᾽. 

5 οὐδ᾽ ἐκ γραμμῶν -B. 

§ τοῦ κόσμου -Leonicus from 1023 p supra. 

7 χινὰ -y. 

8 λέγη -MSS. (y Over erasure in a); λέγει -Aldine; λέγειν 
-Diibner from 1023 © supra (where EK, B, ἢ, m, r also have 
λέγῃ). 

9 δὲ ἁπάσης -Laurent. C. S. 180}. 


354 


1 
2 








EPITOME OF GEN. OF SOUL, 1031 


above ὁ that Plato regards the substance of soul not 
as number either but as being ordered by number. 
4, Besides both of these, moreover, there is 
equally ὃ the argument that neither in limits nor in 
numbers is there any trace of that faculty with which 
the soul naturally forms judgments of what is 
perceptible. Intelligence and intelligibility have 
been produced in her by participation in the in- 
telligible principle ; but opinions and beliefs, that is 
to say what is imaginative and impressionable by the 
qualities in body, one could not conceive [. . .] as 
arising in her simply from units or from lines or 
surfaces. Now, not only do the souls of mortal 
beings have a faculty that is cognizant of the per- 
ceptible ; but he says ὁ that the soul of the circle 4 
also as she is revolving upon herself, whenever she 
touches anything that has being either dispersed or 
indivisible, is moved throughout herself and states ¢ 
of anything’s being the same and different with 


* Thoughtlessly copied from 1023 pn, for neither the pas- 
sage to which it refers (1013 c-p) nor its content has been 
mentioned in this “‘ epitome.” 

ὃ Plutarch’s κοινόν was made meaningless when the epito- 
mizer mistook ἀμφοτέρους τούτους for ἀμφοτέροις τούτοις ἣν τῇ 
1023 p supra: “. .. against both of these in common...”’). 

¢ Plato, Timaeus 87 A 5-B 3. 

ἃ This is the epitomizer’s mistake for ‘‘ the soul of the 
universe ’’ (1023 p supra). 

¢ I translate as if the correct λέγειν stood here (see 1023 & 
supra), for with λέγῃ, which the epitomizer certainly wrote, 
it is impossible to construe the sentence at all. 


— ------ ----- -- 


10 μ88. : ὅτῳ τ᾽ ἂν -1023 Ε supra. 

1 ὡς -Beorr. ; τις -all other MSS., Aldine. 

12 # καὶ ὅτου -B°T-; 7 καὶ ὅτω -all other mss. (w over 
erasure in a), Aldine. 


355 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


/ \ 
(1031) πρὸς ὃ τι τε μάλιστα καὶ ὅπῃ Kal ὅπως συμβαίνει 
καὶ τὰ γιγνόμενα πρὸς ἕκαστον ἕκαστα εἶναι καὶ 





/ 3 / Ὁ“ Ἁ »“". 
πάσχειν. ἐν τούτοις ἅμα καὶ τῶν δέκα κατηγο- 
n , e \ 3) ~ A 3 A 
ριῶν ποιούμενος ὑπογραφὴν ἔτι μᾶλλον τοῖς ἐφεξῆς 
aA / δ 
διασαφεῖ. “ιἷ λόγος ᾿᾿ γάρ φησιν “᾿ ἀληθὴς ὅταν μὲν 
ΚΠ ΔΝ, ὁ \ ͵ 2 1 oe "Ξ , t 
D περὶ τὸ αἰσθητὸν γένηται καὶ ὁ τοῦ θατέρου κύκλος 
) \ 3 3 ἊΝ 2 la >] ~ \ \ 
ὀρθὸς" ἰὼν εἰς πᾶσαν αὐτοῦ τὴν ψυχὴν διαγ- 
/ / \ ὔ , / 4 
γείλῃ, δόξαι καὶ πίστεις γίγνονται βέβαιοι καὶ 
3 A ω 8 > 7 \4 4 \ > 
ἀληθεῖς: ὅταν δ᾽ αὖ πάλιν περὶ τὸ λογιστικὸν ἢ 
καὶ ὁ τοῦ ταὐτοῦ κύκλος εὔτροχος ὧν αὐτὰ μηνύσῃ, 
ἐπιστήμη ἐξ ἀνάγκης ἀποτελεῖται" τούτω δ᾽ ἐν ᾧ 
τῶν ὄντων ἐγγίγνεσθον, ἐάν ποτέ τις αὐτὸ ἄλλο 
πλὴν ψυχὴν προσείπῃ, πᾶν μᾶλλον ἢ τὸ ἀληθὲς 
Setar ’ a 5 oe \ \ 3 ι 
ἐρεῖ. πόθεν οὖν ἔσχεν" ἡ ψυχὴ τὴν ἀντιληπτικὴν 
τοῦ αἰσθητοῦ καὶ δοξαστικὴν ταύτην κίνησιν, ἐτέ- 
“ “ A > 
ραν τῆς νοητῆς" ἐκείνης καὶ τελευτώσης εἰς ἐπι- 
> aA A ’ ~ 
στήμην, ἔργον εἰπεῖν μὴ θεμένους βεβαίως ὅτι viv 
“- A A 
οὐχ ἁπλῶς ψυχὴν ἀλλὰ κόσμου ψυχὴν συνίστησιν 
1 καὶ -MSS.3 κατὰ -B°T- in margin; see 1023 © supra: 
κατὰ τὰ γιγνόμενα (καταγινόμενα -MSS.). 
2 γένοιτο -ἰ (Urb. 100), Laurent. 80, 53 γίγνηται -1023 Ἐ 
supra. | 
8: ὀρθῶς -a! ? (os over erasure), Vat. Reg. 80; see root. 
in 1023 © supra. 
4 mss., Aldine; δ᾽ αὖ περὶ (without πάλιν) -1023 ¥ supra 
and Timaeus 37 c 1. 
5 ἔσχεν -omitted by Laurent. C. 5. 180, Marc. Append. 


IV, 1 (cf. Hubert-Drexler, Moralia vi/1, p. xviit). 
6 mss., Aldine; νοητικῆς -Wyttenbach from 1023 Fr supra. 











¢ From this point on the construction of the original is 
radically altered by the erroneous καὶ τὰ γιγνόμενα which 


356 








EPITOME OF GEN. OF SOUL, 1031 


regard to whatever it is so precisely the respect and 
context and manner in which? even the things that 
come to be happen to be or to have as attribute 
either of these in relation te each. As in these 
words he is simultaneously giving an outline of the 
ten categories too, in those that follow he states the 
case more clearly still, for he says®: “ Whenever 
true discourse is concerning itself about the per- 
ceptible and the circle of difference running aright 
conveys the message through all its soul, there arise 
opinions and beliefs steadfast and true ; but, when- 
ever on the other hand again it is concerned about 
the rational and the circle of sameness running 
smoothly gives the information, knowledge is of 
necessity produced; and, if anyone ever calls by 
another name than soul that one of existing things in 
which these two come to be, he will be speaking 
anything but the truth.’’ Whence, then, did the 
soul get this motion that can apprehend what is 
perceptible and form opinions of it, a motion different 
from that which is intelligible ὁ and issues in know- 
ledge? It is difficult to say without steadfastly 
maintaining that in the present passage ὦ he is con- 
structing not soul in the absolute sense but the soul 


the epitomizer wrote instead of κατὰ τὰ γιγνόμενα (see 
1023 © supra). On the other hand, the ms. that he excerpted 
must have contained the correct ἕκαστα (cf. Timaeus 37 B 2) 
that is lacking in all our mss. of the treatise. 

> Timaeus 37 B 3—c 5. 

¢ The treatise here has “ intellective’ (1023 r supra: 
vontixys), but the epitomizer probably wrote νοητῆς. 

¢ This refers to neither of the two passages just mentioned 
but to Timaeus 35 a 1-8 4, which is quoted at the beginning 
of the treatise (1012 B-c supra) but has not been mentioned 
in the Epitome at all. 


357 


(1081) 


iD 


1032 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


ἐξ ὑποκειμένης" THs TE κρείττονος οὐσίας καὶ ἀμε- 
a “a 

ρίστου καὶ τῆς χείρονος, ἣν περὶ" τὰ σώματα 
μεριστὴν κέκληκεν, οὐχ ἑτέραν οὖσαν ἢ τὴν δοξα- 
στικὴν καὶ φανταστικὴν καὶ συμπαθῆ" τῶν αἰσθη- 
τῶν' κίνησιν, οὐ γενομένην ἀλλὰ ὑφεστῶσαν. ἀΐδιον 
ὥσπερ ἡ ἑτέρα. τὸ γὰρ νοερὸν ἡ φύσις" ἔχουσα 
καὶ τὸ δοξαστικὸν εἶχεν ἀλλ᾽ ἐκεῖνο μὲν ἀκίνητον 
καὶ ἀπαθὲς καὶ περὶ τὴν ἀεὶ “μένουσαν ἱδρυμένον 
οὐσίαν τοῦτο δὲ μεριστὸν καὶ πλανητόν, ἅτε δὴ 
φερομένης καὶ σκεδαννυμένης ἐφαπτόμενον ὕλης. 
οὔτε γὰρ τὸ αἰσθητὸν εἰλήχει τάξεως ἀλλ᾽ ἦν ἄμορ- 
gov καὶ ἀόριστον, ἢ τε περὶ τοῦτο τεταγμένη δύνα- 
μες οὔτε δόξας ᾿ἐνάρθρους οὔτε κινήσεις ἁπάσας 
ἔχουσα" τεταγμένας ἀλλὰ τὰς πολλὰς ἐνυπνιώδεις 
καὶ παραφόρους καὶ ταραττούσας τὸ σωματοειδές, 
ὅσα μὴ κατὰ τύχην τῷ βελτίονι περιέπιπτεν" ἐν 
μέσῳ γὰρ ἦν ἀμφοῖν καὶ πρὸς ἀμφότερα συμπαθῆ 
καὶ συγγενῆ φύσιν εἶχε, τῷ μὲν ᾿αἰσθητικῷ τῆς 
ὕλης ἀντεχομένη τῷ δὲ κριτικῷ τῶν νοητῶν. 

5. Οὕτω δέ πως" καὶ [ἰλάτων" διασαφεῖ τοῖς 
5: τῷ {( a 2) , «( Ἁ “a 2 A 7 
ὀνόμασιν" “ οὗτος ᾿᾿ γάρ φησι “ παρὰ τῆς ἐμῆς ψή- 

1 55,9, Aldine ; ὑποκειμένων -1094. 4 supra. 
παρὰ -"}. 3 συμπλοκὴ -Vat. Keg. 80. 
MSS., Aldine ; : τῷ αἰσθητῷ -1024 a supra. 
νοερὸν ὥσπερ ἡ φύσις -B, n. 

δ᾽ arss., Aldine; εἶχε -W yttenbach ἔγοι 1024 Bw supra (B, 
" ον margin}). 

7 αἰσθητῶ -B. 


8 πως —— by B. 
® msS.; αὐτὸς -1024 B supra. 


a ὦ NS 


¢ Misled by τῆς... οὐσίας, which follows immediately, 
the epitomizer may have misread an abbreviation of the final 
syllable of ὑποκειμένων in the original (1024 4 supra). Both 
entities, of course, were already available to the artificer. 


358 











EPITOME OF GEN. OF SOUL, 1031-1032 


of the universe out of being that is already available, 
the superior, that is to say indivisible, and the 
inferior, which he has called divisible in the case of 
bodies, this latter being none other than the opinion- 
ative and imaginative motion sensitive of the per- 
ceptibles,? not brought into being but having sub- 
sisted everlastingly just like the former. For nature 
possessing intellectuality possessed the opinionative 
faculty also, the former, however, immobile and 
impassive and settled about the being that always 
remains fixed but the latter divisible and erratic 
inasmuch as it was in contact with matter which was 
in motion and dispersion. The fact is that the per- 
ceptible had not got any portion of order but was 
amorphous and indefinite ; and the faculty stationed 
about this was one having ὁ neither articulate opinions 
nor motions that were all orderly, but most of them 
were dreamlike and deranged and were disturbing 
corporeality save in so far as it would by chance en- 
counter that which is the better, for it was inter- 
mediate between the two and had a nature sensitive 
and akin to both, with its perceptivity laying hold on 
matter and with its discernment on the intelligibles. 

5. In terms that go something like this Plato ὦ too 
states the case clearly, for he says¢: “ Let this be 

> This is the epitomizer’s error for “ὁ sensitive to what is 
perceptible ”’ in the original. 

¢ I attempt in this way to render ἔχουσα, a mistake for 
εἶχε that was probably in the epitomizer’s original, for it is 
common to all the mss. here and most of those of the treatise 
(see 1024 B supra). 

4 Here the epitomizer not unintelligently substituted the 
name of Plato for “‘ he... himself ”’ of his original. 

* Timaeus 52 Ὁ 2-4. 

359 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


\ > 

(1032) φου λογισθεὶς ἐν κεφαλαίῳ δεδόσθω λόγος, dv te! 
\ , ‘4 , , A \ \ 
καὶ χώραν καὶ γένεσιν εἶναι τρία τριχῇ καὶ πρὶν 
9 \ / ᾽} νῷ , \ aoe 
οὐρανὸν γενέσθαι.᾽᾽ Kai’ χώραν τε yap καλεῖ τὴν 
ὕλην ὥσπερ ἕδραν ἔστιν ὅτε καὶ ὑποδοχήν," ὃν δὲ τὸ 
νοητόν, γένεσιν δὲ τοῦ κόσμου μήπω γεγονότος 

? / ” Ἅ Ἁ > a \ 4 
οὐδεμίαν ἄλλην ἢ τὴν ἐν μεταβολαῖς Kai κινήσεσιν 
οὐσίαν, τοῦ τυποῦντος καὶ τοῦ τυπουμένου μεταξὺ 
7 “-- 4 3 ~ \ > A 3 
τεταγμένην, διαδιδοῦσαν" ἐνταῦθα τὰς ἐκεῖθεν εἰ- 
κόνας. διά τε δὴ ταῦτα μεριστὴ προσηγορεύθη καὶ 
Β ὅτι τῷ αἰσθητῷ τὸ αἰσθανόμενον καὶ τῷ φανταστῷ 

A 4 3 / ᾿ς 4 
τὸ φανταζόμενον ἀνάγκη συνδιανέμεσθαι καὶ συμ- 
, ¢ \ > \5 , As oe 
παρήκειν: ἡ yap αἰσθητικὴ" κίνησις, ἰδία ψυχῆς 
οὖσα, κινεῖται πρὸς τὸ αἰσθητὸν ἐκτός" ὁ δὲ νοῦς 

2 A \ 2y>? ες As ; S vl eee 
αὐτὸς μὲν ἐφ᾽ ἑαυτοῦ" μόνιμος ἦν καὶ ἀκίνητος, 
ἐγγενόμενος δὲ τῇ ψυχῇ καὶ κρατήσας εἰς ἑαυτὸν 
ἐπιστρέφει καὶ συμπεραίνει τὴν ἐγκύκλιον φορὰν 
περὶ τὸ μένζον)᾽ ἀεὶ μάλιστα" ψαύουσαν τοῦ ὄντος. 
“διὸ καὶ δυσανάκρατος ἡ κοινωνία γέγονεν αὐτῶν, 
τῶν ἀμερίστων᾽" τὸ μεριστὸν καὶ τῶν μηδαμῇ κινη- 


1 ὅν τε -ἘΠ in margin, Basiliensis; ὄντος -all other mss. 
(two dots under τος -B), Aldine. 

2 καὶ -mss., Aldine ; omitted by Basiliensis and lacking in 
1024 c supra. 

3 ὑποδοχεῖν -y- 

4 διαδοῦσαν -y (So also r in 1024 c supra). 

5 αἰσθητὴ -B. 

8 ἀφ᾽ ἑαυτοῦ -Laurent. C. S. 180, Marc. Append. IV, 1 (¢/. 
Hubert-Drexler, Moralia vi/1, p. xvii [so also f, m, r, Escor. 
72 in 1024 c supra}). 


360 











EPITOME OF GEN. OF SOUL, 1032 


the account rendered in summation as reckoned 
from my calculation, that real existence and space 
and becoming were three and distinct even before 
heaven came to be.”’ Now, it is matter that he also 
calls space, as he sometimes calls it abode and 
receptacle, and the intelligible that he calls real 
existence ; and what he calls becoming, the universe 
not yet having come to be, is nothing other than that 
being involved in changes and motions which, ranged 
between what makes impressions and what receives 
them, disperses in this world the semblances from 
that world yonder. For this very reason it was called 
divisible and also because it is necessary for that 
which is perceiving and that which is forming mental 
images to be divided in correspondence with what is 
perceptible and with what is imaginable and to be 
coextensive with them, for the motion of sense-per- 
ception, which is the soul’s own, moves towards what 
is perceptible without but the intelligence, while it 
was abiding and immobile all by itself, upon having 
got into the soul and taken control makes her turn 
around to him and with her accomplishes about that 
which always remains fixed? the circular motion most 
closely in contact with real existence. This is also 
why the union of them proved to be a difficult fusion, 
mixing the divisibility of the indivisibles and the 

¢ It is probable that the epitomizer faithfully copied τὸ 


μὲν ἀεὶ from his original; but, if so, he could not have 
construed the phrase at all. 





7 Wyttenbach from 1024 p supra; τὸ μὲν -Mss. (50 u in 
1024 p supra, where f omits μένον altogether). 
8 μάλιστα -omitted by B. 


9. MSS.3; τῷ ἀμερίστῳ -Stephanus from 1024 ἢ supra. 


361 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 





(1032) τῶν' τὸ πάντῃ φορητὸν μιγνύουσα καὶ καταβια- 
ζομένη" θάτερον εἰς ταὐτὸν" συνελθεῖν. ἦν δὲ τὸ 
4 θάτερον οὐ κίνησις, ὥσπερ οὐδὲ ταὐτὸν στάσις, 
ἀλλ᾽ ἀρχὴ διαφορᾶς καὶ ἀνομοιότητος. ἑκάτερον 
γὰρ ἀπὸ τῆς ἑτέρας ἀρχῆς κάτεισι, τὸ μὲν ταὐτὸν 
ἀπὸ τοῦ ἑνὸς τὸ δὲ θάτερον ἀπὸ τῆς δυάδος" καὶ 
μέμικται πρῶτον ἐνταῦθα περὶ τὴν ψυχήν, ἀριθ- 
μοῖς καὶ "λόγοις συνδεθέντα καὶ μεσότησιν ἐναρμο- 
νίοις, καὶ ποιεῖ θάτερον μὲν ἐγγενόμενον τῷ ταὐτῷ" 
διαφορὰν τὸ δὲ ταὐτὸν ἐν τῷ ἑτέρῳ τάξιν, ὡς δῆλόν 
ἐστιν ἐν ταῖς πρώταις τῆς ψυχῆς δυνάμεσιν' εἰσὶ 
δὲ αὗται τὸ κριτικὸν καὶ τὸ κινητικόν. ἡ μὲν οὖν 
κίνησις εὐθὺς ἐπιδείκνυται περὶ τὸν οὐρανὸν ἐν μὲν 
τῇ ταὐτότητι τὴν ἑτερότητα τῇ περιφορᾷ τῶν ἀ- 
D πλανῶν ἐν δὲ τῇ ἑτερότητι τὴν ταὐτότητα τῇ τάξει 
τῶν πλανήτων" ἐπικρατεῖ γὰρ ἐν ἐκείνοις τὸ ταὐ- 
τὸν ἐν δὲ τοῖς περὶ γῆν τοὐναντίον. ἡ δὲ κρίσις 
ἀρχὰς μὲν ἔχει δύο, τόν τε νοῦν ἀπὸ τοῦ ταὐτοῦ 
πρὸς τὰ καθόλου καὶ τὴν αἴσθησιν ἀπὸ τοῦ ἑτέρου 
πρὸς τὰ καθ᾽ ἕκαστα. μέμικται δὲ λόγος ἐξ ἀμ- 
φοῖν, νόησις ἐν τοῖς νοητοῖς καὶ δόξα γινόμενος ἐν 
τοῖς αἰσθητοῖς ὀργάνοις τε μεταξὺ φαντασίαις τε 
καὶ μνήμαις χρώμενος, ὧν τὰ μὲν ἐν τῷ ταὐτῷ" 
τὸ ἕτερον τὰ δ᾽ ἐν τῷ ἑτέρῳ ποιεῖ τὸ ταὐτόν. ἔστι 
γὰρ ἡ μὲν νόησις κίνησις τοῦ κινοῦντος περὶ τὸ 
1 mss. (τὸ . .. κινητὸν -t [Urb. 100], Laurent. 80, 5) ; 


μηδαμῇ κινητῷ -Stephanus from 1024 pv supra (where r ai 
κινητὸν). 2 καταβιαζομένου -α (3). 

8 ταυτὸ -B, Laurent. C. S. 180. 

4 EF; τῷ αὐτῷ -all other mss. 

5 πλανων (with 47 superscript over vw) -a!; πλανήτων -all 

other mss. 

6 ἘΠ superscript over αὐτῶ : αὐτὸ -Vat. Reg. 80; αὐτῶ 
-all other mss. 


362 











EPITOME OF GEN. OF SOUL, 1032 


thorough transience of the utterly immobile* and 
constraining difference to unite with sameness. 
Difference is not motion, however, as sameness is not 
rest either, but the principle of differentiation and 
dissimilitude. In fact, each of the two derives from 
another of two principles, sameness from the one and 
difference from the dyad ; and it is first here in the 
soul that they have been commingled, bound to- 
gether by numbers and ratios and harmonious means, 
and that difference come to be in sameness produces 
differentiation but sameness in difference order, as is 
clear in the case of the soul’s primary faculties. 
These are the faculties of discernment and motivity. 
Now, directly in the heaven motion exhibits diversity 
in identity by the revolution of the fixed stars and 
identity in diversity by the order of the planets, for 
in the former sameness predominates but its opposite 
in the things about the earth. Discernment, how- 
ever, has two principles, intelligence proceeding 
from sameness to universals and sense-perception 
from difference to particulars ; and reason is a blend 
of both, becoming intellection in the case of the 
intelligibles and opinion in the case of the per- 
ceptibles and employing between them mental 
images and memories as instruments, of which the 
former are produced by difference in sameness and 
the latter by sameness in difference. For intellection 
is motion of the mover ® about what remains fixed, 

α The nonsense of this clause is the result of the epito- 
mnizer’s reading as genitive plurals the dative singulars of 
1024 p supra, a mistake that he made in 1031 Ἑ supra also. 


Ὁ This is the epitomizer’s own mistake for ‘ motion of 
what is cognizing ᾿᾿ (1024 ¥ supra). 


7 κινοῦντος -MSS.; νοοῦντος -Leonicus from 1024 F supra. 


363 


PLUTARCH’S MORALIA 


(1032) μένον, ἡ δὲ δόξα μονὴ τοῦ αἰσθανομένου περὶ τὸ 
κινούμενον" φαντασίαν δὲ συμπλοκὴν δόξης πρὸς 
E αἴσθησιν οὖσαν ἵστησιν ἐν μνήμῃ τὸ ταὐτὸν τὸ δὲ 
θάτερον κινεῖ πάλιν ἐν διαφορᾷ τοῦ πρόσθεν καὶ 
νῦν, ἑτερότητος ἅμα καὶ “ταὐτότητος ἐφαπτόμενον. 
6. Δεῖ δὲ τὴν περὶ τὸ σῶμα τοῦ κόσμου γενο- 
μένην. σύνταξιν' εἰκόνα λαβεῖν τῆς ἀναλογίας ἐν ἧ 
διηρμόσατο τὴν' ψυχήν. ἐκεῖ μὲν γὰρ ἦν ἄκρα τὸ 
πῦρ καὶ ἡ γῆ, χαλεπὴν πρὸς ἄλληλα κραθῆναι 
φύσιν ἔχοντα μᾶλλον δὲ ὅλως ἄκρατον καὶ ἀσύ- 
στατον' ὅθεν ἐν μέσῳ θέμενος αὐτῶν τὸν “μὲν ἀέρα 
πρὸ τοῦ πυρὸς τὸ δὲ ὕδωρ πρὸ τῆς γῆς, ταῦτα 
πρῶτον ἀλλήλοις ἐκέρασεν εἶτα διὰ τούτων ἐκεῖνα 
πρός τε ταῦτα καὶ ἀλληλα συνέμιξε καὶ συνήρμο- 
Ε σεν. ἐνταῦθα δὲ πάλιν τὸ ταὐτὸν καὶ τὸ θάτερον, 
ἐναντίας δυνάμεις καὶ ἀκρότητας ἀντιπάλους, συν- 
ἤγαγεν οὐ διὰ αὑτῶν," ἀλλ᾽ οὐσίας ἑτέρας, μεταξύ, 
τὴν μὲν ἀμέριστον πρὸ" τοῦ ταὐτοῦ πρὸ" δὲ τοῦ 
θατέρου τὴν μεριστήν, ἔστιν ἧ προσήκουσαν ἑκα- 
τέραν ἑκατέρᾳ τάξας εἶτα μιχθείσαις ἐκείναις ἐπ- 
εγκεραννύμενος, οὕτως τὸ πᾶν συνύφηνε τῆς ψυχῆς 
εἶδος, ὡς ἦν ἀνυστόν, ἐκ διαφόρων ὅμοιον ἔκ τε 
πολλῶν Ev" ἀπεργασάμενος .ὃ 


tomas. 4 σύντηξιν -Bernardakis from 1025 a supra. 
2 τὴν “MSS. 3 omitted in 1025 a supra. 
3 MSS.; καὶ πρὸς ἄλληλα -1025 A-B supra. 
4. αὐτῶν “as Laurent. C. S. 180, Aldine. 
. πρὸς -Vat. Reg. oy 
8 πρὸς -Vat. Reg. 8 
7 év-n3 ἕνα - -Laurent. (.».5..180ς ited by Aldine. 
8 MSS. ; ᾿ἀπειργασμένος - -1025 B supra (ἀπειργασάμενος -f). 


~ @ The erroneous ἐφαπτόμενον (in 1025 a supra emended 
to ἐφαπτομένην), which without doubt was in the Ms. ex- 
cerpted by the epitomizer as it is in all the extant mss. of the 


364 





EPITOME OF GEN. OF SOUL, 1032 


and opinion fixity of what is perceiving about what 
is in motion; but mental imagining, which is a 
combination of opinion with sense-perception, is 
brought to a stop in memory by sameness and by 
difference again set moving in the distinction of past 
and present, being in contact with® diversity and 
identity at once. 

6. The construction® that was carried out in the 
case of the body of the universe must be taken as a 
likeness of the proportion with which he regulated 
the soul. In the former case, because there were 
extremes, fire and earth, of a nature difficult to 
blend together or rather utterly immiscible and 
incohesive, he accordingly put between them air in 
front of the fire and water in front of the earth and 
blended these with each other first and then by 
means of these commingled and conjoined those 
extremes with them and each other. And in the 
latter case again he united sameness and difference, 
contrary forces and antagonistic extremes, not just 
by themselves ; but by first interposing other beings, 
the indivisible in front of sameness and in front of 
difference the divisible, as each of the one pair is in 
a way akin to one of the other, and by then making 
an additional blend with those between after they 
had been commingled he thus fabricated the whole 
structure of the soul, from what were various making 
it as nearly uniform and from what were many as 
nearly single as was feasible. 


treatise, could agree only with τὸ θάτερον (“* difference’) and 
taken with this produces nonsense. 

» This mistake for “fusion” (σύντηξιν), which occurs in 
one ms. of the treatise also, may have been in the ms. ex- 
cerpted by the epitomizer. 


365 
















eT A Sai ἀὐγέδι 
a κι" ΟΣ ΤΥ ΟΣ τ te ‘ 
ἂν : ty oe ee κι ys ἢ 


+ 
συ. 





Lene 


ἍΕῚ 


ei 







yan A 
ile as, τρις Τῶν 
as itt 
areas goa 
fou. Ἔ Ὁ Mt 
oh. ων: ὦ 


γα. αν. ; i 
ἢ 

































nd ye ee Se > 
- ὺ ᾿ a , 
| my ὡ ; ἢ 
Sy 
fe “Ὡς δ ary 
τω ᾿ 
αὶ ὩΣ de A ὮΝ 
| ἡ de Pe. iy 
᾿ + ae Se τ" Th 
AE χὶ . re. 
οἱ ΔῊΝ hing. ΚΎΩΝ 
᾿ ; ν 
ee ; 
vic hess 
τ a va 7 
"τὺ Le 
Ade NPGS) 
a a 
1 a 
᾿ 
J A 
Af 
a 
| “me 
¥ ᾽ 
if a 
ἢ ὦ 
if a 
| } ἢ vi ; PR 'e 
Ἷ Ἢ oe 
᾿ | *» “a eae . 7. AD | yl ἡ νν 
ia : Ae TL Sit CPT νλῖναι 
ΠῚ ω i ha), 
4 
4 
. 
| o 
τῳ, ἵ 
: buy 
q 
Suit 











pre - ce i ae; WE ἢ oa nek 


aay. pu Pas! 
ἣν on oe ΑΝ 
ae 










᾿ 
t's 


" FU cs 
ἐφ ων ὧν Pill A a Wiss 


’ wy 7 
᾿ Π 
via’ ane a alts ἐλ ep " 2¢ 
Pa) wane ᾿ 
; ! yy sa 
Π ἊΝ Ρ ᾿ aay 3 ᾿ 
Fi Ἢ : “» 
a iy Ω ‘ py 79s ga i 5 
fi i ΄ A; 4 rte | 
ey 
= ¥ f 7 
. ᾿ ἐ 
i, 
᾿ ἱ 


A, 
Ὁ 
f 
i Prd ! 
νὼ A 
Ἶ͵ ν. 
-- 
- in 
1 
- i 
- ᾿ 
' 
2 } /; 
4 
Ἧ " - 
= 
' 
ἢ - 
9 ἢ 
‘ ak 
y - 
- | 
' ψ 
' j 4 
[ΠῚ I 
᾿ ᾿ Ay is ry 
fs 
+ 
ἌΝ 
Lae 














inlet iN ΒΝ [ΩΣ ει ἢ ἡ Va Wn ial es, hy 
᾿ ihe a eat ΠΝ save ἫΝ Fig hay’) 
i ἕ ΝῊ τ ’ 








+) \ 
᾿ τ 7 ey Pan, f fi Ape 

νι, 
i ς ἫΝ ᾿ Wet ‘a “ τς ἱ 
iM Bi SOC Het Ων 
"ἢ πο ἢ 
il 7 Me ho an tek a he 
ane 9 Ύ f 

Mt 7 he her . “asi 
iil ) Τὴ J ἦν 
᾿ - ; J g a ‘ P [ 
i : Lu, 

ii 

in| ! 

Ἢ = ee 
A , afte 

ts i 7 } 

iH 

ie 

|| 

᾿ r¥ 
i i 

| 

1h) 

] ‘ ᾿ 

| ΄- 

Hil! 

}}} 
i) 
iy 

\\ 

I 

H 

᾿ ; του: 

Ι 

Hi] 

| ᾿ y 
1h} 

ἣ ( 

Ht my A) i \ 

| 

i 

| 

] ‘ 

| “ Ν 

Ai, ® 

᾿ 

| 
bef { 

ey 

"ἢ 

| 2 

| | ) 

|; 

| 

a 


The Loeb Classical Library is the only existing 
series of books which, through original text 
and English translation, gives access to all that 
is important in Greek and Latin literature. A 
list of titles is available from Harvard Univer- 
sity Press and at www.hup.harvard.edu/loeb. 


LOEB CLASSICAL LIBRARY isa registered trademark of the 
President and Fellows of Harvard College. 








ISBN-13: 
ISBN-10: 


| 
4°?80b 74 


978-O-b?4-99470-b 
O-674-99470-1 


40000 





594706